Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-16T16:15:05.390Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THREE SURPRISING INSTANCES OF DIVIDING

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 March 2024

GABRIEL CONANT
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS THE OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY COLUMBUS, OH 43210 USA E-mail: [email protected]
ALEX KRUCKMAN*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS AND COMPUTER SCIENCE WESLEYAN UNIVERSITY MIDDLETOWN, CT 06459 USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We give three counterexamples to the folklore claim that in an arbitrary theory, if a complete type p over a set B does not divide over $C\subseteq B$, then no extension of p to a complete type over $\operatorname {acl}(B)$ divides over C. Two of our examples are also the first known theories where all sets are extension bases for nonforking, but forking and dividing differ for complete types (answering a question of Adler). One example is an $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ theory with a complete type that forks, but does not divide, over a model (answering a question of d’Elbée). Moreover, dividing independence fails to imply M-independence in this example (which refutes another folklore claim). In addition to these counterexamples, we summarize various related properties of dividing that are still true. We also address consequences for previous literature, including an earlier unpublished result about forking and dividing in free amalgamation theories, and some claims about dividing in the theory of generic $K_{m,n}$-free incidence structures.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1. Introduction

The basis for this paper is the discovery that a certain well-known property of dividing independence, which was originally stated in [Reference Adler3] and appears as folklore in a number of places, is actually false.

To elaborate, let T be a complete first-order theory with monster model $\mathbb M$ . We let denote dividing independence for (small) sets in $\mathbb M$ (see Definition 2.2). Given $C\subset \mathbb M$ , we say that has algebraic extension over C if, for any $A,B\subset \mathbb M$ , implies . We say that has algebraic extension if this holds over any $C\subset \mathbb M$ .

Remark 5.4(3) of [Reference Adler3] states that always has algebraic extension. This also appears as Exercise 1.24 $(iii)$ in Chapter 1 of Adler’s thesis [Reference Adler1] (later published as [Reference Adler3]). A solution to this exercise is given in [Reference Adler1]; however, a gap in the argument was found by the first-named author and Terry in February 2013. At that time, Adler suggested a new proof (via personal communication), which was rewritten in notes posted on the first-named author’s website. Then, in February of 2021, the second-named author found that the same gap was still present in the new proof, but hidden in a more subtle way, and subsequently discovered one of three counterexamples we will present here. Each of these examples demonstrates unique aspects of how and where algebraic extension for can fail. To help provide context for how these examples have been curated, note that does have algebraic extension over C whenever forking and dividing over C are the same for complete types (see Remark 2.11). So, for example, has algebraic extension in any simple theory. More generally, if T is $\mathrm {NTP}_2$ and C is an extension base for nonforking, then has algebraic extension over C by [Reference Chernikov and Kaplan6]. With these facts in mind, we now give an overview of our examples.

  1. (1) In Section 3.1, we show that fails algebraic extension over $\varnothing $ in $T=\mathrm {Th}({\mathbb Q},\operatorname {cyc})^{\mathrm {eq}}$ where $\operatorname {cyc}$ is the circular order on ${\mathbb Q}$ . Note that T is NIP, and that $\varnothing $ is (necessarily) not an extension base for nonforking in T.

  2. (2) In Section 3.2, we show that fails algebraic extension over a model in the $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ theory $T=(T^{\varnothing }_{f})^{\mathrm {eq}}$ , where $T^{\varnothing }_{f}$ is the model completion of the empty theory in a language with only a binary function symbol f. In this case, the failure of algebraic extension for actually arises through the failure of (see Section 2.3 for further discussion of M-independence). Thus this example also refutes the claim made in Remark 5.4(4) of [Reference Adler3]. We also show that in T, all sets are extension bases for nonforking.

  3. (3) In Section 3.3, we construct a theory, called $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ , where fails algebraic extension for the stronger reason that need not imply (see Remark 2.9 for further discussion). $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ is an $\mathrm {NSOP}_4$ theory (with $\mathrm {SOP}_3$ ) in which all sets are extension bases for nonforking. This is the original counterexample discovered by the second-named author.

In addition to refuting the erroneous claims made in [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4], these counterexamples also answer some other open questions. First, recall that if (i.e., forking and dividing coincide for complete types), then all sets are extension bases for nonforking. Question A.1 of Adler’s thesis [Reference Adler1] asks whether the converse holds. As noted above, if fails algebraic extension, then , and thus both $(2)$ and $(3)$ provide counterexamples to Adler’s question. Moreover, $(2)$ and $(3)$ appear to be the first known examples of $\mathrm {NSOP}$ theories in which . Whether in $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ theories specifically had been discussed by a number of people in the field, and was asked by d’Elbée in [Reference d’Elbée12, Question 2]. Example $(2)$ shows that need not hold in $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ theories, even over models. In fact, since the discovery of this example, two others have surfaced in previous literature from erroneous arguments relying on [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4] (see Sections 5.3 and 5.4).

We now give an outline of the paper. In Section 2 we recall various definitions, and then we spend some time discussing positive results related to [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4] that are still true. For example, algebraic extension can be viewed as one part of the more general question of preservation of algebraic closure for a ternary relation (Definition 2.5). We clarify in Proposition 2.7 what amount of preservation one can obtain for , and we show that always preserves algebraic closure. These facts are known in the folklore, but for obvious reasons we think it appropriate to provide details. Then in Section 2.3 we focus on the question of when implies , which was the main motivation for [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4]. Among other quick observations, we show in Proposition 2.18 that implies in pregeometric theories (where is especially meaningful; see Fact 2.17). We then move on to our three counterexamples summarized above, which are given in Section 3. The rest of the paper is devoted to addressing uses of [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4] in previous literature. First, in Section 4, we focus on free amalgamation theories, defined by the first-named author in [Reference Conant7]. It turns out that the theory $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ in example $(3)$ above is a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure (Corollary 4.9). Consequently, the failure of algebraic extension in $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ refutes the claim made in an earlier unpublished research note (of the authors) that in any such theory. However, the arguments from that note can be adjusted to show that forking and dividing are the same for complete types over algebraically closed sets (see Theorem 4.5). Finally, Section 5 contains brief discussion of other places where [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4] was used. For example, we amend some incorrect statements from [Reference Conant and Kruckman10] about dividing in the generic theory of $K_{m,n}$ -free incidence structures.

2. Dividing and algebraic closure

Throughout this section, we work in the setting of a complete theory T with monster model $\mathbb M$ . We allow letters $a,b,c,\ldots $ to denote tuples from $\mathbb M$ (which may be infinite), but sometimes also use vector notation $\overline {a},\overline {b},\overline {c},\ldots $ when the distinction between tuples and singletons is important.

2.1. Preliminaries

We first recall several axioms of a ternary relation on small subsets of $\mathbb M$ .

Definition 2.1.

  1. (1) (Invariance) For all $A,B,C$ , if then for all $\sigma \in \operatorname {Aut}(\mathbb M)$ .

  2. (2) (Monotonicity) For all $A,B,C$ , if then for all $A'\subseteq A$ and $B'\subseteq B$ .

  3. (3) (Base monotonicity) For all $A,B,C$ , if and $D\subseteq B$ then .

  4. (4) (Extension) For all $A,B,C$ , if and $D\supseteq B$ , then there is some $A'\equiv _{BC} A$ such that .

  5. (5) (Existence) for all A and C.

Next we recall a few special independence relations.

Definition 2.2. Fix $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , and let a be a tuple enumerating A.

  1. (1) if $\operatorname {tp}(a/BC)$ does not divide over C.

  2. (2) if $\operatorname {tp}(a/BC)$ does not fork over C.

  3. (3) if $\operatorname {acl}(AC)\cap \operatorname {acl}(BC)=\operatorname {acl}(C)$ .

  4. (4) if $\operatorname {acl}(AD)\cap \operatorname {acl}(BD)=\operatorname {acl}(D)$ for any D such that $C\subseteq D\subseteq \operatorname {acl}(BC)$ .

For complete definitions of forking and dividing, see [Reference Adler3] or [Reference Tent and Ziegler24, Chapter 7]. Recall also that a set $C\subset \mathbb M$ is called an extension base for nonforking if for any $A\subset \mathbb M$ . Thus satisfies existence if and only if all sets are extension bases for nonforking.

Remark 2.3. In Adler’s thesis [Reference Adler1], “existence” is used for a stronger axiom that is later renamed “full existence” in [Reference Adler3]. So to forestall potential confusion, we note that existence and full existence are equivalent for (see also [Reference Conant and Hanson9, Fact 4.2]).

2.2. Algebraic extension and preservation of algebraic closure

The next definition repeats the key notion from the introduction, but in the the setting of a general ternary relation on small subsets of $\mathbb M$ .

Definition 2.4. A ternary relation has algebraic extension over $C\subset \mathbb M$ if, for any $A,B\subset \mathbb M$ , implies . We say has algebraic extension if this holds over any $C\subset \mathbb M$ .

We note that algebraic extension is nearly the same as the right closure axiom defined by d’Elbée in [Reference d’Elbée12, Reference d’Elbée13]. Indeed, the two are equivalent for ternary relations satisfying right monotonicity and right normality ( implies ). These axioms are also related to the following stronger property.

Definition 2.5. A ternary relation preserves algebraic closure if, for any $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ ,

Lemma 2.6. Let be an invariant ternary relation satisfying monotonicity and base monotonicity. Then preserves algebraic closure if and only if it has algebraic extension and satisfies the following axioms.

  1. (i) For any $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , if then .

  2. (ii) For any $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , if then .

Proof We only need to prove the nontrivial direction. Assume has algebraic extension and satisfies $(i)$ and $(ii)$ . Then in order to establish preservation of algebraic closure for , it suffices to prove:

  1. (iii) For any $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , if then .

  2. (iv) For any $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , if then .

Both of these are immediate from monotonicity and base monotonicity for .

The reason we have not given axioms $(i)$ and $(ii)$ their own names is because our focus is on which, as we observe next, always satisfies these axioms.

Proposition 2.7. In any theory, satisfies axioms $(i)$ and $(ii)$ of Lemma 2.6. Hence preserves algebraic closure if and only if it has algebraic extension.

Proof The second claim follows from the first by Lemma 2.6 and the fact that satisfies monotonicity and base monotonicity. So it remains to show satisfies $(i)$ and $(ii)$ of Lemma 2.6.

For axiom $(i)$ , recall from [Reference Tent and Ziegler24, Corollary 7.1.5] that if and only if for any C-indiscernible sequence $(b)_{i<\omega }$ , with $b_0$ enumerating B, there is an $AC$ -indiscernible sequence $(b^{\prime }_i)_{i<\omega }$ with the same type over $BC$ as $(b_i)_{i<\omega }$ . Since any $AC$ -indiscernible sequence is automatically $\operatorname {acl}(AC)$ -indiscernible (see, e.g., [Reference Tent and Ziegler24, Exercise 7.1.1]), axiom $(i)$ follows.

For axiom $(ii)$ , assume and let a and b be enumerations of A and B, respectively. Suppose $(b_i)_{i<\omega }$ is a C-indiscernible sequence with $b_0=b$ . Then $(b_i)_{i<\omega }$ is $\operatorname {acl}(C)$ -indiscernible. Since , there is some $a'$ such that $a'b_i\equiv _{\operatorname {acl}(C)}ab$ for all $i<\omega $ . Therefore $a'b_i\equiv _{C}ab$ for all $i<\omega $ . Thus we have shown .

Remark 2.8. It also follows that preserves algebraic closure if and only if, for all $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , we have

Indeed, assume the latter condition holds. We show has algebraic extension, and hence preserves algebraic closure by Proposition 2.7. Suppose . By assumption . Then by monotonicity, and thus by Proposition 2.7.

Remark 2.9. Suppose is an invariant ternary relation with monotonicity and base monotonicity (e.g., ). Consider the following axiom:

(†)

Then clearly $(\dagger )$ holds if has algebraic extension. So given that need not always satisfy algebraic extension, it becomes natural to ask whether the weaker axiom $(\dagger )$ holds for . The theory constructed in Section 3.3 will show that this is not always the case. It is also worth noting that for specifically, $(\dagger )$ is equivalent to the following weakening of algebraic extension: .

Remark 2.10. Given $A,C\subset \mathbb M$ , we always have (since any C-indiscernible sequence is $\operatorname {acl}(C)$ -indiscernible). Thus, any failure of algebraic extension over C for must involve a set B not contained in $\operatorname {acl}(C)$ .

Remark 2.11. In [Reference Adler3], algebraic extension is referred to as a “weak extension property” since it holds of any invariant ternary relation satisfying extension. Indeed, if satisfies extension and , then there is some $A'\equiv _{BC} A$ such that , whence by invariance.

Recall (e.g., from [Reference Adler3, Section 4]) that forking independence is obtained by “forcing the extension axiom” on . So in light of Proposition 2.7 and Remark 2.11, it is reasonable to expect to preserve algebraic closure in any theory. This is again a folklore result (which is actually true in this case), however a proof does not seem to appear in the literature (it is stated for simple theories in [Reference Casanovas4, Proposition 5.20]). So we take the opportunity to provide details.

Proposition 2.12. In any theory, preserves algebraic closure.

Proof Recall that satisfies monotonicity, base monotonicity, and extension (hence algebraic extension by Remark 2.11). So it suffices to show that satisfies axioms $(i)$ and $(ii)$ of Lemma 2.6.

For axiom $(i)$ , suppose . In order to show , we need to fix $D\supseteq B$ and find $E\equiv _{BC} \operatorname {acl}(AC)$ such that . Since , there is $A'\equiv _{BC} A$ such that . So by Proposition 2.7. Thus we can take $E=\operatorname {acl}(A'C)$ .

For axiom $(ii)$ , suppose . In order to show , we need to fix $D\supseteq B$ and find $A'\equiv _{BC} A$ such that . Since , there is $A'\equiv _{B\operatorname {acl}(C)} A$ such that . Then $A'\equiv _{BC}A$ , and by Proposition 2.7.

Corollary 2.13. If forking and dividing are the same for complete types (e.g., if T is simple), then preserves algebraic closure.

2.3. M-independence

We now turn our focus to the relationship between dividing independence and M-independence. In [Reference Adler3], Adler uses the erroneous Remark 5.4(3) to conclude Remark 5.4(4), which says that implies in any theory. The theory constructed in Section 3.2 will in fact also serve as a counterexample to [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4(4)] (see Corollary 3.3). However, we should note that Adler’s primary motivation for the entirety of [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4] is to obtain . This implication, which is the more important one for the purposes of developing thorn-forking, is still true, since satisfies extension.

Remark 2.14. Although the implication does not hold in general, the weaker implication is always true. However, proofs of this fact in the literature often quote [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4(3)]. This is further discussed in [Reference Conant and Hanson9, Section 2], where a direct proof of is given using P. M. Neumann’s Lemma (see [Reference Conant and Hanson9, Proposition 2.3]; the argument is similar to a Mathematics Stack Exchange post of the second-named author [Reference Kruckman18]). As noted in [Reference Conant and Hanson9, Remark 4.12], there is another quick proof of using extension for . This argument is similar to another Mathematics Stack Exchange post of the second-named author [Reference Kruckman19], and we copy it here for completeness.

Assume , and let a and b enumerate A and B. By extension for and Erdős–Rado, one can construct a C-indiscernible sequence $(b_i)_{i<\omega }$ such that $b_0=b$ and for all $i<\omega $ . By [Reference Tent and Ziegler24, Corollary 7.1.5] (and [Reference Tent and Ziegler24, Exercise 7.1.1]), there is an $\operatorname {acl}(a C)$ -indiscernible sequence $(b^{\prime }_i)_{i<\omega }$ such that $(b^{\prime }_i)_{i<\omega }\equiv _{b_0 C}(b_i)_{i<\omega }$ . Therefore

So , as desired.

A direct proof of extension for is given by Adler in [Reference Adler3, Proposition 1.5(1)]. A shorter proof using P. M. Neumann’s Lemma can be found in [Reference Conant and Hanson9, Proposition 2.1]. (Both [Reference Adler3] and [Reference Conant and Hanson9] actually focus on “full existence” for ; see [Reference Conant and Hanson9, Fact 4.2].)

Remark 2.15. Recall that is often viewed as the result of “forcing base monotonicity” on . We can now see that this is slightly misleading. In particular, it would be desirable for the ternary relation obtained by forcing base monotonicity on to be weaker than any other relation that has base monotonicity and implies . But this is not the case for , since it is not always weaker than (see Section 3.2). On the other hand, in [Reference Adler3, Corollary 4.8], Adler refers to a variation of M-independence, which is defined as if and only if for all $C\subseteq D\subseteq BC$ . By definition, has base monotonicity, implies , and is weaker than any other relation with those properties (so, e.g., always holds). Altogether, is really the result of first forcing base monotonicity on to obtain , and then forcing algebraic extension on .

We will now examine some special cases in which one can recover the implication from to .

Remark 2.16.

  1. (1) If has algebraic extension over $C\subset \mathbb M$ then .

  2. (2) It is straightforward to show that always preserves definable closure. Thus if algebraic closure coincides with definable closure, then has algebraic extension and hence .

  3. (3) If algebraic closure in T is modular then since, in this case, coincides with (see [Reference Adler3, Proposition 1.3 $(3)$ ]). However, the example in Section 3.3 has disintegrated algebraic closure. So it is not the case that if algebraic closure in T is modular then has algebraic extension.

Recall that a theory T is pregeometric if algebraic closure in T satisfies the exchange property. In this case, given a tuple $\overline {a}$ from $\mathbb M$ and a set $C\subset \mathbb M$ , we let $\dim (\overline {a}/C)$ denote the size of an $\operatorname {acl}$ -basis for $\overline {a}$ over C. In pregeometric theories, M-independence is especially meaningful due to the following characterization.

Fact 2.17. Suppose T is pregeometric. Then given $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , if and only if $\dim (\overline {a}/BC)=\dim (\overline {a}/C)$ for any finite tuple $\overline {a}$ from A. Moreover, is a strict independence relation in the sense of [Reference Adler3].

As far as we are aware, an explicit statement and proof of Fact 2.17 first appeared in unpublished notes by Adler [Reference Adler2] (see also Theorems 1.2.12 and 1.2.15 of [Reference d’Elbée13]).

Proposition 2.18. If T is pregeometric then implies .

Proof Assume T is pregeometric. Fix $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ such that . Then there is some set D such that $C\subseteq D\subseteq \operatorname {acl}(BC)$ and . So there is some singleton $e\in (\operatorname {acl}(AD)\cap \operatorname {acl}(BD))\backslash \operatorname {acl}(D)$ . Let $\overline {a}$ be a finite tuple from A of minimal length such that $e\in \operatorname {acl}(\overline {a}D)$ . Note that $\overline {a}$ is nonempty (since $e\not \in \operatorname {acl}(D)$ ) and algebraically independent over D. Write $\overline {a}=a_0\overline {a}'$ where $a_0$ is a singleton. Then $e\in \operatorname {acl}(a_0\overline {a}'D)\backslash \operatorname {acl}(\overline {a}'D)$ , hence by exchange $a_0\in \operatorname {acl}(e\overline {a}'D)\subseteq \operatorname {acl}(\overline {a}'BC)$ . Now let $\overline {b}$ be a finite tuple from B of minimal length such that $a_0\in \operatorname {acl}(\overline {a}'\overline {b}C)$ . Again, $\overline {b}$ is nonempty (since $\overline {a}$ is algebraically independent over D, and hence over C as well) and algebraically independent over $\overline {a}'C$ . Write $\overline {b}=b_0\overline {b}'$ where $b_0$ is a singleton. Then $a_0\in \operatorname {acl}(\overline {a}'b_0\overline {b}'C)\backslash \operatorname {acl}(\overline {a}'\overline {b}'C)$ , hence by exchange $b_0\in \operatorname {acl}(\overline {a}\overline {b}' C)$ . Recall that $\overline {b}'$ is algebraically independent over $\overline {a}'C$ , hence over C, so $b_0\not \in \operatorname {acl}(\overline {b}'C)$ . Altogether, $b_0$ witnesses . Therefore . By base monotonicity for , and since $\bar {b}'$ is a tuple from B, we conclude , as desired.

Remark 2.19. The previous proof actually shows that if T is pregeometric then (see Remark 2.15), hence has algebraic extension. However the example in Section 3.3 is pregeometric, and thus is not the case that has algebraic extension in an arbitrary pregeometric theory.

2.4. Conclusion

In the spirit of Adler’s work, a natural thing to do at this point is to construct a new ternary relation by forcing algebraic extension on . So we define:

Then satisfies all of the properties that Remarks 5.4(3) and 5.4(4) of [Reference Adler3] intended for . In particular, preserves algebraic closure and we have

Note also that satisfies existence (by Remark 2.10). Moreover, if and only if forking and dividing are the same for complete types over algebraically closed sets.

Altogether, perhaps is the more natural notion of “dividing independence” in an arbitrary theory. For example, by replacing with , we obtain the following variations of the (formerly) open questions discussed in the introduction.

Question 2.20. Let T be a complete theory.

  1. (1) Suppose satisfies existence. Do and coincide?

  2. (2) Suppose T is $\mathrm {NSOP}$ (or even just $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ ). Do and coincide (even just over models)?

Implicit in these questions is the third question of whether there is an $\mathrm {NSOP}$ theory in which fails existence. In fact, this is open even for $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ theories, and is a question of notable significance for this region due to the results of [Reference Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey15]. We also note that for T $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ , the second question is a stronger version of [Reference Kaplan and Ramsey17, Question 9.19], which asks whether for all sets A and models $M\prec N\prec \mathbb M\models T$ .

3. The counterexamples

3.1. Dense circular order with unordered pairs

In this section, we describe a very straightforward example of the failure of algebraic extension for (refuting [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4(3)]).

Let $T=\mathrm {Th}({\mathbb Q},\operatorname {cyc})^{\mathrm {eq}}$ , where

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{cyc}(x,y,z) \Leftrightarrow (x<y<z) \vee (z<x<y)\vee (y<z<x). \end{align*}$$

Let O be the home sort, and let P be the sort corresponding to the definable equivalence relation E defined by $(x,y)E(x',y')$ if and only if $\{x,y\} = \{x',y'\}$ . So the elements of P can be identified with the unordered pairs and singletons from O. Let $q\colon O^2\to P$ be the quotient map. Working in $\mathbb M\models T$ , let $a,d_1,d_2$ be three distinct elements of the home sort with $\operatorname {cyc}(d_1,a,d_2)$ , and let $b=q(d_1,d_2)$ .

Claim 3.1. , but .

Proof First, since $d_1,d_2\in \operatorname {acl}(b)$ , and the formula $\operatorname {cyc}(d_1,x,d_2)$ divides over $\varnothing $ , we have . So we need to show . We start with a general remark. Suppose $a'$ , $d^{\prime }_1$ , $d^{\prime }_2$ are any pairwise distinct elements of O, and set $b'=q(d^{\prime }_1,d^{\prime }_2)$ . Then either $\operatorname {cyc}(d^{\prime }_1,a',d^{\prime }_2)$ , in which case we have an isomorphism $ad_1d_2\to a'd^{\prime }_1d^{\prime }_2$ , or $\operatorname {cyc}(d^{\prime }_2,a',d^{\prime }_1)$ , in which case we have an isomorphism $ad_1d_2\to a'd^{\prime }_2d^{\prime }_1$ . In either case, by quantifier elimination this yields $a'b'\equiv _\varnothing ab$ .

Now let $(b_n)_{n<\omega }$ be an indiscernible sequence in $\operatorname {tp}(b/\varnothing )$ . For each n, let ${b_n=q(d^n_1,d^n_2)}$ , and note that $d^n_1\neq d^n_2$ . Choose $a'$ from the home sort distinct from $d^n_1,d^n_2$ for all $n<\omega $ . Then, by the above, we have $a'b_n\equiv _\varnothing ab$ for all $n<\omega $ , so , as desired.

We conclude that in T, fails algebraic extension over $\varnothing $ . To recap the discussion from the introduction, note that T is an NIP theory, and that $\varnothing $ is (necessarily) not an extension base for nonforking.

3.2. Generic binary function with unordered pairs

In this section, we give another example of a theory in which fails algebraic extension. Like before, this theory will be the imaginary expansion of a well-known example from the literature. However, in this case we will have better behavior related to forking (compared to the circular order on ${\mathbb Q}$ ), and thus the failure of algebraic extension for will have more interesting consequences.

Let $T^{\varnothing }_f$ be the model completion of the empty theory in a language containing only a binary function symbol f. Then $T^{\varnothing }_f$ is $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ by [Reference Kruckman and Ramsey20], and thus so is the imaginary expansion, which we denote $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ . We will prove that $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ has the following properties:

  1. (1) For any small model M, does not imply . So in addition to implying the failure of algebraic extension for (even over models), this also refutes the weaker claim made in [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4 $(4)$ ].

  2. (2) Consequently, , even over models, which gives a negative answer to an open question about $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ theories (discussed in the introduction).

  3. (3) All sets are extension bases for nonforking in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ . So this theory also gives a negative answer to [Reference Adler1, Question A.1], which asks whether forking and dividing are always the same for complete types in such a theory.

Toward obtaining these statements, we first recall from Corollaries 3.10 and 3.11 of [Reference Kruckman and Ramsey20] that $T^{\varnothing }_f$ has quantifier elimination and the algebraic closure of any set coincides with the substructure generated by that set. Moving now to $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ , we work in a similar setting as in the previous subsection. Let O be the home sort, and let P be the sort corresponding to the definable equivalence relation E defined by $(x,y)E(x',y')$ if and only if $\{x,y\} = \{x',y'\}$ . So as before, the elements of P can be identified with the unordered pairs and singletons from O. Let $q\colon O^2\to P$ be the quotient map. We write $\operatorname {acl}^O(x)$ for the elements of the home sort which are algebraic over x.

Let M be a small model of $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ , and write $M^O$ for its home sort. Let $d_1$ and $d_2$ be distinct elements of the home sort, which are not in M, such that $f(d_i,d_j) = d_i$ for all $i,j\in \{1,2\}$ and $f(m,d_k) = f(d_k,m) = d_k$ for all $k\in \{1,2\}$ and all $m\in M^O$ . Let $b = q(d_1,d_2)$ .

Note that $\operatorname {acl}^O(Mb) = \operatorname {acl}^O(Md_1d_2) = \langle M^O d_1 d_2\rangle = M^O\cup \{d_1,d_2\}$ , and the map swapping $d_1$ and $d_2$ and fixing M pointwise is an automorphism of this substructure. Also, $\operatorname {acl}^O(Md_i) = \langle M^Od_i\rangle = M^O\cup \{d_i\}$ for all $i\in \{1,2\}$ .

Now let a be an element of the home sort such that $f(a,a) = a$ , $f(a,m) = f(m,a) = a$ for all $m\in M$ , $f(a,d_1) = f(d_1,a) = a$ , and $f(a,d_2) = f(d_2,a) = d_1$ . Then $\operatorname {acl}^O(Mad_1) = \langle M^Oad_1\rangle = M^O\cup \{a,d_1\}$ , while $\operatorname {acl}^O(Mad_2) = \langle M^Oad_2\rangle = M^O\cup \{a,d_1,d_2\} = \operatorname {acl}^O(Mad_1d_2)$ .

Claim 3.2. , but and .

Proof First note that $d_1\in \operatorname {acl}(Mad_2)\cap \operatorname {acl}(Mb)$ , but $d_1\notin \operatorname {acl}(Md_2)$ . So . Since $d_2\in \operatorname {acl}(Mb)$ , we have and .

Now we show . Let $a'$ be an element of O and $b'$ an element of P, with $b' = q(d_1',d_2')$ . By quantifier elimination, $ab\equiv _M a'b'$ if and only if there is an isomorphism $\langle Mad_1d_2\rangle \to \langle Ma'd_1'd_2'\rangle $ , fixing M pointwise, with $a\mapsto a'$ and either $d_1\mapsto d_1'$ and $d_2\mapsto d_2'$ , or $d_1\mapsto d_2'$ and $d_2\mapsto d_1'$ .

Let $(b_n)_{n< \omega }$ be an M-indiscernible sequence in $\text {tp}(b/M)$ . For each n, let ${b_n = q(d^n_1,d^n_2)}$ , and note that $d^n_1\neq d^n_2$ and $f(d^n_i,d^n_j) = d^n_i$ for all $i,j\in \{1,2\}$ . Without loss of generality, we can enumerate $d^n_1$ and $d^n_2$ so that the sequence $(b_nd^n_1d^n_2)_{n< \omega }$ is M-indiscernible.

Case 1: For all $n\neq m$ , $d^n_2 \neq d^m_2$ . Then we can find an $a'$ such that $f(a',a') = a'$ , $f(a',m) = f(m,a') = a'$ for all $m\in M$ , $f(a',d^n_1) = f(d^n_1,a') = a'$ , and $f(a',d^n_2) = f(d^n_2,a') = d^n_1$ for all n. Then $a'b_n \equiv _M ab$ for all n.

Case 2: For all $n\neq m$ , $d^n_2 = d^m_2$ . In this case, if $d^n_1\neq d^m_1$ , we cannot find $a'$ such that $f(a',d^n_2) = d^n_1$ and $f(a',d^m_2) = d^m_1$ . However, we can find an $a'$ such that $f(a',a') = a'$ , $f(a',m) = f(m,a') = a'$ for all $m\in M$ , $f(a',d^n_2) = f(d^n_2,a') = a'$ , and $f(a',d^n_1) = f(d^n_1,a') = d^n_2$ for all n. Then $a'b_n \equiv _M ab$ for all n (though in this case the witnessing isomorphisms map $d^n_1\mapsto d_2$ and $d^n_2\mapsto d_1$ ).

In either case, we have an $a'$ such that $a'b_n \equiv _M ab$ for all $n<\omega $ , so .

Corollary 3.3. does not necessarily imply in general. Moreover, does not necessarily imply in $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ theories, even over models.

Explicitly, in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ the formula $\exists w_1\exists w_2\,(q(w_1,w_2) = b\land f(x,w_2) = w_1)$ in $\operatorname {tp}(a/Mb)$ forks but does not divide. It implies the disjunction $f(x,d_2) = d_1\lor f(x,d_1) = d_2$ , and each disjunct divides over M.

We have now established statements $(1)$ and $(2)$ above. For $(3)$ , we need the following general observation.

Proposition 3.4. Suppose T is a complete theory with geometric elimination of imaginaries.

  1. (a) Assume satisfies existence in T. Then satisfies existence in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ .

  2. (b) Assume in T. Then in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ .

Proof We prove part $(b)$ and leave $(a)$ (which is similar and easier) to the reader. Fix $A,B,C\subseteq \mathbb M^{\mathrm {eq}}$ and assume in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ . We need to show in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ . Without loss of generality, assume $C\subseteq A\cap B$ . By geometric elimination of imaginaries, there are real sets $A',B',C'\subseteq \mathbb M$ such that $\operatorname {acl}^{\mathrm {eq}}(A)=\operatorname {acl}^{\mathrm {eq}}(A')$ , $\operatorname {acl}^{\mathrm {eq}}(B)=\operatorname {acl}^{\mathrm {eq}}(B')$ , and $\operatorname {acl}^{\mathrm {eq}}(C)=\operatorname {acl}^{\mathrm {eq}}(C')$ . Since preserves algebraic closure, we have . By monotonicity for and Proposition 2.7, this yields in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ , and hence also in T. So in T, and thus in T by assumption. Therefore in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ , which yields in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ using Proposition 2.12 and the choice of $A'$ , $B'$ , and $C'$ .

Now, to obtain statement $(3)$ above, we recall the results from [Reference Kruckman and Ramsey20] that $T^{\varnothing }_f$ has weak elimination of imaginaries and satisfies (see Section 5.1 for further related discussion). So satisfies existence in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ by the previous proposition. Note that this conclusion only requires part $(a)$ ; however part $(b)$ gives us the stronger statement that in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ (cf. Question 2.20).

Remark 3.5. Since is true in $T^{\varnothing }_f$ but not in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ , our example shows that the property does not transfer from T to $T^{\mathrm {eq}}$ , even when T has weak elimination of imaginaries. This is in contrast to the properties and existence for in Proposition 3.4.

3.3. The original counterexample

In this section, we construct a complete theory for which does not have algebraic extension due to a failure of the weaker axiom discussed in Remark 2.9. Specifically, there are $a,b\in \mathbb M$ such that and . This is also the original counterexample first discovered by the second-named author to refute [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4(3)].

The example we construct will be the theory of a Fraïssé limit for a Fraïssé class with free amalgamation. We briefly recall the definition of free amalgamation. Given a (many-sorted) language $\mathcal L$ with only relation symbols and constant symbols, and three $\mathcal L$ -structures A, B, C, where C is a common substructure of A and B, the free amalgam of A and B over C is the $\mathcal L$ -structure D defined as follows. For each sort S, $S(D) = S(A)\sqcup _{S(C)} S(B)$ , the disjoint union of $S(A)$ and $S(B)$ over $S(C)$ . For each relation symbol R in $\mathcal L$ , $R^D = R^A\cup R^B$ . That is, no relations hold in D, other than those which hold in A and in B. The constant symbols in $\mathcal L$ receive the same interpretation in D as in A, B, and C. We say that a class of finite $\mathcal L$ -structures has free amalgamation if whenever A, B, and C are in the class, and C is a common substructure of A and B, the free amalgam of A and B over C is again in the class.

We now describe our example. Consider a language $\mathcal L'$ with:

  • * Three sorts: O, G, and C.

  • * Two constant symbols $0$ and $1$ of type C.

  • * A relation symbol R of type $G\times G \times C$ .

  • * A relation symbol E of type $O\times G \times C$ .

Let $\mathcal {K}$ be the class of finite $\mathcal L'$ -structures satisfying the following conditions:

  1. (1) $0\neq 1$ , and for all $c\in C$ , $c = 0$ or $c = 1$ .

  2. (2) The binary relations $R(x,y,0)$ and $R(x,y,1)$ are disjoint graph relations on G, i.e., they are each symmetric and anti-reflexive, and for all $v,w\in G$ , it is not the case that $R(v,w,0)$ and $R(v,w,1)$ .

  3. (3) For all $v,w\in G$ and $c\in C$ , if $R(v,w,c)$ , then there is no $o\in O$ such that $E(o,v,c)$ and $E(o,w,c)$ .

It is easy to check that $\mathcal {K}$ is a Fraïssé class with free amalgamation. Let $M'$ be the Fraïssé limit of $\mathcal {K}$ .

Now let $\mathcal L$ be the sub-language of $\mathcal L'$ which omits the constant symbols $0$ and $1$ . Let M be the reduct of $M'$ to $\mathcal L$ , and set $T_{\mathsf {OG}}=\mathrm {Th}(M)$ . We observe the following:

  1. (i) $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ is $\aleph _0$ -categorical. Indeed, it is a reduct of a Fraïssé limit of a class of finite structures in a finite language with no function symbols.

  2. (ii) For any $A\subseteq M$ , $\operatorname {acl}(A) = A\cup C$ . Indeed, $A\cup C$ is the domain of a substructure of $M'$ . Since amalgamation in $\mathcal {K}$ is disjoint, $A\cup C$ is algebraically closed in $M'$ , so it remains algebraically closed in the reduct M.

  3. (iii) There is an automorphism $\sigma $ of M swapping the two elements of C. This can be established by a back-and-forth argument.

  4. (iv) For any finite tuples a and b from M, $\operatorname {tp}(a) = \operatorname {tp}(b)$ if and only if there is an isomorphism of $\mathcal L$ -structures $f\colon \operatorname {acl}(a)\to \operatorname {acl}(b)$ such that $f(a) = b$ . The forward direction follows from $\aleph _0$ -homogeneity of M. For the converse, suppose $f\colon \operatorname {acl}(a)\to \operatorname {acl}(b)$ is such an isomorphism. If f is the identity on C, then it is an isomorphism between $\mathcal L'$ -substructures of $M'$ , so it extends to an automorphism of $M'$ moving a to b, and hence $\operatorname {tp}(a) = \operatorname {tp}(b)$ . If f swaps the two elements of C, let $f' = f\circ \sigma ^{-1}\colon \sigma (\operatorname {acl}(a))\to \operatorname {acl}(b)$ , where $\sigma $ is an automorphism of M as in $(iii)$ above. Then $f'$ is an isomorphism which is the identity on C and such that $f'(\sigma (a)) = b$ . Extending $f'$ to an automorphism of $M'$ as above, then pre-composing with $\sigma $ , we find an automorphism of M moving a to b, so $\operatorname {tp}(a) = \operatorname {tp}(b)$ .

By $\aleph _0$ -categoricity, to understand dividing and the properties $\mathrm {SOP}_n$ in $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ , it suffices to work in M. We will refer to the elements of C as $0$ and $1$ (even though these constant symbols are not in $\mathcal L$ ).

Claim 3.6. $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ is $\mathrm {SOP}_3$ and $\mathrm {NSOP}_4$ .

Proof Since $\mathrm {Th}(M')$ is the theory of an $\aleph _0$ -categorical Fraïssé limit with free amalgamation, it is $\mathrm {NSOP}_4$ . (This is an unpublished result of R. Patel [Reference Patel22]; see also [Reference Conant7, Section 4].) Therefore its reduct $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ is also $\mathrm {NSOP}_4$ . We will show that $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ is $\mathrm {SOP}_3$ using the “two formula” formulation (see, e.g., [Reference Shelah23, Claim 2.19]). Let x be a variable of type O and $y,y'$ variables of type G. Let $\varphi (x;y,y')$ be the formula $E(x,y,0)$ , and let $\varphi '(x;y,y')$ be the formula $E(x,y',0)$ . Let $(b_i,b_i')_{i< \omega }$ be a sequence such that $R(b_i',b_j,0)$ if and only if $i< j$ . Then for all $n< \omega $ , we have $\{\varphi (x;b_i,b_i')\mid i < n\}\cup \{\varphi '(x;b_j,b_j')\mid j\geq n\}$ is consistent by genericity of the Fraïssé limit and compactness, but for all $i < j$ , $\{\varphi '(x;b_i,b_i'),\varphi (x;b_j,b_j')\}$ is inconsistent by condition (3) in the definition of $\mathcal K$ . This establishes $\mathrm {SOP}_3$ .

We now show that $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ exhibits the properties claimed at the start of this section.

Claim 3.7. Fix $a\in O$ and $b\in G$ such that $E(a,b,0)$ and $\lnot E(a,b,1)$ . Then , but .

Proof We first show . Let $(b_i)_{i< \omega }$ be an indiscernible sequence in $\text {tp}(b/\varnothing )$ .

Case 1: $M\models \lnot R(b_i,b_j,0)$ for all $i\neq j$ . Then we can find some $a'\in O$ with $M\models E(a',b_i,0)\land \lnot E(a',b_i,1)$ for all $i< \omega $ . The map $f_i\colon \operatorname {acl}(a'b_i)\to \operatorname {acl}(ab)$ which is the identity on C and maps $a'$ to a and $b_i$ to b is an isomorphism of $\mathcal L$ -substructures of M, so $a'b_i\equiv ab$ for all $i<\omega $ by $(iv)$ above.

Case 2: Otherwise, by indiscernibility, $M\models R(b_i,b_j,0)$ for all $i\neq j$ . Since $R(x,y,0)$ and $R(x,y,1)$ are disjoint relations, $M\models \lnot R(b_i,b_j,1)$ for all $i\neq j$ . So we can find some $a'\in O$ with $M\models E(a',b_i,1)\land \lnot E(a',b_i,0)$ for all $i<\omega $ . Now the map $f_i\colon \operatorname {acl}(a'b_i)\to \operatorname {acl}(ab)$ which swaps the elements of C and maps $a'$ to a and $b_i$ to b is an isomorphism of $\mathcal L$ -substructures of M, so $a'b_i\equiv ab$ for all $i<\omega $ by $(iv)$ above.

It remains to show . Note that $\operatorname {acl}(\varnothing ) = C$ , so $\text {tp}(a/\operatorname {acl}(\varnothing )b)$ contains the formula $E(x,b,0)$ . It suffices to show that this formula divides over C.

By $(iv)$ above, all elements of G have the same type over C. Let $(b_i)_{i< \omega }$ be a sequence of elements of G such that for all $i\neq j$ , $R(b_i,b_j,0)$ . Then the set $\{E(x,b_i,0)\mid i< \omega \}$ is $2$ -inconsistent, which witnesses dividing.

In the introduction we also claimed that all sets are extension bases in $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ . This will be deduced from our general analysis of free amalgamation theories in Section 4 (see Corollary 4.10). Therefore $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ is a second example demonstrating a negative answer to [Reference Adler3, Question A.1] (in addition to the example in Section 3.2).

4. Free amalgamation theories

In this section, we show that if T is a free amalgamation theory (as defined in [Reference Conant7]) with disintegrated algebraic closure, then forking and dividing are the same for complete types over algebraically closed sets. This proof is from an unpublished research note by the authors, written in May 2017. In the original note, we in fact claimed that this result holds for complete types over any set. However, our argument was flawed because we used [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4(3)] to reduce to algebraically closed sets. In fact, the stronger claim fails since the theory $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ from Section 3.3 is a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure (see Proposition 4.9).

Let T be a complete first-order theory with monster model $\mathbb M$ . For convenience, and to follow the conventions of [Reference Conant7], we will call a subset $A\subset \mathbb M$ closed if $A=\operatorname {acl}(A)$ .

Definition 4.1. T is a free amalgamation theory if there is an invariant ternary relation on small subsets of $\mathbb M$ satisfying monotonicity and the following axioms:

  1. (i) (Symmetry) For all $A,B,C$ , if then .

  2. (ii) (Full transitivity) For all A and $D\subseteq C\subseteq B$ , if and only if and .

  3. (iii) (Full existence over closed sets) For all $B,C\subset \mathbb M$ and tuples $a\in \mathbb M$ , if C is closed then there is $a'\equiv _C a$ such that .

  4. (iv) (Stationarity over closed sets) For all closed $C\subset \mathbb M$ and closed tuples $a,a',b\in \mathbb M$ , with $C\subseteq a\cap b$ , if , , and $a'\equiv _C a$ , then $ab\equiv _C a'b$ .

  5. (v) (Freedom) For all $A,B,C,D$ , if and $C\cap AB\subseteq D\subseteq C$ , then .

  6. (vi) (Closure) For all closed $A,B,C$ , if $C\subseteq A\cap B$ and then $AB$ is closed.

We will ultimately focus on the case when T has disintegrated algebraic closure, which is to say that the algebraic closure of any set $A\subset \mathbb M$ is the union of the algebraic closures of singleton elements in A. This is equivalent to the property that $AB$ is closed for any closed $A,B\subset \mathbb M$ .

Example 4.2. The following are examples of free amalgamation theories with disintegrated algebraic closure.

  1. (1) Let $\mathcal L$ be a finite relational language and let $\mathcal K$ be a Fraïssé class of finite $\mathcal L$ -structures with free amalgamation. Let T be the complete theory of the Fraïssé limit of $\mathcal K$ . Then T is a free amalgamation theory, and $\operatorname {acl}(A)=A$ for any $A\subset \mathbb M$ .

  2. (2) Let $\mathcal L$ be the language of graphs and fix $n\geq 3$ . There is a unique (up to isomorphism) countable, universal, and existentially complete $(K_n+K_3)$ -free graph (where $K_n+K_3$ denotes the free amalgamation of $K_n$ and $K_3$ over a single vertex). If T is the complete theory of this graph, then T is a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure.

In both cases, the desired ternary relation is free amalgamation of relational structures: given $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , if and only if $ABC$ is the free amalgam of $AC$ and $BC$ over C. The verification of the axioms of Definition 4.1 for these examples is sketched in [Reference Conant7]. In the first case, all axioms are immediate from classical Fraïssé theory (see, e.g., [Reference Hodges16]). For the second case, the axioms rely on work of Cherlin, Shelah, and Shi [Reference Cherlin, Shelah and Shi5], and Patel [Reference Patel22].

Recall our goal is to show that if T is a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure, then forking and dividing are the same for complete types over algebraically closed sets. Our proof strategy will follow that of [Reference Conant8], where this result is shown for the special case that T is the theory of the generic $K_n$ -free graph. In particular, we will first prove a “mixed transitivity” lemma involving dividing independence and the ternary relation in Definition 4.1. This general strategy is also used in [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Reference d’Elbée12, Reference Kruckman and Ramsey20], where the equivalence of forking and dividing for complete types (over algebraically closed sets) is established via a mixed transitivity lemma involving a stationary independence relation.

Lemma 4.3. Let T be a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure. Suppose $A,B,C,D\subset \mathbb M$ are such that $D\subseteq C\subseteq B$ and $C,D$ are closed. Then

Proof Assume and . Enumerate $B=b=(b_i)_{i\in I}$ . Assume $I_0\subseteq J$ are initial segments of I such that $D=(b_i)_{i\in I_0}$ and $C=c=(b_i)_{i\in J}$ . Let $(b^n)_{n<\omega }$ be a D-indiscernible sequence, with $b^0=b$ . Let a enumerate A. We want to find $a'$ such that $a'b^n\equiv _Dab$ for all $n<\omega $ .

For $n<\omega $ , let $c^n=(b^n_i)_{i\in J}$ , and note that $(c^n)_{n<\omega }$ is D-indiscernible with $c^0=c$ . There is some $I_1$ such that $I_0\subseteq I_1\subseteq J$ and, for all $m< n<\omega $ and $i\in J$ , $b^m_i=b^n_i$ if and only if $i\in I_1$ . Set $D'=(b_i)_{i\in I_1}$ , so $D\subseteq D'\subseteq C$ , and by base monotonicity for , we have . Note also that $(b^n)_{n<\omega }$ and $(c^n)_{n<\omega }$ are each $D'$ -indiscernible. We claim $D'$ is closed so that we may assume without loss of generality that $I_1=I_0$ and $D'=D$ .

To show $D'$ is closed, fix $d\in \operatorname {acl}(D')$ . Since C is closed, $d = b_{j_0}$ for some $j_0\in J$ . Let $j_0<\dots <j_{k-1}$ be the indices of the finitely many conjugates of $b_{j_0}$ over $D'$ . For every $n\in \omega $ , there is some permutation $\sigma _n\in S_k$ such that $b^n_{j_i} = b_{j_{\sigma _n(i)}}$ for all $i<k$ . By Pigeonhole, there exist $n<m$ such that $\sigma _n = \sigma _m$ . Then $b^n_{j_i} = b^m_{j_i}$ for all $i<k$ , so by indiscernibility $b^{n'}_{j_i} = b^n_{j_i}$ for all $n<n'$ , and hence $j_i\in I_1$ for all $i<k$ . In particular, $d = b_{j_0}\in D'$ .

Since , there is $a_*$ such that $a_*c^n\equiv _D ac$ for all $n<\omega $ . Set $C_*=\operatorname {acl}(c^{<\omega })$ . Let e enumerate $\operatorname {acl}(a_*C_*)$ . By full existence for , there is $e'\equiv _{C_*} e$ such that . Note that there is some $a'\equiv _{C_*}a_*$ such that $e'$ enumerates $\operatorname {acl}(a'C_*)$ . So we have . For each $n<\omega $ , we have $a'c^n\equiv _Da_*c^n\equiv _Dac$ . By monotonicity, for all $n<\omega $ .

Claim. For any $n<\omega $ , $C^*\cap \operatorname {acl}(a'c^n)b^n=c^n$ .

Proof Since algebraic closure in T is disintegrated, we have $\operatorname {acl}(a'c^n)=\operatorname {acl}(a')c^n$ and $C^*=c^{<\omega }$ . So it suffices to show $c^{<\omega }\cap \operatorname {acl}(a')b^n=c^n$ . Fix some $x\in c^{<\omega }\cap \operatorname {acl}(a')b^n$ . There is $m<\omega $ and $i\in J$ such that $x=b^m_i$ . Suppose first that $x\in \operatorname {acl}(a')$ . Then $b^m_i\in \operatorname {acl}(a')\cap c^m$ , which means $b_i\in \operatorname {acl}(a)\cap c$ . Since , we have $\operatorname {acl}(a)\cap c\subseteq D$ , and so $i\in I_0$ . Thus $b^m_i=b^n_i\in c^n$ . Finally, suppose $x\in b^n$ . There is $j\in I$ such that $b^m_i=b^n_j$ . It follows that $b^m_i=b^n_i$ (if $m=n$ this is trivial, and if $m\neq n$ use $b^m_i=b^n_j$ and indiscernibility). So $x=b^n_i\in c^n$ . $\dashv _{\text {claim}}$

To finish the proof, we show $a'b^n\equiv _D ab$ for all $n<\omega $ . So fix $n<\omega $ , and let $\sigma \in \operatorname {Aut}(\mathbb M/D)$ be such that $\sigma (b^n)=b$ (note that $\sigma (c^n)=c$ ). By the claim and freedom, we have . So by invariance, and since $\sigma (\operatorname {acl}(a'c^n))=\operatorname {acl}(\sigma (a')c)$ . Also, we have $\sigma (a')c\equiv _D a'c^n\equiv _D ac$ , and so $\sigma (a')c\equiv _c ac$ . Therefore $\operatorname {acl}(\sigma (a')c)\equiv _c \operatorname {acl}(ac)$ . So we may fix tuples e and $e'$ such that $\operatorname {acl}(ac)=ace$ , $\operatorname {acl}(\sigma (a')c)=\sigma (a')ce'$ , and $ace\equiv _c \sigma (a')ce'$ . We have and, by assumption, . Since $c\subseteq ace\cap b$ , we may apply stationarity to conclude $aceb\equiv _c \sigma (a')ce' b$ . In particular, $a'b^n\equiv _D \sigma (a')b\equiv _D ab$ .

Remark 4.4. Suppose T is a free amalgamation theory, witnessed by . Given closed $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ , with $C\subseteq A\cap B$ , if then by [Reference Conant7, Lemma 7.15]. Therefore Lemma 4.3 can be seen as a weakening of transitivity for . It is worth noting that many examples of such theories are not simple (e.g., the theory of the generic $K_n$ -free graph for $n\geq 3$ ), and hence need not be transitive.

We now prove the main result.

Theorem 4.5. Let T be a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure. Then for any $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M$ ,

Proof First recall that in any theory we have . So conversely, suppose . We want to show . By Proposition 2.12, it suffices to show . We have by base monotonicity for . So, altogether, we may assume without loss of generality that $B,C$ are closed and $C\subseteq B$ . To show , it suffices to fix $\hat {B}\supseteq B$ and find $A'\equiv _{B}A$ such that .

Let witness that T is a free amalgamation theory. By full existence there is $A'$ such that $A'\equiv _B A$ and . By invariance of , we have . By Lemma 4.3, , as desired.

Remark 4.6. Given $n\geq 3$ , let $T_n$ be the theory of the generic $K_n$ -free graph. In [Reference Conant8], is characterized for $T_n$ by purely combinatorial properties of graphs. It would be interesting to give similar descriptions of for other theories listed in Example 4.2.

Question 4.7. Does Theorem 4.5 hold without the assumption of disintegrated algebraic closure, or under the weaker assumption that algebraic closure is modular?

A possible lead toward the previous question could be recent work of Mutchnik [Reference Mutchnik21] which, among other things, studies a generalization of the class of free amalgamation theories.

Theorem 4.5 and Remark 2.10 together yield the following conclusion.

Corollary 4.8. If T is a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure then all sets are extension bases for nonforking.

Finally we revisit the theory $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ from Section 3.3.

Proposition 4.9. $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ is a free amalgamation theory with disintegrated algebraic closure.

Proof If $A\subset \mathbb M$ then $\operatorname {acl}(A)=A\cup \{0,1\}$ . Therefore algebraic closure is disintegrated. Let denote the usual free amalgamation of relational structures. Then we have invariance, monotonicity, symmetry, full transitivity, and freedom by the standard proofs (see the discussion in [Reference Conant7, Example 3.2]). Full existence over closed sets follows from free amalgamation in the class $\mathcal K$ , and stationarity over closed sets follows from the description of algebraic closure and “almost quantifier elimination”. Finally, the closure axiom is trivial since algebraic closure is disintegrated.

Corollary 4.10. In $T_{\mathsf {OG}}$ , satisfies full existence, but .

5. Corrections to literature

The purpose of this section is to collect and discuss some arguments in the literature which rely on the incorrect statements made in [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4]. We do not claim that this list is exhaustive.

5.1. The model completion of the empty theory

Let $\mathcal L$ be an arbitrary language and let $T^{\varnothing }_{\mathcal L}$ be the model completion of the empty $\mathcal L$ -theory. In [Reference Kruckman and Ramsey20, Proposition 3.17], it is shown that coincides with in (any completion of) $T^{\varnothing }_{\mathcal L}$ . The proof quotes [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4(4)] for , which is valid in this case since algebraic closure and definable closure coincide (see [Reference Kruckman and Ramsey20, Corollary 3.11]).

5.2. Simple free amalgamation theories

In [Reference Conant7], preservation of algebraic closure for is stated as Fact 7.4 and used in the proof that a free amalgamation theory is simple if and only if it is $\mathrm {NTP}_2$ , as well as the corresponding analysis of forking independence in this case. However, it turns out that the full power of Fact 7.4 is only required in the context of simplicity, and the remaining applications actually use weaker statements (which are true). See the corrigenda to [Reference Conant7] for further details (available in the most recent arXiv version of [Reference Conant7]).

5.3. Generic incidence structures

Let $\mathcal L=\{P,L,I\}$ where P and L are unary relations (for “points” and “lines”) and I is a binary relation (for “incidences”). An incidence structure is an $\mathcal L$ -structure in which P and L partition the universe and $I\subseteq P\times L$ . In [Reference Conant and Kruckman10], we study the complete theory $T_{m,n}$ of existentially closed $K_{m,n}$ -free incidence structures, where $m,n\geq 1$ . The special case $T_{2,2}$ can also be viewed as the theory of existentially closed projective planes. In the paper, we define a certain ternary relation and use it to show that $T_{m,n}$ is $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ and that, over models, coincides with Kim-independence (see [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Theorem 4.11]). We later claim in Corollaries 4.14 and 4.24 of [Reference Conant and Kruckman10] that and are the same, and coincide with “forcing base monotonicity” on (in the sense of [Reference Adler3]). However, our arguments tacitly use [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4(3)] in a few places and, as we will show below, it is in fact not true that has algebraic extension in $T_{m,n}$ for all $m,n\geq 1$ .

Before getting deeper into these issues, we first note that when $m=n=2$ (which is the main case of interest), our proofs are valid because algebraic closure coincides with definable closure in this case (see [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Proposition 2.14] and the closing remarks of [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Section 2]). Our proofs are also valid when $\min \{m,n\}=1$ because in this case $T_{m,n}$ is stable (see [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Section 4.5]).

For general $m,n$ , we will show that the above claims about are not always true. However, it is easy to see that our proofs work with replaced by . Thus we have that for $A,B,C\subset \mathbb M\models T_{m,n}$ ,

Part of the proof uses [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Lemma 4.23], which gives a mixed transitivity statement for using a stationary independence relation (similar to Lemma 4.3). The proof tacitly assumes preservation of algebraic closure for , and so here one needs to also replace with to obtain a correct statement.

We also note that [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Proposition 4.22] includes the claim that implies . While this is presented as an immediate consequence of [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Corollary 4.14] (which is false as stated), one can instead obtain this claim directly from Lemma 4.8 and Remark 4.12 of [Reference Conant and Kruckman10], which are unaffected by the issues with [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4].

Finally, we describe a counterexample to [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Corollary 4.14], which also gives an instance where and disagree. We will assume some familiarity with general setup of [Reference Conant and Kruckman10]. Work in $T_{4,2}$ , so any four points are incident a unique line, and any two lines have exactly three points incident to them. Consider the incidence structure $(P,L;I)$ where $P=\{a_0,a_1,a_2,d_0,d_1,d_2\}$ , $L=\{b_0,b_1,e\}$ , and I consists of $(d_0,e)$ , $(d_1,e)$ , $(d_i,b_j)$ for all i and j, and $(a_i,e)$ for all i. Then $(P,L;I)$ is $K_{4,2}$ -free, so we can freely complete it and embed it in the monster model of $T_{4,2}$ . Note that $\{d_0, d_1, d_2\}$ is the unique set of three points incident to the lines $b_0$ and $b_1$ , hence $d_0,d_1,d_2\in \operatorname {acl}(b_0,b_1)$ . One can then show that and , which altogether refutes [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Corollary 4.14]. Moreover, since implies (and satisfies base monotonicity and extension), we also have and thus a counterexample to [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Corollary 4.24]. We leave the verification of these details to the reader. When checking , the key point is that every indiscernible sequence of $3$ -tuples is either constant in at least two coordinates or non-constant in at least two coordinates. This explains the need for $m=4$ in order to work with $3$ -tuples.

Recall that $T_{4,2}$ is $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ and thus, in addition to the theory $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ from Section 3.2, this gives another counterexample to the question from [Reference d’Elbée12] discussed in the introduction. Note also that one can adjust the above configuration to obtain for any small model M by starting with a copy of $(P,L;I)$ with no incidences to M (and taking the free completion with M).

For $m\geq 4$ and $n\geq 2$ , a similar configuration can be constructed in $T_{m,n}$ using the interpretation of $T_{4,2}$ in $T_{m,n}$ described in [Reference Conant and Kruckman10, Lemma 3.2]. This leaves open the case of $T_{3,2}$ , which we will not pursue here.

5.4. Algebraically closed fields with a generic additive subgroup

For a fixed $p>0$ , let ACFG denote the model companion of the theory of algebraically closed fields of characteristic p with a predicate G for an additive subgroup. It turns out that the study of this theory is affected by [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4] in ways very similar to the theories $T_{m,n}$ (discussed in the previous subsection). In particular, d’Elbée first showed in [Reference d’Elbée11] that (any completion of) ACFG is properly $\mathrm {NSOP}_1$ , and then in a sequel paper [Reference d’Elbée12] it is asserted that and are the same and coincide with forcing base monotonicity on Kim independence. However, some arguments in [Reference d’Elbée12] rely on [Reference Adler3, Remark 5.4]. Following discussions based on an early version of this paper, d’Elbée has constructed an example showing that, like in $T^{\mathrm {eq}}_f$ and $T_{4,2}$ , and need not coincide in ACFG, even over models. On the other hand, the arguments from [Reference d’Elbée12] work with replaced by . So it is still true that forking and dividing are the same for complete types over algebraically closed sets, and that is the base monotonization of Kim independence (see [Reference d’Elbée14] for details).

Acknowledgements

The authors thank Christian d’Elbée and Nick Ramsey for stimulating discussions, as well as the anonymous referee for their careful reading of the paper and helpful revisions. Conant was partially supported by NSF grant DMS-2204787.

References

REFERENCES

Adler, H., Explanation of independence, Ph.D. thesis, Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg, 2005.Google Scholar
Adler, H., Around pregeometric theories, unpublished notes, 2007.Google Scholar
Adler, H., A geometric introduction to forking and thorn-forking . Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 9 (2009), no. 1, pp. 120.10.1142/S0219061309000811CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casanovas, E., Simple Theories and Hyperimaginaries, Lecture Notes in Logic, 39, Association for Symbolic Logic, Chicago, 2011.10.1017/CBO9781139003728CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cherlin, G., Shelah, S., and Shi, N., Universal graphs with forbidden subgraphs and algebraic closure , Advances in Applied Mathematics, vol. 22 (1999), no. 4, pp. 454491.10.1006/aama.1998.0641CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chernikov, A. and Kaplan, I., Forking and dividing in $\mathrm{NTP}_2$ theories, this Journal, vol. 77 (2012), no. 1, pp. 1–20.2012 Google Scholar
Conant, G., An axiomatic approach to free amalgamation, this Journal, vol. 82 (2017), no. 2, pp. 648–671.2017 Google Scholar
Conant, G., Forking and dividing in Henson graphs . Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 58 (2017), no. 4, pp. 555566.10.1215/00294527-2017-0016CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conant, G. and Hanson, J., Separation for isometric group actions and hyperimaginary independence . Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 259 (2022), no. 1, pp. 97109.10.4064/fm167-2-2022CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conant, G. and Kruckman, A., Independence in generic incidence structures, this Journal, vol. 84 (2019), no. 2, pp. 750–780.2019 Google Scholar
d’Elbée, C., Generic expansions by a reduct . Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 21 (2021), no. 3, Article no. 2150016, 44 pp.10.1142/S0219061321500161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
d’Elbée, C., Forking, imaginaries, and other features of $\mathrm{ACFG}$ , this Journal, vol. 86 (2021), no. 2, pp. 669–700.2021 Google Scholar
d’Elbée, C., Axiomatic theory of independence relations in model theory, preprint, 2023, arXiv:2308.07064.Google Scholar
d’Elbée, C., Note on a bomb dropped by Mr Conant and Mr Kruckman, and its consequences for the theory ACFG, preprint, 2023, arXiv:2311.02208.Google Scholar
Dobrowolski, J., Kim, B., and Ramsey, N., Independence over arbitrary sets in $NSO{P}_1$ theories . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 173 (2022), no. 2, Article no. 103058, 20 pp.Google Scholar
Hodges, W., Model Theory, Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, 42, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993.10.1017/CBO9780511551574CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, I. and Ramsey, N., On Kim-independence . Journal of the European Mathematical Society (JEMS), vol. 22 (2020), no. 5, pp. 14231474.10.4171/jems/948CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kruckman, A., How to show that an algebraic formula divides?, Mathematics Stack Exchange, 2019, https://math.stackexchange.com/q/3349094 (version: 2019-09-10).Google Scholar
Kruckman, A., Independence and algebraic closure for stable theories, Mathematics Stack Exchange, 2021, https://math.stackexchange.com/q/4120234 (version: 2021-08-02).Google Scholar
Kruckman, A. and Ramsey, N., Generic expansion and Skolemization in $\mathrm{NSOP}_1$ theories . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 169 (2018), no. 8, pp. 755774.10.1016/j.apal.2018.04.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mutchnik, S., Conant-independence and generalized free amalgamation, preprint, 2022, arXiv:2210.07527.Google Scholar
Patel, R., A family of countably universal graphs without SOP ${}_4$ , preprint, 2006.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Toward classifying unstable theories . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 80 (1996), no. 3, pp. 229255.10.1016/0168-0072(95)00066-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tent, K. and Ziegler, M., A Course in Model Theory, Lecture Notes in Logic, 40, Association for Symbolic Logic, La Jolla, 2012.10.1017/CBO9781139015417CrossRefGoogle Scholar