Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T19:05:49.264Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Thought Experimental Method: Avicenna's Flying Man Argument

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 October 2018

PETER ADAMSON
Affiliation:
LMU [email protected]@lrz.uni-muenchen.de
FEDOR BENEVICH
Affiliation:
LMU [email protected]@lrz.uni-muenchen.de

Abstract

No argument from the Arabic philosophical tradition has received more scholarly attention than Avicenna's ‘flying man’ thought experiment, in which a human is created out of thin air and is able to grasp his existence without grasping that he has a body. This paper offers a new interpretation of the version of this thought experiment found at the end of the first chapter of Avicenna's treatment of soul in the Healing. We argue that it needs to be understood in light of an epistemological theory set out elsewhere by Avicenna, which allows that all the constitutive properties of an essence will be clear to someone who understands and considers that essence. On our reading, this theory is put to work in the ‘flying man’: because the flying man would grasp that his own essence has existence without grasping that he has a body, connection to body cannot be constitutive of the essence.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

We are grateful for helpful suggestions from Salimeh Maghsoudlou, Helen Beebee, and Miranda Fricker as well as participants in a seminar on this paper at the University of Toronto. We are thankful to Dag N. Hasse and all other members of the Arabic reading group held at Würzburg and Munich, where we first started exploring the ideas that led to this paper. Finally we gladly acknowledge the DFG for support of our work under the aegis of the project ‘The Heirs of Avicenna: Philosophy in the Islamic East, 12th–13th Centuries’.

This article is the second in a special series of commissioned articles on non-Western philosophies. The first article ‘Marxism and Buddhism: Not Such Strange Bedfellows', by Graham Priest, appeared in Volume 4, Issue 1, pp. 2–13.

References

Adamson, Peter. (2004) ‘Correcting Plotinus: Soul's Relationship to Body in Avicenna's Commentary on the Theology of Aristotle’. In Adamson, P., Baltussen, H., and Stone, M. W. F. (eds.), Philosophy, Science and Exegesis in Greek, Arabic and Latin Commentaries. (London: Institute for Classical Studies), 2: 5975.Google Scholar
Alpina, Tomaso. (2016) ‘Subject, Definition, Activity: The Epistemological Status of the Science of the Soul in Avicenna's Kitāb al-nafs’. PhD diss., Scuola Normale Superiore, Pisa.Google Scholar
Avicenna. (1952) ‘Introduction’. In Qanawatī, Jurj Sh., al-Ḥudayrī, Maḥmūd M., and al-Ahwānī, Aḥmad F. (eds.), al-Shifāʾ, al-Manṭiq, al-Madkhal. Cairo: al-Maṭbaʿa al-amīriyya.Google Scholar
Avicenna. (1959) ‘On the Soul’. In Rahman, Fazlur (ed.), Avicenna's De Anima: Being the Psychological Part of Kitāb al-Shifāʾ. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Avicenna. (1985) ‘Salvation’. In Dānishpazhūh, M. (ed.), al-Najāt min al-gharq fī baḥr al-dalālāt. Tehran: Dānishgāh-I Tehrān.Google Scholar
Avicenna. (2008) ‘Pointers and Reminders’. In al-Zāriʿī, M. (ed.), al-Ishārāt wa-l-tanbīhāt. Tehran: Bustān-i kitāb.Google Scholar
Avicenna. (2014) Commentaire sur le livre Lambda de la Métaphysique d'Aristote. Edited and translated by Sebti, M., Geoffrey, M., and Janssens, J.. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Benevich, Fedor. (2017) ‘Fire and Heat: Yaḥyā b. ʿAdī and Avicenna on the Essentiality of Being Substance or Accident’. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, 27, 237–67.Google Scholar
Bertolacci, Amos. (2006) The Reception of Aristotle's Metaphysics in Avicenna's Kitāb al-Shifāʾ: A Milestone of Western Metaphysical Thought. Leiden-Boston: Brill.Google Scholar
Black, Deborah L. (2008) ‘Avicenna on Self-Awareness and Knowing that One Knows’. In Rahman, S. et al. (eds.), The Unity of Science in the Arabic Tradition (Dordrecht: Springer), 6387.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David J. (1996) The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
D'Ancona, Cristina. (2008) ‘Degrees of Abstraction in Avicenna: How to Combine Aristotle's De anima and the Enneads’. In Knuuttila, S. and Kärkkäinen, P. (eds.), Theories of Perception in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy (Berlin: Springer), 4771.Google Scholar
Descartes, René. (1984) ‘Sixth Meditation: The existence of material things, and the real distinction between mind and body’. In Descartes, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, translated by Cottingham, J. et al. , vol. 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 5062.Google Scholar
Druart, Thérèse-Anne. (1988) ‘The Soul and Body Problem: Avicenna and Descartes’. In Druart, T.-A. (ed.), Arabic Philosophy and the West: Continuity and Interaction (Washington DC: Center for Contemporary Arab Studies, Georgetown University), 2749.Google Scholar
Hasnawi, Ahmed. (1997) ‘La conscience de soi chez Avicenne et Descartes’. In Biard, J. and Rashed, R. (eds.), Descartes et le Moyen Âge (Paris: Vrin), 283–91.Google Scholar
Hasse, Dag N. (2000) Avicenna's De Anima in the Latin West. London: Warburg Institute.Google Scholar
Hasse, Dag N. (2001) ‘Avicenna on Abstraction’. In Wisnovksy, R. (ed.), Aspects of Avicenna (Princeton: Wiener), 3972.Google Scholar
Hasse, Dag N. (2013) ‘Avicenna's Epistemological Optimism’. In Adamson, P. (ed.), Interpreting Avicenna (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 109–19.Google Scholar
Kaukua, Jari. (2015) Self-Awareness in Islamic Philosophy: Avicenna and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kukkonen, Taneli. (2014) ‘Ibn Sīnā and the Early History of Thought Experiments’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 52, 433–59.Google Scholar
Marmura, Michael E. (1986) ‘Avicenna's ‘Flying Man’ in Context’. Monist, 69, 383–95.Google Scholar
McGinnis, Jon. (2007a) ‘Logic and Science: The Role of Genus and Difference in Avicenna's Logic, Science and Natural Philosophy’. Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale, 18, 165–86.Google Scholar
McGinnis, Jon. (2007b) ‘Making Abstraction Less Abstract: The Logical, Psychological, and Metaphysical Dimensions of Avicenna's Theory of Abstraction’. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 80, 169–83.Google Scholar
Sebti, Meryem. (2000) Avicenne: L’âme humain. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.Google Scholar
Sorabji, Richard. (2004) The Philosophy of the Commentators, 200–600 AD: A Sourcebook, vol. 1, Psychology. London: Bristol Classical Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, Richard. (2006) Self: Ancient and Modern Insights about Individuality, Life, and Death. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Wisnovsky, Robert. (2003) Avicenna's Metaphysics in Context. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Zupko, Jack. (1993) ‘Nominalism Meets Individualism’. Medieval Philosophy and Theology, 3, 158–85.Google Scholar