Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T21:09:51.247Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Persistence and Herbrand expansions1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Joseph S. Wholey*
Affiliation:
Institute for Defense Analyses

Extract

Following Robinson [3], we say that a first-order sentence S is persistent with respect to a set of sentences K if, whenever S is true in a model M of K, then S is true in every extension of M that is also a model of K. Robinson proved in [3] that:

(T) In order that the sentence S be persistent with respect to the set K it is necessary and sufficient that there be some existential sentence Y such that the sentence S↔Y is deducible from K.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1964

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This note is based on part of Chapter 5 of the author's Harvard University dissertation. The author thanks Professors Michael Rabin and Burton Dreben for help in putting the results in their present form.

References

Referentes

[1]Davis, M. and Putnam, H., A computing procedure for quantification theory, Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery, vol. 7 (1960), pp. 201215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Quine, W. V., Interpretations of sets of conditions, this Journal, vol. 19 (1954), pp. 97102.Google Scholar
[3]Robinson, A., Note on a problem of L. Henkin, this Journal, vol. 21 (1956), pp. 3335.Google Scholar
[4]Robinson, A., Complete Theories, Amsterdam (North-Holland), 1956.Google Scholar
[5]Tarski, A. and Vaught, R. L., Arithmetical extensions of relational systems, Composltio Mathematica, vol. 13 (1957), pp. 81102.Google Scholar