Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T15:05:23.547Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Agency, Akrasia, and the Normative Environment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 September 2019

GREGORY ANTILL*
Affiliation:
CLAREMONT MCKENNA COLLEGE

Abstract

Just as the existence of practical akrasia has been treated as important evidence for the existence of our practical agency, the alleged absence of epistemic akrasia—cases in which a believer believes some proposition contrary to her considered judgments about what she has most reason to believe—has recently been marshaled as grounds for skepticism about the existence of similar forms of epistemic agency. In this paper, I defend the existence of epistemic agency against such objections. Rather than argue against the impossibility of epistemic akrasia, I argue that the impossibility of epistemic akrasia is actually compatible with the existence of epistemic agency. The crucial mistake, I argue, is that skeptics about epistemic agency are failing to distinguish carefully between differences in the structure of believing and acting and differences in the structure of normative reasons to believe and normative reasons to act. I show that once these ‘environmental’ differences are properly distinguished, we can see that absence of epistemic akrasia provides no reason to doubt that practical and epistemic agency are on a par with one another.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Earlier versions of this material were presented to audiences at Pomona College, Northwestern University, the University of Colorado Boulder, Sacramento State University, the St. Louis Conference on Reasons and Rationality, and the Central Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association. I am grateful to everyone who commented on those occasions, in particular to Alfred Mele, Juan Comesaña, Abigail Bruxvoort-Wilson, John Phillips, Jonathan Way, Grant Rozeboom, Sarah Stroud, and Peter Railton. The material has also benefitted enormously from written commentary from and conversation with Pamela Hieronymi, Dion Scott-Kakures, Andrew Hsu, Tyler Burge, Stephen White, Andrew Jewell, Amy Floweree, and Baron Reed.

References

Adler, Jonathan. (2002) ‘Akratic Believing?Philosophical Studies, 110, 127.Google Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1959) Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Antill, G. E. (2018) ‘Epistemic Freedom Revisited’. Synthese. https://doi-org.ccl.idm.oclc.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1735-6.Google Scholar
Antill, G. E. (2019) ‘Evidence and Self-Fulfilling Belief’. American Philosophical Quarterly, 56.Google Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy. (2000) ‘On Acting Rationally Against One's Best Judgment’. Ethics, 110, 488513.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. (1969) ‘How Is Weakness of the Will Possible?’ In Feinberg, Joel (ed.), Moral Concepts (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 93113.Google Scholar
Flowerree, Amy. (2017) ‘Agency of Belief and Intention’. Synthese, 194, 2763–84.Google Scholar
Heil, John. (1984) ‘Doxastic Incontinence’. Mind, 93, 5670.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, Pamela. (2009) ‘The Will as Reason’. Philosophical Perspectives, 23, 201–20.Google Scholar
Hurley, Susan. (1993) Natural Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. (1996) The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. (1997) ‘Finkish Dispositions’. Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 143–58.Google Scholar
Luthra, Yannig, and Borgoni, Christina. (2017) ‘Epistemic Akrasia and the Fallibility of Critical Reasoning’. Philosophical Studies, 174, 877–86.Google Scholar
Moran, Richard. (2001) Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Owens, David. (2017) ‘Epistemic Akrasia’. In Normativity and Control (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3751.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip, and Smith, Michael. (1996) ‘Freedom in Belief and Desire’. Journal of Philosophy, 93, 429–49.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. (1973) ‘Meaning and Reference’. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 699711.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. (2001) Engaging Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. (2007) ‘Reasons: Practical and Adaptive’. SSRN eLibrary.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998) What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Mark Andrew. (2007) Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Setiya, Kieran. (2013) ‘Epistemic Agency: Some Doubts’. Philosophical Issues, 23, 179–98.Google Scholar
Stroud, Sarah, and Tappolet, Christine. (2003) ‘Introduction’. In Stroud, Sarah and Tappolet, Christine (eds.), Weakness of Will and Practical Irrationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press), 812.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay. (2001) ‘Normativity, Commitment, and Instrumental Reason’. Philosophers' Imprint, 1, 126.Google Scholar