Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T16:19:49.980Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

MAKER–BREAKER GAMES ON $ K_{\omega _1}$ AND $K_{\omega ,\omega _1}$

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 June 2022

NATHAN BOWLER
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITÄT HAMBURG BUNDESSTRASSE 55 (GEOMATIKUM) 20146 HAMBURG, GERMANY E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected]
FLORIAN GUT*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITÄT HAMBURG BUNDESSTRASSE 55 (GEOMATIKUM) 20146 HAMBURG, GERMANY E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected]
ATTILA JOÓ
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITÄT HAMBURG BUNDESSTRASSE 55 (GEOMATIKUM) 20146 HAMBURG, GERMANY and LOGIC, SET THEORY AND TOPOLOGY DEPARTMENT ALFRÉD RÉNYI INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS 13-15 REÁLTANODA STREET BUDAPEST, HUNGARY E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected]
MAX PITZ
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITÄT HAMBURG BUNDESSTRASSE 55 (GEOMATIKUM) 20146 HAMBURG, GERMANY E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We investigate Maker–Breaker games on graphs of size $\aleph _1$ in which Maker’s goal is to build a copy of the host graph. We establish a firm dependence of the outcome of the game on the axiomatic framework. Relating to this, we prove that there is a winning strategy for Maker in the $K_{\omega ,\omega _1}$ -game under ZFC+MA+ $\neg $ CH and a winning strategy for Breaker under ZFC+CH. We prove a similar result for the $K_{\omega _1}$ -game. Here, Maker has a winning strategy under ZF+DC+AD, while Breaker has one under ZFC+CH again.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

Games on graphs are a very natural concept and so it is no wonder that this field has emerged jointly with graph theory as a whole. For finite boards one often considers strong games, i.e., where two players interchangeably colour edges of a finite graph G with the aim to be the first player to have some previously agreed upon graph contained as a subgraph in the graph induced by their respective coloured edges. Another important kind of games is the so-called “Maker–Breaker games.” A typical setup for such games on (potentially infinite) graphs is the following: at each turn, Maker claims an edge of $ G $ (not previously claimed by either player) after which Breaker claims an unclaimed edge. There is either a fixed number of turns or they play until the whole edge set is distributed. The set of winning sets of Maker is public knowledge and usually has some combinatorial description. Classical games of this type are for example the Shannon switching game, in which Maker’s goal is to connect two vertices by a path (see [Reference Lehman11]), and the game where Maker’s goal is to build a spanning tree (see [Reference Chvátal and Erdős4]) or more generally a base of a matroid (see [Reference Bednarska and Pikhurko2]).

For recent results about Maker–Breaker games on infinite graphs we refer to [Reference Bowler, Emde and Gut3, Reference Nicholas Day and Falgas-Ravry12]. Some games (like the base-exchange game in [Reference Aharoni and Pouzet1]) can be phrased more naturally in the language of infinite matroids. It is worth mentioning that Maker–Breaker games have been investigated in an even more abstract settings as well (see [Reference Csirmaz and Nagy5]).

Let G and G, be graphs. Then we denote by $\mathfrak{MB}(G, H) $ the MakerBreaker game where G (more precisely the set of edges) is the board, there are turns (indexed by ordinals) each of which begins with Maker claiming a previously unclaimed edge, after which Breaker does likewise. The game terminates when all the edges are claimed and Maker wins if and only if at the end of the game the subgraph $ G_M $ of $ G $ induced by the edges claimed by Maker contains a subgraph isomorphic to $ H $ . Let us recall that a graph $ G $ is an ordered pair $ (V,E) $ with $ E\subseteq [V]^{2} $ where $ V $ is called the vertex set and $ E $ is the edge set of $ G $ . The complete graph on $ \kappa $ is $ K_\kappa :=(\kappa , [\kappa ]^{2}) $ . The complete bipartite graph with vertex classes of size $ \lambda $ and $ \kappa $ is denoted by $ K_{\lambda ,\kappa } $ , its vertex set is $ (\lambda \times \{ 0 \})\cup (\kappa \times \{ 1 \}) $ , and its edge set is $ \{ (\alpha ,0), (\beta , 1):\ \alpha <\lambda , \beta <\kappa \} $ . Note that the vertex sets of these graphs are already well-ordered, and so we generally do not need to invoke the axiom of choice. It was shown that in the game $ \mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega }, K_{\omega }) $ Maker has a winning strategy (see [Reference Bowler, Emde and Gut3]). In this note we analyse similar games on uncountable graphs.

Note that each outcome of the game defines a 2-colouring of $E(G)$ . This suggests a possible connection to Ramsey type problems, although in the current context the colourings in question are not arbitrary but are produced by players with particular goals in mind. There are colourings of the edges of a $K_{\omega _1}$ with two colours without any monochromatic $K_{\omega _1}$ in ZFC (see [Reference Sierpiński13]), but if instead of the axiom of choice one assumes DC+AD, then there is always a monochromatic $K_{\omega _1}$ because $\omega _1$ becomes measurable (see [Reference Kanamori9, Theorem 28.2]) and hence weakly compactFootnote 1 .

The existence of a monochromatic $K_{\omega ,\omega _1}$ when colouring the edges of a $K_{\omega ,\omega _1}$ with two colours is even more dependent on the set-theoretic framework. While there is a colouring without a monochromatic copy in ZFC+CH, there is no such colouring in ZFC+ $\omega _1<\mathfrak {p} $ . Since we could not find these particular statements formulated anywhere in the literature on infinite Ramsey theory, for the sake of completeness we include them here as Corollaries 2.2 and 3.3.

These Ramsey-type results compare well to the corresponding results about the existence of a winning strategy for either player. Our main results are as follows:

Theorem 1.1. It is independent of ZFC if Breaker has a winning strategy in the game $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega , \omega _1}, K_{\omega ,\omega _1}) $ . He has one under ZFC+GCH,Footnote 2 while Maker has one under ZFC $+\omega _1<\mathfrak {p}$ .

Theorem 1.2. It is independent of ZFC if every $ 2 $ -colouring of the edges of $ K_{\omega , \omega _1} $ admits a monochromatic copy of $ K_{\omega , \omega _1} $ . It is true in ZFC $+\omega _1<\mathfrak {p} $ but fails under ZFC+CH.

Theorem 1.3. Assuming the consistency of AD, it is independent of ZF+DC if Breaker has winning strategies in the games $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _n}, K_{\omega _n}) $ for $ n\in \{ 1,2 \} $ . He has such winning strategies under ZFC+GCH, while Maker has winning strategies in these games under ZF+DC+AD.

Let $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\kappa }, K_{\mathsf {club}}) $ be the game in which Maker’s goal is to build a “ $K_{\mathsf {club}}$ ,” i.e., a complete graph whose vertex set is a closed unbounded subset of $ \kappa $ .

Theorem 1.4. Assuming the consistency of AD, it is independent of ZF+DC if Breaker has a winning strategy in the game $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _1}, K_{\mathsf {club}}) $ .

Our results raise the following natural questions:

Question 1.5. Is it consistent with ZFC that neither Maker nor Breaker has a winning strategy in the game $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega , \omega _1}, K_{\omega ,\omega _1}) $ ?

Question 1.6. Does Breaker have a winning strategy in $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _1}, K_{\omega _1})$ under ZFC?

Question 1.7. Does Maker have a winning strategy in $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _1}, K_{\mathsf {club}}) $ under ZF+DC+AD?

2 The winning strategies of Breaker under GCH

Proposition 2.1 (ZFC+GCH).

For every infinite cardinal $ \kappa $ , Breaker has a winning strategy in the game $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\kappa ^{+}}, K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}}) $ .

Proof Let us assume that $ K_{\kappa ^{+}} $ is represented as the complete graph on the vertex set $\kappa ^+$ . Working under GCH, we fix an enumeration $ \{ A_\alpha : \alpha <\kappa ^{+} \} $ of $ [\kappa ^{+}]^{\kappa } $ and for each $\alpha <\kappa ^{+}$ , we pick a surjective function $ f_\alpha : \kappa \rightarrow \{ A_\beta : \beta \leq \alpha \}$ ). Whenever Maker plays an edge $ \{ \beta , \alpha \} $ with $ \beta < \alpha $ and there is a $ \gamma <\kappa $ such that this is the $(\gamma +1) $ st downwards edge from $ \alpha $ she claims, Breaker chooses the smallest $\delta \in f_\alpha (\gamma ) $ for which $ \{ \delta , \alpha \} $ is available, and plays $ \{ \delta , \alpha \} $ if such a $ \delta $ exists—otherwise he plays arbitrarily.

Suppose for a contradiction that Maker manages to build a $ K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}} $ (despite Breaker playing as above) and let $ A $ be its smaller and $ B $ its bigger vertex class. Then there is an $ \alpha <\kappa ^{+} $ with $A_{\alpha }=A$ . Fix a $ \beta \in B $ with $ \beta> \max \{\alpha , \sup A\} $ and let $ \gamma < \kappa $ with $ f_\beta (\gamma )=A $ . At the turn when Maker claims a downwards edge from $ \beta $ for the $ (\gamma +1) $ st time, there are still $ \kappa $ many $ \delta \in A $ for which $ \{ \delta , \beta \} $ is available, and thus Breaker’s next play is $ \{ \delta , \beta \} $ for the smallest such $ \delta $ . This contradicts $ \{ \delta , \beta \}\in E(G_M) $ .

The corresponding negative Ramsey-result can be proved in a similar manner:

Corollary 2.2 (ZFC+GCH).

For every infinite cardinal $ \kappa $ , there exists a $ 2 $ -colouring of the edge set of $ K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}} $ without a monochromatic copy of $ K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}} $ .

Proof Let $ \{ v_\alpha : \alpha <\kappa ^{+} \} $ be an enumeration of the larger vertex class and let $ \{ A_\alpha : \alpha <\kappa ^{+} \} $ be an enumeration of $ [\kappa ^{+}]^{\kappa } $ . For each $ \alpha <\kappa ^{+} $ , we colour the edges incident with $ v_\alpha $ in such a way that for every $ \beta \leq \alpha $ both colours appear among the edges between $ v_\alpha $ and $ A_\beta $ . This clearly ensures that no set $ A $ can be the smaller vertex class of a monochromatic copy of $ K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}} $ and therefore no such a monochromatic copy exists.

Observation 2.3. If Breaker has a winning strategy in $ \mathfrak {MB}(G,H) $ , then he also has one in every game $ \mathfrak {MB}(G',H') $ where $ G' $ is a subgraph of $ G $ and $ H' $ is a supergraph of $ H $ .

Since $ K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}} $ is a subgraph of $ K_{\kappa ^{+}} $ , Observation 2.3 guarantees that Proposition 2.1 has the following consequences:

Corollary 2.4 (ZFC+GCH).

For every infinite cardinal $ \kappa $ , Breaker has a winning strategy in the following games:

  1. (1) $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}}, K_{\kappa , \kappa ^{+}}) $ ,

  2. (2) $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\kappa ^{+}}, K_{\kappa ^{+}}) $ ,

  3. (3) $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\kappa ^{+}}, K_{\mathsf {club}}). $

3 Winning strategies for Maker

During the course of play in $\mathfrak {MB}(G,H)$ we will refer to a vertex as fresh if no edge incident with that vertex has been claimed yet by either player.

3.1 A winning strategy for Maker in $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega , \omega _1}, K_{\omega , \omega _1})$

A set $\mathcal {F}$ of sets has the strong finite intersection property if the intersection of any finitely many elements of $\mathcal {F}$ is infinite. Given two sets X and Y, write $X \subseteq ^*Y$ if $X \setminus Y$ is finite. A pseudo-intersection for a set $\mathcal {F}$ of sets is a set P with $P \subseteq ^* F$ for all $F \in \mathcal {F}$ . The cardinal $\mathfrak {p}$ is the minimum cardinality of a set $\mathcal {F}$ of subsets of $\omega $ that has the strong finite intersection property but does not admit an infinite pseudo-intersection. Clearly $\aleph _0<\mathfrak {p} \leq 2^{\aleph _0}$ and it is known that $ \omega _1<\mathfrak {p} $ is consistent relative to ZFC (see [Reference Kunen10, Lemma III.3.22 on p. 176]).

Proposition 3.1. Maker has a winning strategy in $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega , \omega _1}, K_{\omega , \omega _1}) $ if $ \omega _1<\mathfrak {p} $ .

Proof Let $ U$ and $ V $ be the two sides of the bipartite graph $ K_{\omega , \omega _1} $ , where $ \left |U\right |=\omega $ and $ \left |V\right |=\omega _1 $ . We denote the subgraph of $ G $ induced by the edges Maker claimed before turn $ \alpha $ by $ G^{\alpha }_M $ and we write $ N_{G^{\alpha }_{M}}(v) $ for the set of the neighbours of v in this graph.

During the game Maker will choose a sequence $\langle v_{\alpha } \colon \alpha < \kappa \rangle \langle v_{\alpha } \colon \alpha < \omega _1 \rangle $ of distinct vertices from V and a sequence $\langle N_{\alpha } \colon \alpha < \kappa \rangle $ of subsets of U in such a way as to ensure that for any $\alpha < \kappa $ and a sequence $\langle N_{\alpha } \colon \alpha < \omega _1\rangle $ of subsets of U in such a way as to ensure that for any $\alpha < \omega _1$

  1. (1) $N_{\alpha } \subseteq N_{G_M}^{\omega \cdot (\alpha + 1)}(v_{\alpha })$ ,

  2. (2) the set $\{N_{\beta } \colon \beta \leq \alpha \}$ has the strong finite intersection property.

Assume that turn $ \alpha \cdot \omega $ has just begun for some $\alpha <\omega _1$ and that Maker has constructed suitable $v_{\beta }$ and $N_{\beta }$ for all $\beta < \alpha $ . She picks $ v_{\alpha }$ to be any fresh vertex in V. Using (2) for all $\beta < \alpha $ , we know that the set $\{N_{\beta } \colon \beta < \alpha \}$ has the strong finite intersection property. Let $P_\alpha $ be an infinite pseudo-intersection of this family. In each of the next $ \omega $ turns, Maker claims an edge $ \{ u, v_\alpha \} $ with $ u\in P_\alpha $ . Let $N_{\alpha }$ be the set of all the endpoints $u \in U$ of these edges. It is easy to check that this construction satisfies (1) and (2) for $\alpha $ .

At the end of the game $ \{N_{\alpha } \colon \alpha <\omega _1 \} $ has the strong finite intersection property and hence (by the assumption $ \omega _1<\mathfrak {p} $ ) admits an infinite pseudo-intersection $ P $ . By the definition of $ P $ , for each $ \alpha <\omega _1 $ , the set $ P\setminus N_\alpha $ is finite. Then there exists an uncountable $ O\subseteq \omega _1 $ and a finite $ F\subseteq P $ such that $ P\setminus N_\alpha =F $ for every $ \alpha \in O $ . Finally, $ (P\setminus F)\cup \{ v_\alpha : \alpha \in O \} $ induces a copy of $ K_{\omega , \omega _1} $ , all of whose edges have been claimed by Maker.

Remark 3.2. The same proof shows that Maker has a winning strategy in $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega , \kappa }, K_{\omega , \kappa }) $ for every $\kappa <\mathfrak {p}$ with $ \mathsf {cf}(\kappa )>\aleph _0 $ .

The proof of Proposition 3.1 leads to the following positive Ramsey result:

Corollary 3.3. If $ \omega _1<\mathfrak {p} $ , then any $ 2 $ -colouring of the edges of $ K_{\omega , \omega _1} $ admits a monochromatic copy of $ K_{\omega , \omega _1} $ .

Proof Call the colours red and blue, and call the countable and uncountable sides of the original graph U and V respectively. We pick a free ultrafilter $ \mathcal {U} $ on $ U $ . Then for each $ v\in V $ either the set $ N_r(v) $ of the red neighbours of $ v $ is in $ \mathcal {U} $ or the set $N_b(v)$ of the blue neighbours. We may assume that there is an uncountable $ V'\subseteq V $ such that $ N_r(v)\in \mathcal {U} $ for each $ v\in V' $ . Since $ \mathcal {U} $ is a free ultrafilter, the family $ \{ N_r(v): v\in V' \} $ has the strong finite intersection property and therefore (by $ \omega _1<\mathfrak {p} $ ) admits an infinite pseudo-intersection $ P $ . This means that for every $ v\in V' $ the set $ P\setminus N_r(v) $ is finite. Then there exists an uncountable $ V"\subseteq V' $ and finite $ F\subseteq P $ such that $ P\setminus N_r(v)=F $ for each $ v\in V" $ and hence $ (P\setminus F)\cup V" $ induces a red copy of $ K_{\omega , \omega _1} $ .

Question 3.4. Is it consistent with ZFC $+\aleph _\omega <2^{\aleph _0}$ that Maker has a winning strategy in the game $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega , \omega _\omega }, K_{\omega , \omega _\omega }) $ ?

Theorem 1.1 is implied by the case $ \kappa =\omega $ of Corollary 2.4/(1) together with Proposition 3.1. Similarly, Theorem 1.2 follows from Corollaries 2.2 and 3.3.

3.2 A winning strategy for Maker in $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _1}, K_{\omega _1})$ and $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _2}, K_{\omega _2})$

Proposition 3.5 (ZF).

If either $ \kappa $ is measurable or $ \kappa =\omega $ , then Maker has a winning strategy in the game $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\kappa }, K_{\kappa }) $ .

Proof A sub-binary Hausdorff tree is a set theoretic tree $ T $ in which each vertex has at most two children and no two vertices at any limit level have the same set of predecessors.

During the game Maker builds a sequence $ \left \langle T_\alpha : \alpha \leq \kappa \right \rangle $ of sub-binary Hausdorff trees with root $ 0 $ and $ T_\alpha \subseteq \kappa $ of height at most $1+\alpha $ such that:

  1. (a)
    1. (i) $ T_0=\{ 0 \} $ ,

    2. (ii) $ T_{\alpha +1} $ is obtained from $ T_\alpha $ by inserting a new maximal element,

    3. (iii) $ T_\alpha =\bigcup _{\beta <\alpha }T_\beta $ if $ \alpha $ is a limit ordinal,

  2. (b) for every distinct $ <_{T_\alpha } $ -comparable $ u,v\in T_\alpha $ , the edge $ \{ u,v \} $ is claimed by Maker in the game.

Suppose that $ \alpha =\beta +1 $ and $ T_\beta $ is already defined. Maker picks the smallest ordinal $ v $ such that no edge incident with v is claimed and claims edge $ \{ 0, v \} $ . Then, for as long as she can, on each following turn she connects $ v $ to vertices in $ T_\beta $ in such a way that:

  1. (1) she maintains that the current neighbourhood of $ v $ in her graph is a downward closed chain in $ T_\beta $ ,

  2. (2) whenever she claims some $ \{ u,v \} $ , then Breaker has no edge between $ v $ and the subtree $ T_{\beta , u} $ of $ T_\beta $ rooted at $ u $ .

Note that, at any step at which v has a largest Maker-neighbour in $T_\beta $ and this neighbour has two children in $ T_\beta $ , she can proceed. Moreover, she can also proceed even if there is no such largest Maker-neighbour as long as there is some element of $T_{\beta }$ whose predecessors are precisely the Maker-neighbours of v in $T_{\beta }$ . Thus, if Maker is unable to continue this process with $ v $ , then either $ v $ has a largest Maker-neighbour in $ T_\beta $ which has at most one child or else there is no vertex in $T_{\beta }$ with precisely the Maker-neighbours of u as its predecessors. In either case we can define $ T_{\beta +1} $ by adding $ v $ to $ T_\beta $ with its current set of Maker-neighbours as its predecessors, and Maker starts a new phase with a new fresh vertex.

It is enough to show that there is a $ \kappa $ -branch $ B $ in $ T_\kappa $ , because then $ G_M[B] $ is a copy of $ K_{\kappa } $ by (b). Since $ \left |T_\kappa \right |=\kappa $ by (a), we can fix a $ \kappa $ -complete free ultrafilter $ \mathcal {U} $ on $ T_\kappa $ .

By transfinite recursion we build a $ \kappa $ -branch. Let $ v_0:=0 $ . Suppose that there is an $ \alpha <\kappa $ such that the $ <_{T_\kappa } $ -increasing sequence $ \left \langle v_\beta : \beta <\alpha \right \rangle $ is already defined and for each $ \beta <\alpha $ , $ T_{\kappa , v_\beta }\in \mathcal {U} $ . If $ \alpha $ is a limit ordinal, then since $\bigcap _{\beta <\alpha }T_{v_\beta }\in \mathcal {U} $ by the $ \kappa $ -completeness of $ \mathcal {U} $ , there is at least one vertex of T with all $v_{\beta }$ as predecessors. We define $ v_\alpha $ to be the unique minimal such vertex, so that $ T_{v_\alpha }=\bigcap _{\beta <\alpha }T_{v_\beta }\in \mathcal {U} $ . If $ \alpha =\beta +1 $ , then $ T_{\kappa , v_\beta }\in \mathcal {U} $ by assumption. Since $ T_\kappa $ is sub-binary, $ v_\beta $ has a unique child $ v $ satisfying $ T_{\kappa , v}\in \mathcal {U} $ and we let $ v_{\beta +1}:=v $ . The recursion is done and $\{ v_\alpha : \alpha <\kappa \} $ is clearly a $ \kappa $ -branch.

We remark that this strategy is quite flexible and deals also with a number of variants of the Maker–Breaker game. For example, if Breaker is allowed $k<\omega $ moves for every move that Maker picks, simply take a sub- $(k+1)$ -regular Hausdorff tree, in which every node has at most $k+1$ children. Furthermore, if in addition Breaker is allowed to go first in every turn, simply weaken the Hausdorff assumption to the requirement that at most $k+1$ vertices at a limit level have the same set of predecessors.

Since $ \omega _1 $ and $ \omega _2 $ are measurable cardinals under ZF+DC+AD [Reference Kanamori9, Theorems 28.2 and 28.6], the cases $ \kappa \in \{\omega , \omega _1 \} $ of Corollary 2.4/(2) and the cases $\kappa \in \{\omega _1, \omega _2\}$ of Proposition 3.5 together imply Theorem 1.3.

3.3 Breaker may lose the $\mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _1}, K_{\mathsf {club}})$ -game

Proposition 3.6. Under ZF+DC+AD, Breaker does not have a winning strategy in the game $ \mathfrak {MB}(K_{\omega _1}, K_{\mathsf {club}}) $ .

Proof First of all, the club filter on $ \omega _1 $ is a countably complete free ultrafilter under ZF+DC+AD (this is explicit in the proof of [Reference Kanamori9, Theorem 28.2]). Furthermore, it is normal [Reference Dorais and Hathaway6, Proposition 4.1]. Thus for any 2-colouring of $ [\omega _1]^{2} $ there exists a colour with a monochromatic $ K_{\mathsf {club}} $ (the standard proof of this for arbitrary normal ultrafilters uses only ZF, see [Reference Jech8, Theorem 10.22]). It follows that if Breaker successfully prevents Maker from building a $ K_{\mathsf {club}} $ , then he necessarily builds a $ K_{\mathsf {club}} $ himself.

Suppose for a contradiction that Breaker has a winning strategy. We shall show that Maker can “steal” this winning strategy. Indeed, Maker picks an arbitrary edge in turn $ 0 $ as well as in each limit turn while in successor turns she pretends to be Breaker and claims edges according to his winning strategy. This is a winning strategy for Maker, a contradiction.

Theorem 1.4 follows from the case $ \kappa =\omega $ of Corollary 2.4/(3) and Proposition 3.6.

Remark 3.7. The same strategy stealing argument shows that if $\kappa $ is a weakly compact cardinal, then Breaker does not have a winning strategy in the game $ \mathfrak {MB}(K_{\kappa }, K_{\kappa }) $ .

Remark 3.8. We did not really use the full power of AD, just some consequences that are weaker in the sense of consistency strength than AD itself. The axiom-system ZF+DC+“ $\omega _1$ is measurable” is equiconsistent with ZFC+“there exists a measurable cardinal” (see [Reference Jech7]). The club filter being an ultrafilter is a strictly stronger assumption; for more details see page 3 of [Reference Dorais and Hathaway6].

Acknowledgements

The authors are grateful to Stefan Geschke, Zoltán Vidnyánszky, and Daniel Hathaway for the insightful discussions about the Axiom of determinacy. The third author would like to thank the generous support of the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation and NKFIH OTKA-129211.

Footnotes

1 We write CH, GCH, DC, AD, and $ \mathfrak {p} $ for the continuum hypothesis, generalised continuum hypothesis, axiom of dependent choice, axiom of determinacy, and the pseudo-intersection number respectively.

2 A closer analysis shows that only CH is needed here, but we have chosen a simpler exposition over optimality of the results, since the independence is our main concern.

References

Aharoni, R. and Pouzet, M., Bases in infinite matroids . Journal of the London Mathematical Society , vol. 2 (1991), no. 3, 385392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bednarska, M. and Pikhurko, O., Biased positional games on matroids . European Journal of Combinatorics , vol. 26 (2005), no. 2, pp. 271285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowler, N., Emde, M., and Gut, F., Maker breaker games on an infinite board: Vertex colouring , 2020.Google Scholar
Chvátal, V. and Erdős, P., Biased positional games . Annals of Discrete Mathematics , vol. 2 (1978), pp. 221229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Csirmaz, L. and Nagy, Z. S., On a generalization of the game go-moku, II . Studia Scientiarum Mathematicarum Hungarica , vol. 14 (1979), pp. 461469.Google Scholar
Dorais, F. and Hathaway, D., Bounding 2D functions by products of 1D functions. Mathematical Logic Quarterly, vol. 68 (2022), no. 2, pp. 202212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, T., ω1 can be measurable . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 6 (1968), no. 4, pp. 363367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, T., Set Theory , Springer Monographs in Mathematics, vol. 14, Springer, Berlin, 2003.Google Scholar
Kanamori, A., The Higher Infinite: Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings . Springer, Berlin, 2008.Google Scholar
Kunen, K., Set Theory , Studies in Logic: Mathematical Logic and Foundations, vol. 34, College Publications, London, 2011.Google Scholar
Lehman, A., A solution of the Shannon switching game . Journal of the Society for Industrial and Applied Mathematics , vol. 12 (1964), no. 4, pp. 687725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nicholas Day, A. and Falgas-Ravry, V., Maker-breaker percolation games II: Escaping to infinity . Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B , vol. 151 (2021), pp. 482508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sierpiński, W., Sur un problème de la théorie des relations . Annali della Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa—Classe di Scienze , vol. 2 (1933), no. 3, pp. 285287 (in French).Google Scholar