Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T17:33:26.013Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Does Wine Have a Place in Kant's Theory of Taste?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 February 2016

RACHEL CRISTY*
Affiliation:

Abstract:

Kant claims in the third Critique that one can make about wine the merely subjective judgment that it is agreeable but never the universally valid judgment that it is beautiful. This follows from his views that judgments of beauty can be made only about the formal (spatiotemporal) features of a representation and that aromas and flavors consist of formless sensory matter. However, I argue that Kant's theory permits judgments of beauty about wine because the experience displays a temporal structure: the aromas and flavors evolve over the course of a tasting from the bouquet through the palate to the finish. An analogy with music, which Kant describes as ‘a play of sensations in time’, illuminates how wine qualifies as an object of pure judgments of taste: the ‘structure’ of a wine can be compared to harmonic structure, and its development throughout the taste can be compared to the unfolding of melody and harmonic progression.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allen, M. S., and Lacey, M. J.. (1998) ‘Methoxypyrazines of Grapes and Wines’. In Waterhouse, A. and Ebler, S. (eds.), Chemistry of Wine Flavor: American Chemical Society Symposium 714 (New York: Oxford University Press), 3138.Google Scholar
Allison, Henry E. (2001) Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, Kent. (2007) ‘Knowledge, Wine and Taste: What Good is Knowledge (in Enjoying Wine)?’ In Smith, Barry C. (ed.), Questions of Taste: The Philosophy of Wine (New York: Oxford University Press), 2140.Google Scholar
Cannon, Joseph. (2008) ‘The Intentionality of Judgments of Taste in Kant's Critique of Judgment’. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 66, 5365.Google Scholar
Charters, Steve and Pettigrew, Simone (2005) ‘Is Wine Consumption an Aesthetic Experience?’ Journal of Wine Research, 16.2, 121–36.Google Scholar
Coombs, Amy. (2008) ‘Scientia Vitis: Decanting the Science of Wine Flavor’. Chemical Heritage Magazine, 26 (Winter 2008/9). Available at: http://www.chemheritage.org/discover/media/magazine/articles/26-4-scientia-vitis.aspx?page=1.Google Scholar
Crane, Tim. (2007) ‘Wine as an Aesthetic Object’. In Smith, Barry C. (ed.), Questions of Taste: The Philosophy of Wine (New York: Oxford University Press), 141–55.Google Scholar
Francis, I. Leigh, Kassara, Stella, Noble, Ann C., and Williams, Patrick J.. (1998) ‘The Contribution of Glycoside Precursors to Cabernet Sauvignon and Merlot Aroma: Sensory and Compositional Studies’. In Waterhouse, A. and Ebler, S. (eds.), Chemistry of Wine Flavor: American Chemical Society Symposium 714 (New York: Oxford University Press), 1330.Google Scholar
Goldstein, Robin, Almenberg, Johan, Dreber, Anna, Emerson, John W., Herschkowitsch, Alexis, and Katz, Jacob. (2008) ‘Do More Expensive Wines Taste Better? Evidence from a Large Sample of Blind Tastings’. Journal of Wine Economics, 3, 19.Google Scholar
Gray, W. Blake. (2011) ‘Robert Parker's Tasting Notes’. Blog entry on The Gray Report, March 21, 2011. http://blog.wblakegray.com/2011/03/robert-parkers-tasting-notes.html.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. (1979) Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul. (1977) ‘Formalism and the Theory of Expression in Kant's Aesthetics’. Kant-Studien, 68, 4670.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. ([1781, 1787] 1998) Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Guyer, Paul and Wood, Allen W.. New York: Cambridge University Press. (Cited with page numbers from the first and second editions in A/B format.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. ([1790, 1793] 2000) Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited by Guyer, Paul, translated by Guyer, Paul and Matthews, Eric. New York: Cambridge University Press. (Cited by section number, then volume and page number of the Academy edition of Kant's collected works.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1900–) Kants gesammelte Schriften. 29 vols. Edited by the Royal Prussian (later: German) Academy of Sciences. Berlin: Georg Reimer (later: Walter de Gruyter).Google Scholar
Johnson, Mark L. (1979) ‘Kant's Unified Theory of Beauty’. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 38, 167–78.Google Scholar
Lukacs, Paul, and Thomas, Marguerite. (2010) ‘Wine With. . . Grilled Bison Steak’. Wine Review Online, July 20, 2010. Available at: http://www.winereviewonline.com/WW_Grilled_Bison_Steak.cfm.Google Scholar
McCarthy, Ed. (2012) ‘Cobb Wines: California's Greatest Pinot Noirs?’ Wine Review Online, May 22, 2012. Available at: http://www.winereviewonline.com/Ed_McCarthy_on_Cobb_Pinots.cfm.Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander. (2007) Only a Promise of Happiness: The Place of Beauty in a World of Art. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rudi Wiest Selections (cited as RWS). (2005) ‘Wine Spectator—1999 Vintage’. Available at: http://www.germanwine.net/tastingnotes/WineSpectator1999.htm.Google Scholar
Smith, Barry C., ed. (2007) Questions of Taste: The Philosophy of Wine. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles Senn. (1988) ‘Prolegomena to an Aesthetics of Wine’. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, n.s., 2, 120–39.Google Scholar
Zangwill, Nick. (1999) ‘Feasible Aesthetic Formalism’. Noûs, 33, 610–29.Google Scholar