Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T17:14:48.305Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

DENSITY-LIKE AND GENERALIZED DENSITY IDEALS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 November 2021

ADAM KWELA
Affiliation:
INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS FACULTY OF MATHEMATICS, PHYSICS AND INFORMATICS UNIVERSITY OF GDAŃSK UL. WITA STWOSZA 57, 80-308 GDAŃSK, POLANDE-mail:[email protected]
PAOLO LEONETTI
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF DECISION SCIENCES UNIVERSITÀ “LUIGI BOCCONI” VIA ROENTGEN 1, 20136MILAN, ITALYE-mail:[email protected]: https://sites.google.com/site/leonettipaolo/
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We show that there exist uncountably many (tall and nontall) pairwise nonisomorphic density-like ideals on $\omega $ which are not generalized density ideals. In addition, they are nonpathological. This answers a question posed by Borodulin-Nadzieja et al. in [this Journal, vol. 80 (2015), pp. 1268–1289]. Lastly, we provide sufficient conditions for a density-like ideal to be necessarily a generalized density ideal.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

An ideal $\mathcal {I}$ on the nonnegative integers $\omega $ is a family of subsets of $\omega $ closed under finite unions and subsets. Unless otherwise stated, we assume that $\mathcal {I}$ is admissible (i.e., it contains $\mathrm {Fin}:=[\omega ]^{<\omega }$ ) and proper (i.e., $\omega \notin \mathcal {I}$ ). An ideal $\mathcal {I}$ is tall if each infinite set $A\subseteq \omega $ contains an infinite subset in $\mathcal {I}$ . It is a P-ideal if it is $\sigma $ -directed modulo finite sets, i.e., for each sequence $(A_n)$ in $\mathcal {I}$ there is $A\in \mathcal {I}$ such that $A_n\setminus A$ is finite for all n. Ideals are regarded as subsets of $\{0,1\}^\omega $ with the Cantor-space topology, hence it is possible to speak about Borel, analytic ideals, etc. We refer to [Reference Hrušák11, Reference Uzcátegui Aylwin27] for recent surveys on ideals and associated filters.

A lower semicontinuous submeasure (lscsm) $\varphi :\mathcal {P}(\omega ) \to [0,\infty ]$ is a subadditive monotone function such that $\varphi (\emptyset )=0$ , $\varphi (\{n\})<\infty $ for all $n\in \omega $ , and $\varphi (A)=\lim _n \varphi (A\cap n)$ for all $A\subseteq \omega $ (here, as usual, each n is identified with $\{0,1,\ldots ,n-1\}$ ). Denote by $\mathrm {supp}(\varphi ):=\{n \in \omega : \varphi (\{n\})\neq 0\}$ its support. A lscsm with finite support will be typically denoted by $\mu $ . It is folklore that the pointwise supremum of lscsms is a lscsm. For each lscsm $\varphi $ , we associate its exhaustive ideal

$$ \begin{align*} {\mathrm{Exh}}(\varphi):=\left\{A\subseteq \omega: \|A\|_\varphi=0\right\}, \end{align*} $$

where $\|A\|_\varphi :=\inf _{F \in \mathrm {Fin}} \varphi (A\setminus F)$ . A classical result of Solecki states that a (not necessarily proper) ideal $\mathcal {I}$ is an analytic P-ideal if and only if $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ for some lscsm $\varphi $ such that $\varphi (\omega )<\infty $ , see e.g., [Reference Farah6, Section 1.2] for a textbook exposition. In particular, each analytic P-ideal is $F_{\sigma \delta }$ . Every lscsm $\varphi $ defines a metric $d_\varphi $ on $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ given by $d_\varphi (A,B)=\varphi (A\triangle B)$ for all $A,B \in \mathcal {I}$ . The topology induced on $\mathcal {I}$ is Polish and does not depend on the choice of $\varphi $ , see [Reference Solecki22].

The aim of this work is to study the relationship between two families of analytic P-ideals defined below.

Definition 1.1. An ideal $\mathcal {I}$ is called a generalized density ideal if there exists a sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of lscsms with finite pairwise disjoint supports such that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ , where $\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }}:=\sup _n \mu _n$ .

Note that if $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ is a sequence of lscsms with finite pairwise disjoint supports, then

$$ \begin{align*}\mathrm{Exh}\left(\varphi_{\boldsymbol{\mu}}\right)=\mathrm{Exh}\left(\limsup_{n\to \infty}\mu_n\right). \end{align*} $$

Generalized density ideals have been introduced by Farah in [Reference Farah7, Section 2.10], see also [Reference Farah9], and have been used in different contexts, see e.g., [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Reference Filipów, Mrożek, Recław and Szuca10, Reference Leonetti16]. We remark that Farah’s original definition assumed that $\{\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n): n \in \omega \}$ is a partition of $\omega $ into finite intervals; however, we will show in Proposition 2.1 that this is equivalent to Definition 1.1. The family of generalized density ideals is very rich. Indeed, if each $\mu _n$ is a measure then $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ is a density ideal, as defined in [Reference Farah6, Section 1.13], cf. also [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Proposition 6.3]. In particular, it includes $\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}$ , the ideal of density zero sets

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{Z}:=\left\{A\subseteq \omega: \lim_{n\to \infty}\frac{|A\cap n|}{n}=0\right\}, \end{align*} $$

and all the Erdős–Ulam ideals introduced by Just and Krawczyk in [Reference Just and Krawczyk12], that is, ideals of the type $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{f})$ where $f: \omega \to (0,\infty )$ is a function such that $\sum _{n}f(n)=\infty $ , $f(n)=o\left (\sum _{i\le n}f(i)\right )$ as $n\to \infty $ , and $\varphi _f: \mathcal {P}(\omega ) \to (0,\infty )$ is the submeasure defined by

$$ \begin{align*} \forall A\subseteq \omega,\quad \varphi_f(A)=\sup_{n \in \omega} \frac{\sum_{i\le n,\, i \in A}f(i)}{\sum_{i\le n}f(i)}, \end{align*} $$

see [Reference Farah6, pp. 42–43]. In addition, this family contains the ideals associated with suitable modifications of the natural asymptotic density, the so-called simple density ideals, see [Reference Balcerzak, Das, Filipczak and Swaczyna2, Reference Kwela, Popławski, Swaczyna and Tryba15] and Section 3. Lastly, a large class of generalized density ideals has been defined by Louveau and Veličković in [Reference Louveau and Veličković17, Reference Louveau and Veličković18], cf. also [Reference Farah7, Section 2.11].

Definition 1.2. An ideal $\mathcal {I}$ is said to be density-like if $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ for a density-like lscsm $\varphi $ , that is, a lscsm such that for all $\varepsilon>0$ there exists $\delta>0$ for which, if $(F_n) \in \mathrm {Fin}^\omega $ is a sequence of finite pairwise disjoint sets with $\varphi (F_n)<\delta $ for all n, then $\varphi (\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i) < \varepsilon $ for some infinite $I\subseteq \omega $ .

The class of density-like ideals played a role in [Reference Mátrai19, Reference Solecki and Todorcevic25]. The main result of [Reference Solecki and Todorcevic25] states that the ideal $\mathrm {NWD}$ of all closed nowhere dense subsets of $2^\omega $ is not Tukey reducible to any density-like ideal $\mathcal {I}$ (that is, there is no function $f:\mathrm {NWD}\to \mathcal {I}$ such that for each $A\in \mathcal {I}$ there exists $B\in \mathrm {NWD}$ for which $f(X)\subseteq A$ implies $X\subseteq B$ , i.e., preimages of bounded sets are bounded). In particular, this works for $\mathcal {Z}$ (since it is a density-like ideal), thus answering old questions of Isbell from 1972 and Fremlin from 1991.

It is known that if $\varphi $ is density-like and $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )=\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ , for some lscsm $\psi $ , then $\psi $ is density-like too. In addition, tall $F_\sigma $ P-ideals are not density-like, see [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Fact 5.1], and there exists a nontall $F_\sigma $ P-ideal which is not density-like, see [Reference Mátrai19].

On the one hand, every generalized density ideal $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ is a density-like ideal (indeed, $\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }}$ is a density-like lscsm). On the other hand, the converse has been asked in [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Question 5.11]:

Question 1. Is there a density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal?

This question is closely connected to the notion of representability of ideals in Polish Abelian groups and in Banach spaces. Following [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5], we say that an ideal $\mathcal {I}$ on $\omega $ is representable in a Polish Abelian group X if there is a function $f:\omega \to X$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle A\in\mathcal{I}\ \Longleftrightarrow\ \sum_{n\in A}f(n)\text{ is unconditionally convergent in }X. \end{align*} $$

By [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Theorems 4.1 and 4.4], an ideal is representable in some Polish Abelian group if and only if it is an analytic P-ideal, and it is representable in some Banach space if and only if it is a nonpathological analytic P-ideal (cf. Remark 3.3). Moreover, for instance, it is known that an ideal is representable in $\mathbb {R}^\omega $ if and only if it is an intersection of countably many summable ideals [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Example 3.8] (i.e., ideals of the form $\mathcal {I}_f:=\left \{A\subseteq \omega :\ \sum _{n\in A}f(n)<\infty \right \}$ for some $f:\omega \to [0,\infty )$ such that $\sum _{n}f(n)=\infty $ ); for more on this notion see [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5]. It is worth mentioning that Borodulin-Nadzieja and Farkas, using representability of ideals in Banach spaces, constructed a new example of a Banach space [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja and Farkas4, Example 5.9], and strengthened Mazur’s Lemma [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja and Farkas4, Corollary 7.6], which is a basic tool in Banach space theory (they were able to specify the form of the convex combination in Mazur’s Lemma). This suggests that studying the interplay between representability and theory of analytic P-ideals may have some relevant yet unexploited potential for the study of the geometry of Banach spaces.

Question 1 is motivated by the problem of characterizing ideals which are representable in the Banach space $c_0$ [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Question 5.10]. It is known that a tall $F_\sigma $ P-ideal is representable in $c_0$ if and only if it is a summable ideal [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Theorem 5.7] and that all nonpathological generalized density ideals are representable in $c_0$ [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Example 4.2].

The motivation of this work is to shed some light on [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Question 5.10] by providing a large class of density-like ideals which are not generalized density ideals. In particular, we give a positive answer to Question 1.

Theorem 1.3. There exists a density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal.

More precisely, our main contributions are:

  1. (i) There exist uncountably many nonpathological, nontall, and pairwise nonisomorphic density-like ideals which are not generalized density ideals, see Theorem 3.7.

  2. (ii) There exist uncountably many nonpathological, tall, and pairwise nonisomorphic density-like ideals which are not generalized density ideals, see Theorem 4.24.

  3. (iii) A characterization of generalized density ideals which is reminiscent of the definition of density-like ideals, see Theorem 5.3.

2 Preliminaries

Given (not necessarily proper or admissible) ideals $\mathcal {I}, \mathcal {J}$ on $\omega $ , we let their disjoint sum and Fubini product be

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{I} \oplus \mathcal{J}:=\left\{B\subseteq 2\times\omega: B_{(0)} \in \mathcal{I},B_{(1)} \in \mathcal{J} \right\}, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{I} \times \mathcal{J}:=\left\{B\subseteq \omega^2: \{m \in \omega: B_{(m)}\notin \mathcal{J}\} \in \mathcal{I} \right\}, \end{align*} $$

where $B_{(m)}:=\{k \in \omega : (m,k) \in B\}$ . Then $\mathcal {I}\times \mathcal {J}$ is an ideal on $\omega ^2$ . We identify ideals on $\omega ^2$ with ideals on $\omega $ through the bijection $h: \omega ^2 \to \omega $ defined by

(1) $$ \begin{align} \forall (x,y) \in \omega^2,\quad h(x,y):=2^{x}(2y+1)-1. \end{align} $$

To ease the notation, we define the families $\mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ , $\mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}}$ , and $\mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {int}}$ of sequences of nonempty finite sets which are, respectively, pairwise disjoint, increasing, and increasing intervals:

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \mathcal{F}_{\mathrm{disj}}:=&\{(F_n) \in (\mathrm{Fin}\setminus \{\emptyset\})^\omega: \forall \{i,j\} \in [\omega]^2, F_i \cap F_j=\emptyset\},\\ \mathcal{F}_{\mathrm{incr}}:=&\{(F_n) \in \mathcal{F}_{\mathrm{disj}}: \forall n \in \omega, \max F_n+1\le \min F_{n+1}\},\\ \mathcal{F}_{\mathrm{int}}:=&\{(F_n) \in \mathcal{F}_{\mathrm{incr}}: \forall n \in \omega, F_n \text{ is an interval}\}. \end{split} \end{align*} $$

In particular, $\mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {int}}\subseteq \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}}\subseteq \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ .

We start with some characterizations of generalized density ideals, cf. also Proposition 2.3 and Theorem 5.3.

Proposition 2.1. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be an ideal. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (G1) $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ for a sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of lscsms with $(\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {int}}$ ;

  2. (G2) $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ for a sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of lscsms with $(\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}}$ ;

  3. (G3) $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ for a sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of lscsms with $(\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ (that is, $\mathcal {I}$ is a generalized density ideal); and

  4. (G4) $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ for a sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of bounded lscsms such that

    $$ \begin{align*} \forall k \in \omega,\quad \{n \in \omega: k \in \mathrm{supp}(\mu_n)\} \in \mathrm{Fin}{.} \end{align*} $$

Proof. It is clear that (G1) $\implies $ (G2) $\implies $ (G3) $\implies $ (G4).

(G4) $\implies $ (G3) See [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Proposition 5.4].

(G3) $\implies $ (G1) Suppose that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ for some sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of lscsms such that $(S_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ , where $S_n:=\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)$ for each n. Note that we can assume without loss of generality that $S:=\bigcup _n S_n=\omega $ . Indeed, in the opposite, if $S^c$ is finite then it is sufficient to replace $\mu _0(A)$ with $\mu _0(A)+|A\cap S^c|$ for all $A\subseteq \omega $ . Otherwise, let $(x_n)$ be the infinite increasing enumeration of $S^c$ and replace every $\mu _n(A)$ with $\mu _n(A)+\frac {1}{n}|A\cap \{x_n\}|$ . This is possible, considering that

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle \mathcal{I}=\mathrm{Exh}(\varphi_{\boldsymbol{\mu}})=\mathrm{Exh}(\limsup_{n}\mu_n). \end{align*} $$

At this point, let $(T_n)\in \mathrm {Fin}^\omega $ be the sequence defined recursively as it follows: set $T_0:=[0,\max S_0]$ and, for each $n\in \omega $ , set

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle T_{n+1}:=\left(\max \bigcup_{i\le n}T_i,\, \max\left(S_{n+1}\cup \bigcup \{S_k: \min S_k \le \max \bigcup_{i\le n}T_i\}\right)\right]. \end{align*} $$

Observe that $(T_n)$ is a sequence of (possibly empty) pairwise disjoint finite intervals such that $\bigcup _{n}T_n=\omega $ . Moreover, for each $n \in \omega $ there exists $j=j(n)\in \omega $ with $S_n\subseteq T_{j(n)}\cup T_{j(n)+1}$ : indeed, if $j(n)$ is the minimal integer such that $S_n\cap T_{j(n)}\neq \emptyset $ (so that $T_{j(n)}\neq \emptyset $ and $\min S_n \le \max T_{j(n)}$ ), then

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \max(T_{j(n)+1})\geq\max\left(\bigcup\{S_k: \min S_k \le \max \bigcup_{i\le j(n)}T_i\}\right)\geq\max(S_n). \end{align*} $$

Let $(V_n)$ be the biggest subsequence of $(T_n)$ with nonempty elements, so that $(V_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {int}}$ , and define the sequence $\boldsymbol {\nu }=(\nu _n)$ of lscsms by

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle \forall n \in \omega, \forall A\subseteq \omega, \quad \nu_n(A):=\sup_k \mu_k(A \cap V_n). \end{align*} $$

Note that $\nu _n(A)=\sup _{k\geq n}\mu _k(A\cap V_n)$ , since $S_k\cap V_n=\emptyset $ whenever $k<n$ (indeed $S_k\subseteq \bigcup _{n\le k} T_n\subseteq \bigcup _{n\le k}V_n$ for all $k \in \omega $ ). Moreover, it follows by construction that $\text {supp}(\nu _n)=V_n$ for each $n \in \omega $ , hence it is sufficient to show that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\nu }})$ .

On the one hand, it is clear that if $\mu _n(A)\to 0$ then

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle \nu_n(A)=\sup_{k\ge n}\mu_k(A\cap V_n) \le \sup_{k\ge n}\mu_k(A) \to 0, \end{align*} $$

hence $\mathcal {I}\subseteq \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\nu }})$ .

On the other hand, suppose that $\nu _n(A)\to 0$ and fix $\varepsilon>0$ . Then there exists $n_0\in \omega $ such that for all $n> n_0$ . Let $k_0$ be the minimal integer such that $S_k\cap \bigcup _{n\le n_0}V_n=\emptyset $ for all $k\ge k_0$ . Fix $k\ge k_0$ and $n\in \omega $ such that $S_k\subseteq V_n\cup V_{n+1}$ (hence, in particular, $n>n_0$ ). We conclude that

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \mu_k(A)&=\mu_k(A\cap S_k)\leq\mu_k(A\cap (V_n\cup V_{n+1}))\\ &\textstyle \leq\mu_k(A\cap V_n)+\mu_k(A\cap V_{n+1}) \leq\nu_n(A)+\nu_{n+1}(A)\le \frac{\varepsilon}{2}+\frac{\varepsilon}{2}=\varepsilon, \end{split} \end{align*} $$

which shows that $\mu _k(A)\to 0$ , therefore $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\nu }}) \subseteq \mathcal {I}$ .⊣

Some additional notations are in order. Given a lscsm $\varphi $ and a real $\delta>0$ , let $\mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }$ be the set of sequences of subsets of $\omega $ with $\varphi $ -value smaller than $\delta $ , that is,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{G}_{\varphi,\delta}:=\left\{(F_n) \in \mathcal{P}(\omega)^\omega: \forall n\in \omega, \,\,\varphi(F_n)< \delta\right\}. \end{align*} $$

Let $\mathcal {I}$ , $\mathcal {J}$ be ideals on $\omega $ and let $\mathcal {I}^+$ be the family of $\mathcal {I}$ -positive sets, that is, $\{A\subseteq \omega : A\notin \mathcal {I}\}$ . Following Solecki and Todorcevic [Reference Solecki and Todorcevic24, p. 1892], we say that a separable metric space X is $(\mathcal {I}^+,\mathcal {J})$ -calibrated if the following property holds: for each sequence $x=(x_n)$ in X with $\Gamma _x(\mathcal {I}) \neq \emptyset $ , there exists $A\in \mathcal {I}^+$ such that $\{x_n: n \in A\cap B\}$ is bounded for all $B \in \mathcal {J}$ (where $\Gamma _x(\mathcal {I})$ denotes the set of $\mathcal {I}$ -cluster points of x, that is, the set of $\ell \in X$ such that $\{n \in \omega : x_n \in U\} \notin \mathcal {I}$ for all neighborhoods U of $\ell $ , cf. [Reference Balcerzak and Leonetti3]).

We continue with some characterizations of density-like ideals, see also [Reference Solecki23, Theorem 4.5].

Proposition 2.2. Let $\varphi $ be a lscsm and set $\mathcal {I}:=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ . Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (D1) $\textstyle \forall \varepsilon>0, \exists \delta >0, \forall (F_n) \in \mathcal {I}^\omega \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }, \exists I \in [\omega ]^\omega , \varphi \left (\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i\right )<\varepsilon $ ;

  2. (D2) $\textstyle \forall \varepsilon>0, \exists \delta >0, \forall (F_n) \in \mathrm {Fin}^\omega \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }, \exists I \in [\omega ]^\omega , \varphi \left (\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i\right )<\varepsilon $ ;

  3. (D3) $\textstyle \forall \varepsilon>0, \exists \delta >0, \forall (F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }, \exists I \in [\omega ]^\omega , \varphi \left (\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i\right )<\varepsilon $ (that is, $\mathcal {I}$ is density-like);

  4. (D4) $\textstyle \forall \varepsilon>0, \exists \delta >0, \forall (F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }, \exists I \in [\omega ]^\omega , \varphi \left (\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i\right )<\varepsilon $ ; and

  5. (D5) $\mathcal {I}$ is $((\mathrm {Fin}\times \mathrm {Fin})^+, \emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})$ -calibrated.

Proof. It is clear that (D1) $\implies $ (D2) $\implies $ (D3) $\implies $ (D4).

(D3) $\Longleftrightarrow $ (D5) See [Reference Solecki and Todorcevic24, Lemma 6.7].

(D4) $\implies $ (D1) See [Reference Solecki and Todorcevic25, Lemma 3.1].⊣

To conclude, every density-like ideal is a generalized density ideal, provided that, in addition, it is $F_\sigma $ .

Proposition 2.3. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be an $F_\sigma $ ideal. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (F1) $\mathcal {I}$ is a generalized density ideal;

  2. (F2) $\mathcal {I}$ is a density-like ideal;

  3. (F3) $\mathcal {I}$ is $((\mathrm {Fin}\times \mathrm {Fin})^+, \emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})$ -calibrated; and

  4. (F4) $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Fin}$ or $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Fin}\oplus \mathcal {P}(\omega )$ .

Proof. (F1) $\implies $ (F2) This is obvious.

(F2) $\implies $ (F3) See [Reference Solecki and Todorcevic24, Lemma 6.7].

(F3) $\implies $ (F4) See [Reference Solecki and Todorcevic24, Proposition 6.8(b)].

(F4) $\implies $ (F1) If $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Fin}$ then $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ , where $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ and each $\mu _n$ is the Dirac measure on $n \in \omega $ . If $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Fin}\oplus \mathcal {P}(\omega )$ is represented on $\omega $ as $\{A\subseteq \omega : A \cap 2\omega \in \mathrm {Fin}\}$ , then $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ , where $\mu _n$ is the Dirac measure on $2n$ , for each $n \in \omega $ .⊣

3 Nontall solutions to Question 1

In this section, we provide a positive answer to Question 1 by showing that there exists a nontall density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal.

To this aim, given an ideal $\mathcal {I}\subseteq \mathcal {P}(\omega )$ , define

(2) $$ \begin{align} \widehat{\mathcal{I}}:=h[(\emptyset \times \mathrm{Fin}) \cap (\mathcal{I} \times \emptyset)]. \end{align} $$

Note that $(\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}) \cap (\mathcal {I} \times \emptyset )$ is an ideal on $\omega ^2$ , hence $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is an ideal on $\omega $ . The ideal $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ has been introduced and studied by Oliver in [Reference Oliver20, Definition 2.1], following an idea of Hjorth. It is remarkable that Oliver used these ideals $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ to show that, in any model of ZFC, there exist an uncountable family of Borel ideals $\mathcal {J}$ such that the quotient Boolean algebras $\mathcal {P}(\omega )/\mathcal {J}$ are pairwise nonisomorphic, see [Reference Oliver20, Theorem 3.2], addressing also a well-known question due to Farah [Reference Farah7].

Lemma 3.1. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be an ideal. Then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is a nontall ideal.

Proof. It is sufficient to see that $h[\{0\}\times \omega ]$ is an infinite set which does not contain any infinite subset in $\mathcal {I}$ .⊣

Here, we show first that if $\mathcal {I}$ is an analytic P-ideal [density-like, respectively], then so is $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ ; notice that the first claim, with an essentially equivalent proof, can be already found in Oliver’s work [Reference Oliver20, Lemma 3.6], but we repeat it here for the sake of readers’ convenience (e.g., we will make explicit use of the submeasure $\lambda $ defined in (4) also later). Then, we prove that $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is not a generalized density ideal whenever $\mathcal {I}$ is tall.

Theorem 3.2. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be an analytic P-ideal. Then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is an analytic P-ideal.

Proof. Let $\varphi $ be a lscsm such that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ . We may assume that $\mathrm {supp}(\varphi )=\omega $ (indeed, it is easy check that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\tilde {\varphi })$ , where $\tilde {\varphi }$ is the lscsm defined by $\tilde {\varphi }(A):=\varphi (A)+\sum _{a \in A\setminus \mathrm {supp}(\varphi )}1/(a+1)^{2}$ for all $A\subseteq \omega $ ).

Let $\nu $ be the submeasure defined by

(3) $$ \begin{align} \forall B\subseteq \omega^2,\quad \nu(B):=\varphi\left(\left\{m \in \omega: B_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\right\}\right). \end{align} $$

To conclude the proof, we claim that $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}=\mathrm {Exh}(\lambda )$ , where $\lambda $ is the submeasure defined by

(4) $$ \begin{align} \forall A\subseteq \omega,\quad \lambda(A):=\nu(h^{-1}[A]). \end{align} $$

(Note that $\lambda $ is a lscsm and that $\mathrm {supp}(\lambda )=\omega $ .)

$\mathrm {Exh}(\lambda )\subseteq \widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ : Fix $A \in \mathrm {Exh}(\lambda )$ and set $B:=h^{-1}[A]$ . Then

(5) $$ \begin{align} \textstyle 0=\|A\|_\lambda=\inf_{F \in \mathrm{Fin}}\lambda(A\setminus F)=\inf_{G \in [\omega^2]^{<\omega}}\nu(B\setminus G). \end{align} $$

First, we want to prove that $B \in \emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}$ . Indeed, in the opposite, there would exist $m \in \omega $ such that $B_{(m)}\notin \mathrm {Fin}$ . However, we would obtain

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle \nu(B\setminus G) \ge \nu((\{m\}\times B_{(m)})\setminus G)=\varphi(\{m\})>0, \end{align*} $$

for every finite set $G\subseteq \omega ^2$ , which contradicts (5). Secondly, we show that $B \in \mathcal {I}\times \emptyset $ . Thanks to (5), for every $\varepsilon>0$ , there exists a finite set $G\subseteq \omega ^2$ such that $\nu (B\setminus G)<\varepsilon $ . Let $F=\{m\in \omega :G_{(m)} \neq \emptyset \}\in \mathrm {Fin}$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*} \varphi\left(\left\{m\in\omega:B_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\right\}\setminus F\right)\leq \varphi\left(\left\{m\in\omega:(B\setminus G)_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\right\}\right)=\nu(B\setminus G)<\varepsilon. \end{align*} $$

By the arbitrariness of $\varepsilon $ , we have $B \in \mathcal {I}\times \emptyset $ . To sum up, we have $B \in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}) \cap (\mathcal {I}\times \emptyset )$ , so that $h^{-1}[\mathrm {Exh}(\lambda )] \subseteq (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})\cap (\mathcal {I}\times \emptyset )$ .

$\widehat {\mathcal {I}}\subseteq \mathrm {Exh}(\lambda )$ : Suppose now that $B \in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})\cap (\mathcal {I}\times \emptyset )$ and fix $\varepsilon>0$ . Since $B \in \mathcal {I}\times \emptyset $ , there exists $F\in \mathrm {Fin}$ such that $\varphi \left (\left \{m\in \omega : B_{(m)} \neq \emptyset \right \}\setminus F\right )<\varepsilon $ . However, since $B \in \emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}$ , the set $G:=B \cap (F\times \omega )$ is finite. Hence

$$ \begin{align*} \nu(B\setminus G)=\varphi\left(\left\{m\in\omega:(B\setminus G)_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\right\}\right)=\varphi\left(\left\{m\in\omega:B_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\right\}\setminus F\right)<\varepsilon. \end{align*} $$

Therefore $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}=\mathrm {Exh}(\lambda )$ , which concludes the proof.⊣

Remark 3.3. Let us suppose that $\varphi $ is a nonpathological lscsm (in the sense of Farah [Reference Farah6, Section 1.7]), that is,

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle \forall A\subseteq \omega,\quad \varphi(A)=\sup_{\eta \in \mathcal{N}(\varphi)}\eta(A), \end{align*} $$

where $\mathcal {N}(\varphi )$ stands for the set of finitely additive measures $\eta $ such that $\eta (V)\le \varphi (V)$ for all $V\subseteq \omega $ (note that $\mathcal {N}(\varphi )\neq \emptyset $ as it contains $\eta =0$ ); strictly related notions have been used in game theory, see [Reference Schmeidler21], and in the context of measure algebras, see [Reference Farah8, Reference Kalton and Roberts13, Reference Talagrand26].

Then the lscsm $\lambda $ defined in (4) is nonpathological as well. To this aim, fix $A\subseteq \omega $ such that $\lambda (A)\neq 0$ (otherwise the claim is trivial), and recall that

$$ \begin{align*}\lambda(A)=\nu(h^{-1}[A])=\varphi(M), \text{ where }M:=\{m \in \omega: h^{-1}[A]_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\}. \end{align*} $$

In particular, M is nonempty. For each $m \in M$ , pick $a_m \in h^{-1}[A]_{(m)}$ . Since $\varphi $ is nonpathological, there exists a sequence $(\eta _n) \in \mathcal {N}(\varphi )^\omega $ such that $\varphi (M)=\lim _n \eta _n(M)$ . At this point, define

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \forall n \in \omega, \forall V \subseteq \omega,\quad \psi_n(V):=\eta_n(\{m \in M: (m,a_m) \in h^{-1}[V]\}). \end{align*} $$

It is easy to see that each $\psi _n$ is a finitely additive measure. Moreover, since each $\eta _n$ is pointwise dominated by $\varphi $ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \textstyle \forall n \in \omega, \forall V\subseteq \omega,\quad \psi_n(V) &\le \varphi(\{m \in M: (m,a_m) \in h^{-1}[V]\})\\ & \le \varphi(\{m \in M: h^{-1}[V]_{(m)}\neq \emptyset\})\le \lambda(V), \end{split} \end{align*} $$

which implies that $(\psi _n) \in \mathcal {N}(\lambda )^\omega $ . Lastly, we have that

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \lambda(A)&\textstyle =\varphi(M)=\lim_{n\to \infty} \eta_n(M)\\ &=\lim_{n \to \infty} \eta_n(\{m \in M: h^{-1}[A]_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\})=\lim_{n\to \infty}\psi_n(A). \end{split} \end{align*} $$

This proves that $\lambda (A)=\sup _{\psi \in \mathcal {N}(\lambda )}\psi (A)$ , i.e., $\lambda $ is nonpathological.

Now we show that the submeasure $\lambda $ defined in (4) is density-like provided that $\varphi $ is density-like (for an alternative shorter proof in the case where $\mathcal {I}$ is an Erdős-Ulam ideal, see Corollary 4.15).

Theorem 3.4. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be a density-like ideal. Then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is a density-like ideal as well.

Proof. Let $\varphi $ be a density-like lscsm such that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ and consider the lscsm $\lambda $ defined as in the proof of Theorem 3.2. Fix $\varepsilon>0$ . By Proposition 2.2, there is $\delta =\delta (\varepsilon )>0$ such that for all $(E_n) \in \mathrm {Fin}^\omega \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }$ there exists $I \in [\omega ]^\omega $ with $\varphi \left (\bigcup _{i \in I}E_i\right )<\varepsilon $ . We claim that the same $\delta $ witnesses the fact that $\lambda $ is density-like.

Fix $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\lambda ,\delta }$ . Define $E_n:=\left \{m \in \omega : h^{-1}[F_n]_{(m)}\neq \emptyset \right \} \in \mathrm {Fin}$ for each $n \in \omega $ and note that

$$ \begin{align*}\varphi(E_n)=\varphi\left(\left\{m \in \omega: h^{-1}[F_n]_{(m)}\neq \emptyset\right\}\right)=\lambda(F_n)<\delta. \end{align*} $$

Thus, $(E_n) \in \mathrm {Fin}^\omega \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }$ and there exists $I \in [\omega ]^\omega $ with $\varphi \left (\bigcup _{i \in I}E_i\right )<\varepsilon $ . Then

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \lambda(F)=\varphi(\{m \in \omega: h^{-1}[F]_{(m)} \neq \emptyset\})=\varphi(\bigcup_{i \in I}E_i)<\varepsilon, \end{align*} $$

where $F:=\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i$ . This concludes the proof.⊣

Theorem 3.5. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be a tall ideal. Then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is not a generalized density ideal.

Proof. Let us suppose that $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ , where $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ is a sequence of lscsms such that $(G_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ , where $G_n:=\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)$ for each $n \in \omega $ .

Fix a strictly increasing sequence $(x_n) \in \omega ^\omega $ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\forall n \in \omega, \quad x_n \in h[\{n\} \times \omega] \,\,\,\text{ and }\,\,\, |G_n \cap X| \le 1, \end{align*} $$

where $X:=\{x_k: k \in \omega \}$ (it is easy to see that such sequence exists). It follows that $X\notin h[\mathcal {I}\times \emptyset ]$ , hence $X\notin \widehat {\mathcal {I}}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ . This implies that there exists $\varepsilon>0$ and a strictly increasing sequence $(m_t)\in \omega ^\omega $ such that $\mu _{m_t}(X) \ge \varepsilon $ for all $t \in \omega $ . However, by construction, each $G_{m_t}$ contains at most one element from X; hence, exactly one since $\mu _{m_t}(X)\neq 0$ , let us say $\{y_t\}:=G_{m_t} \cap X$ for all $t \in \omega $ . It follows that $\mu _{m_t}(Z) \not \to 0$ , where Z stands for any infinite subset of $Y:=\{y_t: t \in \omega \}$ , therefore $\mathcal {P}(Y) \cap [\omega ]^\omega \cap \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})=\emptyset $ . This implies that every infinite subset of Y does not belong to $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ . Considering that $Y \cap h[\{n\}\times \omega ]$ is finite for all $n \in \omega $ , this contradicts the hypothesis that $\mathcal {I}$ is tall.⊣

As an immediate consequence, we obtain the proof of Theorem 1.3

Proof of Theorem 1.3. Let $\mathcal {I}_d$ be the ideal of density zero sets, which is a tall generalized density ideal. By Lemma 3.1 and Theorems 3.4 and 3.5, we get that $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}_d$ is a (nontall) density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal.⊣

At this point, a natural question would be:

Question 2. How many pairwise nonisomorphic ideals $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ are there, with $\mathcal {I}$ tall density-like ideal?

To this aim, given ideals $\mathcal {I},\mathcal {J}$ on $\omega $ we say that $\mathcal {I}$ is isomorphic to $\mathcal {J}$ if there exists a bijection $f: \omega \to \omega $ such that $A\in \mathcal {I}$ if and only if $f^{-1}[A] \in \mathcal {J}$ for all $A\subseteq \omega $ . In addition, we say that $\mathcal {I}$ is below $\mathcal {J}$ in the Katětov order (written as $\mathcal {I}\le _{\mathrm {K}}\mathcal {J}$ ) if there exists a function $\kappa :\omega \to \omega $ such that $A \in \mathcal {I}$ implies $\kappa ^{-1}[A] \in \mathcal {J}$ for all $A\subseteq \omega $ , cf. e.g., [Reference Kwela, Popławski, Swaczyna and Tryba15].

Lastly, we recall that an ideal $\mathcal {I}$ is called a simple density ideal if there exists a function $g: \omega \to [0,\infty )$ such that $g(n)\to \infty $ , $n/g(n)\not \to 0$ and

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{I}=\mathcal{Z}_g:=\left\{A\subseteq \omega: \lim_{n\to \infty}\frac{|A\cap n|}{g(n)}=0\right\}, \end{align*} $$

see [Reference Balcerzak, Das, Filipczak and Swaczyna2, Reference Kwela14, Reference Kwela, Popławski, Swaczyna and Tryba15]. In particular, it has been proved in [Reference Balcerzak, Das, Filipczak and Swaczyna2, Theorem 3.2] that $\mathcal {Z}_g$ is a density ideal (hence, in particular, a generalized density ideal). It is also evident that $\mathcal {Z}_g$ is tall.

The next result can be deduced also as an immediate consequence of [Reference Oliver20, Theorem 3.4]; however, the latter one has a different (and seemingly more complicated) proof, hence we present our argument for the sake of completeness.

Theorem 3.6. There are $2^\omega $ tall density-like ideals $\mathcal {I}$ such that the ideals $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ are pairwise nonisomorphic.

Proof. Thanks to [Reference Kwela, Popławski, Swaczyna and Tryba15, Theorem 3], there exists a family of simple density ideals $\{\mathcal {I}_\alpha : \alpha <2^\omega \}$ such that $\mathcal {I}_\alpha \not \leq _{\mathrm {K}}\mathcal {I}_\beta $ for all distinct $\alpha ,\beta <2^\omega $ .

Hence, given distinct $\alpha ,\beta <2^{\omega }$ , we claim that $\widehat {\mathcal {I}_\alpha }$ is not isomorphic to $\widehat {\mathcal {I}_\beta }$ , i.e., there is no bijection $f: \omega ^2\to \omega ^2$ such that $f[A] \in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})\cap (\mathcal {I}_\alpha \times \emptyset )$ if and only if $A \in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})\cap (\mathcal {I}_\beta \times \emptyset )$ for all $A\subseteq \omega ^2$ .

Suppose that $f: \omega ^2 \to \omega ^2$ is a bijection and suppose that there exist an infinite set $A\subseteq \omega $ and $k\in \omega $ such that $f[A\times \{0\}]\subseteq \{k\}\times \omega $ . Since $\mathcal {I}_\beta $ is tall, there is an infinite $B\subseteq A$ such that $B\in \mathcal {I}_\beta $ . Thus, $B\times \{0\}\in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})\cap (\mathcal {I}_\beta \times \emptyset )$ , but $f[B\times \{0\}]\notin (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})\cap (\mathcal {I}_\alpha \times \emptyset )$ as $f[B\times \{0\}]\cap (\{k\}\times \omega )$ is infinite. This implies that the function $g:\omega \to \omega $ defined by $f(n,0) \in \{g(n)\} \times \omega $ for all $n \in \omega $ is finite-to-one.

Since $\mathcal {I}_\alpha \not \leq _{\mathrm {K}}\mathcal {I}_\beta $ , there exists a (necessarily infinite) set $X\in \mathcal {I}_\alpha $ such that $g^{-1}[X]\notin \mathcal {I}_\beta $ . Define $Y:=f[\omega \times \{0\}] \cap (X\times \omega )$ . Note that, since g is finite-to-one, then $Y\subseteq f[\omega \times \{0\}] \in \emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}$ . Hence $Y \in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}) \cap (\mathcal {I}_\alpha \times \emptyset )$ .

To conclude the proof, let us suppose for the sake of contradiction that $f^{-1}[Y] \in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin})\cap (\mathcal {I}_\beta \times \emptyset )$ . Hence, in particular, $f^{-1}[Y] \in \mathcal {I}_\beta \times \emptyset $ , that is,

$$ \begin{align*}Z:=\{n \in\omega: f^{-1}[Y]_{(n)}\neq \emptyset\} \in \mathcal{I}_\beta. \end{align*} $$

On the other hand, we have

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} Z&=\{n \in \omega: \exists k \in \omega, (n,k) \in f^{-1}[Y]\}=\{n \in \omega: \exists k \in \omega, f(n,k) \in Y\}\\ &=\{n \in \omega: f(n,0) \in Y\}\supseteq \{n \in \omega: g(n) \in X\}=g^{-1}[X] \notin \mathcal{I}_\beta, \end{split} \end{align*} $$

where we used that, if $g(n) \in X$ , then $f(n,0) \in \{g(n)\}\times \omega $ and $f(n,0) \in f[\omega \times \{0\}]$ , i.e., $f(n,0) \in Y$ . This completes the proof.⊣

Thus, we can answer Question 2:

Theorem 3.7. There are $2^\omega $ nonpathological and pairwise nonisomorphic nontall density-like ideals which are not generalized density ideals.

Proof. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be a simple density ideal. Then $\mathcal {I}$ is a density ideal and, in particular, it is nonpathological. Thanks to Remark 3.3, $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is nonpathological as well. The claim follows by Lemma 3.1, Theorems 3.43.6.⊣

4 Tall solutions to Question 1

In the previous Section we have shown that there exists a nontall density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal, providing a positive answer to Question 1. Hence, we may ask:

Question 3. Does there exist a tall density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal?

In this section, we answer positively also Question 3.

Definition 4.1. A sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of lscsms is equi-density-like if for all $\varepsilon>0$ there exists $\delta>0$ such that for all $n\in \omega $ and $(F_k) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\mu _n,\delta }$ there exists an infinite set $I\subseteq \omega $ such that $\mu _n(\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i) < \varepsilon $ .

In words, each lscsm $\mu _n$ is density-like and the choice of $\delta =\delta (\varepsilon )$ is uniform within all $\mu _n$ s.

Theorem 4.2. Let $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ be a sequence of lscsms with pairwise disjoint supports. Then $\varphi :=\sup _n\mu _n$ is density-like if and only if $\boldsymbol {\mu }$ is equi-density-like.

Proof. Define $S_n:=\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)$ for each $n \in \omega $ .

Only If part. Suppose that $\boldsymbol {\mu }$ is not equi-density-like. Then there exists $\varepsilon>0$ such that for all $\delta>0$ there are $n \in \omega $ and $(F_k) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\mu _n,\delta }$ for which $\mu _n(\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i) \ge \varepsilon $ whenever $I\in [\omega ]^{\omega }$ . We claim that this $\varepsilon>0$ witnesses that $\varphi $ is not density-like. To this aim, fix any $\delta>0$ and let n and $(F_k)$ be as before. Define $E_k:=F_k \cap S_n$ for all $k \in \omega $ . Then $\varphi (E_k)=\mu _n(E_k)<\delta $ and $(E_k) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi , \delta }$ . At the same time, we have

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \forall I \in [\omega]^{\omega}, \quad \varphi\left(\bigcup_{i \in I}E_i\right)=\mu_n\left(\bigcup_{i \in I}E_i\right)=\mu_n\left(\bigcup_{i \in I}F_i\right)\ge \varepsilon. \end{align*} $$

Therefore $\varphi $ is not density-like.

If part. Conversely, suppose that $\boldsymbol {\mu }$ is equi-density-like, and fix $\varepsilon>0$ . Then there exists a sufficiently small such that

(6) $$ \begin{align} \textstyle \forall n \in \omega, \forall (F_k) \in \mathcal{F}_{\mathrm{disj}} \cap \mathcal{G}_{\mu_n,\delta}, \exists I \in [\omega]^\omega, \mu_n\left(\bigcup_{i \in I}F_i\right)<\frac{\varepsilon}{4}. \end{align} $$

Fix $(F_k) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }$ and define $(T_k) \in \mathrm {Fin}^\omega $ by $T_k:=\{n \in \omega : F_k \cap S_n \neq \emptyset \}$ for all $k \in \omega $ . At this point, we claim that there exist a sequence of infinite sets $(X_j) \in (\mathrm {Fin}^+)^\omega $ and an increasing sequence $(i_j) \in \omega ^\omega $ such that, for all $j \in \omega $ :

  1. (i) $i_j=\min X_j$ ,

  2. (ii) $X_{j+1}\subseteq X_j\setminus \{i_j\}$ , and

  3. (iii) $\mu _t\left (F^{(j)} \cup \bigcup _{i\in X_{j+1}} F_i\right )<\frac {\varepsilon }{2}$ for each $t\in T^{(j)}$ , where $F^{(j)}:=\bigcup _{k\le j} F_{i_k}$ and $T^{(j)}:=\bigcup _{k\le j} T_{i_k}$ .

We define these sequences recursively. Start with $X_0=\omega $ and $i_0=0$ . Suppose now that $X_k$ and $i_k$ have been defined for all $k\le j \in \omega $ and satisfy (i)–(iii). If $T:=T_{i_j}\setminus T^{(j-1)}$ is empty, set $X_{j+1}:=X_j\setminus \{i_j\}$ and $i_{j+1}:=\min X_{j+1}$ ; if $T\neq \emptyset $ , since $\mu _n(F_k)\leq \varphi (F_k)<\delta $ for all $n,k\in \omega $ , we can find $X_{j+1}\subseteq X_j\setminus \{i_j\}$ such that $\mu _t\left (\bigcup _{i \in X_{j+1}}F_i\right )<\frac {\varepsilon }{4}$ for all $t \in T$ ; finally, set $i_{j+1}:=\min X_{j+1}$ . If $j\neq 0$ and $t \in T^{(j-1)}$ , it follows by the induction hypothesis that

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \mu_t\left(F^{(j)} \cup \bigcup_{i\in X_{j+1}} F_i\right)\le \mu_t\left(F^{(j-1)} \cup \bigcup_{i\in X_{j}} F_i\right) < \frac{\varepsilon}{2}. \end{align*} $$

On the other hand, if $j=0$ or $t \in T$ , then

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \mu_t\left(F^{(j)} \cup \bigcup_{i\in X_{j+1}} F_i\right)\le \mu_t(F_{i_j})+\mu_t\left(\bigcup_{i\in X_{j+1}} F_i\right) < \delta+\frac{\varepsilon}{4}< \frac{\varepsilon}{2}, \end{align*} $$

which proves the condition (iii) and completes the induction.

To complete the proof, note that if $n \notin \bigcup _k T^{(k)}$ then $\mu _n\left (\bigcup _k F^{(k)}\right )=0$ for all $n \in \omega $ . Moreover, if $n \in \bigcup _k T^{(k)}$ then

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \forall j \in \omega, \quad \mu_n\left(\bigcup_k F^{(k)}\right)\le \mu_n\left(F^{(j)} \cup \bigcup_{i\in X_{j+1}} F_i\right)<\frac{\varepsilon}{2}. \end{align*} $$

Thus $\varphi \left (\bigcup _k F^{(k)}\right )\le \frac {\varepsilon }{2}<\varepsilon $ , which shows that $\varphi $ is density-like.⊣

It is worth noting that the above proof works also if $\boldsymbol {\mu }$ is a sequence of lscsms such that $\{n\in \omega :k\in \textrm {supp}(\mu _n)\}$ is finite for all $k\in \omega $ , in the same spirit of [Reference Borodulin-Nadzieja, Farkas and Plebanek5, Proposition 5.4], cf. Proposition 2.1.

The aim of the next example is twofold: first of all, it shows that there exist sequences of lscsms that are not equi-density-like (hence, their pointwise supremum is not density-like); secondly, it proves that the ideal $\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)$ depends on the sequence of lscsms $(\mu _n)$ , not on the sequence of ideals $(\mathrm {Exh}(\mu _n))$ , that is, there are two sequences of lscsms $(\mu _n)$ and $(\nu _n)$ such that $\mathrm {Exh}(\mu _n)=\mathrm {Exh}(\nu _n)$ for each $n\in \omega $ and, on the other hand, $\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)\neq \mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \nu _n)$ .

Example 4.3. Let $(I_{n,m})_{n,m\in \omega }$ be a sequence of pairwise disjoint finite subsets of $\omega $ such that $|I_{n,m}|=2^{m}$ for each $n,m\in \omega $ . Moreover, let $(\eta _{n,m})_{n,m\in \omega }$ be the sequence of probability measures on $\omega $ defined by

$$ \begin{align*} \forall n,m \in \omega, \forall A\subseteq \omega,\quad \eta_{n,m}(A)=\frac{|A\cap I_{n,m}|}{2^m}. \end{align*} $$

Then, define the sequences of lscsms $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ and $\boldsymbol {\nu }=(\nu _n)$ by

$$ \begin{align*} \forall n \in \omega,\quad \mu_n=\sup_{m \in \omega}\eta_{n,m} \,\,\,\text{ and }\,\,\, \nu_n=\sup_{M \in [\omega]^{n+1}}\sum_{m \in M} \eta_{n,m}, \end{align*} $$

where the suprema are meant in the pointwise order.

On the one hand, it is easy to see that $\|A\|_{\mu _n}=0$ if and only if $\|A\|_{\nu _n}=0$ , so that $\mathrm {Exh}(\mu _n)$ and $\mathrm {Exh}(\nu _n)$ are density ideals and they coincide for each $n \in \omega $ .

On the other hand, $\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)=\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _{n,m}\eta _{n,m})$ is a density ideal (hence, in particular, it is a density-like ideal), and it is not equal to $\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \nu _n)$ . Indeed, we will prove that $\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \nu _n)$ is not density-like. Thanks to Theorem 4.2, this is equivalent to show that $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ is not equi-density-like.

To this aim, put $\varepsilon =1$ and fix any $\delta>0$ . There is $k\in \omega $ such that $\frac {1}{2^k}<\delta $ . We will find a sequence $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\nu _{2^k},\delta }$ such that $\nu _{2^k}(\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i) \geq \varepsilon $ for each infinite $I\subseteq \omega $ . For each $n \in \omega $ , fix a subset $F_n\subseteq I_{2^k,k+n}$ such that $|F_n|=2^n$ . Note that $\nu _{2^k}(F_n)=\eta _{2^k,n+k}(F_n)=1/2^{k}<\delta $ for all $n \in \omega $ . Therefore $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\nu _{2^k},\delta }$ . Lastly, fix an infinite set $I \subseteq \omega $ and a subset $M\subseteq I$ such that $|M|=2^k+1$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*}\nu_{2^k}\left(\bigcup_{i \in I}F_i\right) \geq \nu_{2^k}\left(\bigcup_{i \in M}F_{i}\right) \ge \sum_{m \in M}\eta_{2^k,k+m}\left(\bigcup_{i \in M}F_{i}\right) =\sum_{m \in M}\eta_{2^k,k+m}(F_m)>1, \end{align*} $$

which proves that $\boldsymbol {\nu }$ is not equi-density-like.

Definition 4.4. A lscsm $\varphi $ is strongly-density-like if there is a constant $c= c(\varphi )>0$ such that, for all $\varepsilon>0$ and $(F_k) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,c \varepsilon }$ , there exists an infinite set $I \subseteq \omega $ such that $\varphi (\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i) < \varepsilon $ .

Remark 4.5. Observe that if $\boldsymbol {\mu }$ is a sequence of lscsms with pairwise disjoint finite supports, then $\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }}=\sup _n \mu _n$ is strongly-density-like with any constant $c(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})<1$ . Thus, if $\mathcal {I}$ is a generalized density ideal, then there is a strongly-density-like lscsm $\varphi $ with $\varphi $ with $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ .

In the following example we show that there exist density-like lscsms which are not strongly-density-like, cf. also Section 6.

Example 4.6. Let $h: \omega ^2 \to \omega $ be the bijection defined in (1). For each $n \in \omega $ define $X_n:=h^{-1}[\{n\}\times \omega ]$ , so that $\{X_n\}$ is a partition of $\omega $ into infinite sets. Define $a_k:=1/(k+2)!$ for each $k \in \omega $ and note that $a_k\to 0$ as $k\to +\infty $ and $a_{k-1}>(k+1)a_k$ for all $k>0$ . Moreover, set $\varphi :=\sup _n \mu _n$ , where $(\mu _n)$ is the sequence of lscsms given by

$$ \begin{align*}\forall n \in \omega, \forall A\subseteq \omega,\quad \mu_n(A)=a_n \min\{n+1,|A\cap X_n|\}. \end{align*} $$

We claim that $\varphi $ is a density-like lscsm which is not strongly-density-like.

First, we show that $\varphi $ is not strongly-density-like. To this aim, fix an arbitrary constant $c>0$ and a positive integer k such that . Then, set $\varepsilon :=(k+1)a_k$ and $F_n:=\{h^{-1}(k,n)\}$ for each $n \in \omega $ . It follows that

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \forall n\in \omega,\quad \varphi(F_n)=\mu_k(F_k)=a_k< \frac{(k+1)a_k}{k}\le c\varepsilon, \end{align*} $$

hence $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,c\varepsilon }$ . On the other hand, for each infinite set $I\subseteq \omega $ , we have $ \varphi (\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i)= \mu _k(\bigcup _{i \in I}F_i)=(k+1)a_k=\varepsilon. $

Now let us show that $\varphi $ is density-like. Fix $\varepsilon>0$ and define $\delta :=a_k$ , where k is an integer such that $(k+1)a_k<\varepsilon $ . Fix also $(F_k) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }$ . Note that $F_k \cap \bigcup _{n\le k-1}X_n=\emptyset $ for each $k \in \omega $ : indeed

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \forall x \in \bigcup_{n\le k-1}X_{n},\quad \varphi(\{x\}) \ge a_{k-1}> (k+1)a_{k} \ge a_{k} =\delta. \end{align*} $$

Therefore

$$ \begin{align*} \forall I \in [\omega]^\omega,\quad \varphi\left(\bigcup_{i \in I}F_{i}\right)\le \varphi\left(\bigcup_{n\ge k}X_n\right)=\sup_{k\ge n} \mu_k(X_k)=(k+1)a_k<\varepsilon, \end{align*} $$

concluding the proof.

Proposition 4.7. Fix $q \in [1,\infty )$ . Then the set of strongly-density-like lscsms is q-convex, that is, for each strongly-density-like lscsms $\varphi _1,\ldots ,\varphi _k$ and $a_1,\ldots ,a_k \in [0,1]$ with $\sum _{i\le k} a_i=1$ , the lscsm $ \varphi :=(\sum _{i\le k}a_i \varphi _i^q)^{1/q} $ is strongly-density-like. In addition, a witnessing constant of $\varphi $ is $c(\varphi )=\frac {1}{2}\min \{c(\varphi _1),\ldots ,c(\varphi _k)\}$ .

Proof. Let $\varphi _1,\ldots ,\varphi _k$ be strongly-density-like lscsms, fix $a_1,\ldots ,a_k \in [0,1]$ with $\sum _{i\le k} a_i=1$ , and define the lscsm $\varphi :=(\sum _{i\le k}a_i \varphi _i^q)^{1/q}$ . Set $c:=\frac {1}{2}\min _{i\le k}c(\varphi _i)$ , so that $2c$ is a witnessing constant for each $\varphi _i$ .

Fix $\varepsilon>0$ and a sequence $(F_j) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}\cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,c\varepsilon }$ . For each $j \in \omega $ and $i \in \{1,\ldots ,k\}$ define the integer $ z_{i,j}:=\left \lfloor \varphi _i(F_j)/c\varepsilon \right \rfloor. $ Note that $z_{i,j}<a_i^{-1/q}$ , indeed

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \forall i=1,\ldots,k,\quad c\varepsilon>\varphi(F_j)\ge a_i^{1/q}\varphi_i(F_j) \ge a_i^{1/q}z_{i,j}c\varepsilon. \end{align*} $$

Considering that $L:=\prod _{i=1}^k (\omega \cap [0,a_i^{-1/q}))$ is finite, there exists $\ell =(\ell _1,\ldots ,\ell _k) \in L$ and an infinite set $J\subseteq \omega $ such that $z_{i,j}=\ell _i$ for all $i =1,\ldots ,k$ and $j \in J$ .

At this point, observe that $\sum _{i\le k}a_i\ell _i^q<1$ , indeed

$$ \begin{align*} \sum_{i\le k}a_i(c\varepsilon\ell_i)^q=\sum_{i\le k}a_i(c\varepsilon z_{i,\min J})^q\le \sum_{i\le k}a_i\varphi_i(F_{\min J})^q=\varphi(F_{\min J})^q < (c\varepsilon)^q. \end{align*} $$

Since each $\varphi _i$ is strongly-density-like with witnessing constant $2c$ , we have that $\varphi _i(F_j)<(z_{i,j}+1)c\varepsilon =(2c)\cdot \frac {(\ell _i+1)\varepsilon }{2}$ for all $j \in J$ . Hence there exists an infinite set $T\subseteq J$ such that $ \varphi _i(\bigcup _{t \in T}F_t)<\frac {(\ell _i+1)\,\varepsilon }{2}. $ for all $i=1,\ldots ,k$ .

Thanks to Minkowski’s inequality, we conclude that

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle \varphi(\bigcup_{t \in T}F_t)<\frac{\varepsilon}{2}\left(\sum_{i\le k}a_i (\ell_i+1)^q\right)^{1/q}\le \frac{\varepsilon}{2}\left(\left(\sum_{i\le k}a_i\ell_i^q\right)^{1/q}+1\right)<\varepsilon, \end{align*} $$

which proves that $\varphi $ is strongly-density-like.⊣

Definition 4.8. An ideal $\mathcal {I}$ is said to be a $\mathrm {DL}$ -ideal if it is isomorphic to some $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ , where $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ is a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ defined by

(7) $$ \begin{align} \forall A\subseteq \omega^2,\quad \psi(A):=\sup_{n \in \omega}\,(\sum_{k \in S_n}a_k \varphi_k^{q_n}(A_{(k)}))^{1/q_n}, \end{align} $$

where $\boldsymbol {\varphi }=(\varphi _n)$ is a sequence a strongly-density-like lscsms on $\omega $ , $q=(q_n)$ is a sequence in $[1,\infty )$ , and $a=(a_n) \in [0,1]^\omega $ and $S=(S_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ are sequences such that $\sum _{k \in S_n}a_k=1$ for all $n \in \omega $ .

For the rest of this section, it may be helpful to take in mind the following example of DL-ideals.

Example 4.9. Fix a strictly increasing sequence $(\iota _n)$ of nonnegative integers such that $\iota _0:=0$ and $\lim _n |I_n|=\infty $ , where $I_n:=[\iota _n,\iota _{n+1})$ for all $n \in \omega $ . In particular, thanks to Remark 4.5, the map $\mathcal {P}(\omega ) \to [0,\infty ]$ defined by $S\mapsto \sup _m |S\cap I_m|/|I_m|$ is a strongly-density-like lscsm. It follows that $\mathcal {I}:=\{h[A]: A \in \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )\}$ is a DL-ideal, where $\psi : \omega ^2 \to [0,\infty ]$ is the lscsm defined by

$$ \begin{align*}\forall A\subseteq \omega^2, \quad \psi(A):=\sup_{n \in \omega} \left(\frac{1}{|I_n|}\sum_{k \in I_n}\sup_{m\in \omega} \frac{|A_{(k)}\cap I_m|}{|I_m|}\right). \end{align*} $$

As it will be shown below in Corollary 4.21, the above ideal provides an affirmative answer to Question 3.

Remark 4.10. It is not difficult to see that, if $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ is a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) such that q is the constant sequence $(1)$ and each $\varphi _n$ is nonpathological, then $\psi $ is nonpathological as well. For each lscsm $\phi $ on $\omega $ and for each $k \in \omega $ , let $\tilde {\phi }^{(k)}$ be the lscsm on $\omega ^2$ defined by $\tilde {\phi }^{(k)}(A):=\phi (A_{(k)})$ for all $A\subseteq \omega ^2$ . Then, with the same notation of Remark 3.3, we know that

$$ \begin{align*} \forall A\subseteq \omega^2, \forall k \in \omega,\quad \varphi_k(A_{(k)})=\sup_{\eta \in \mathcal{N}(\varphi_k)}\eta(A_{(k)}) =\sup_{\tilde{\eta}^{(k)} \in \mathcal{N}_k(\varphi_k)}\tilde{\eta}^{(k)}(A), \end{align*} $$

where $\mathcal {N}_k(\varphi _k):=\{\tilde {\eta }^{(k)}: \eta \in \mathcal {N}(\varphi _k)\}$ (note that, if $k\neq k^\prime $ , then measures in $\mathcal {N}_k(\varphi _k)$ have disjoint supports from measures in $\mathcal {N}_{k^\prime }(\varphi _{k^\prime })$ ). Let $\tilde {\mathcal {N}}(\psi )$ be the set of finitely additive measures on $\omega ^2$ which are pointwise dominated by $\psi $ . Then

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \forall A\subseteq \omega^2,\quad \sup_{\tilde{\eta} \in \tilde{\mathcal{N}}(\psi)}\tilde{\eta}(A)&\le \psi(A)=\sup_{n \in \omega} \sum_{k \in S_n} a_k \sup_{\tilde{\eta}^{(k)} \in \mathcal{N}_k(\varphi_k)} \tilde{\eta}^{(k)}(A)\\ &=\sup_{n \in \omega} \sup_{\substack{\tilde{\eta}^{(k)} \in \mathcal{N}_k(\varphi_k), \\ \text{ with }k \in S_n}} \sum_{k \in S_n} a_k \tilde{\eta}^{(k)}(A) \le \sup_{\tilde{\eta} \in \tilde{\mathcal{N}}(\psi)}\tilde{\eta}(A), \end{split} \end{align*} $$

where the last inequality is justified by the fact that each $\sum _{k \in S_n} a_k \tilde {\eta }^{(k)}$ is finitely additive measure which is dominated by $\psi $ . Therefore $\psi $ is nonpathological.

Remark 4.11. Each generalized density ideal is a $\mathrm {DL}$ -ideal. Indeed, let $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ be a sequence of lscsms with pairwise disjoint finite supports such that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)$ . Moreover, let $h: \omega ^2 \to \omega $ be the bijection defined in (1) and $f: \omega ^2 \to \omega $ be a bijection such that

$$ \begin{align*} \forall n,m \in \omega,\quad \mathrm{supp}(\mu_{h(n,m)})\subseteq f[\{n\}\times\omega]. \end{align*} $$

Then it suffices to set $\boldsymbol {\varphi }=(\varphi _n)$ , where $\varphi _n(A)=\sup _{m\in \omega }\mu _{h(n,m)}(f[\{n\}\times A])$ for all $n\in \omega $ and $A\subseteq \omega $ , $q=(1)$ , $a=(1)$ , and $S=(\{n\})$ . It follows that each $\varphi _n$ is strongly-density-like (cf. Remark 4.5) and that $\mathcal {I}$ is isomorphic to $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ , where $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ is the lscsm on $\omega ^2$ defined as in (7).

Proposition 4.12. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be an Erdős–Ulam ideal. Then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is a $\mathrm {DL}$ -ideal.

Proof. By [Reference Farah6, Example 1.2.3(d), Theorem 1.13.3(a), and Lemma 1.13.9(Z3)], there is a sequence $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ of probability measures on $\omega $ such that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)$ , and $(M_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ , where $M_n:=\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)$ for each $n \in \omega $ . Then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is isomorphic to the ideal $\mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ on $\omega ^2$ , where $\nu $ is the lscsm defined by

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \forall A\subseteq \omega^2,\quad \nu(A)=\sup_{n\in \omega} \mu_n(\{k \in \omega: A_{(k)}\neq \emptyset\}), \end{align*} $$

cf. (3) in the proof of Theorem 3.2.

To conclude the proof, we show that $\nu =\psi $ , for some $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ . To this aim, let $\boldsymbol {\varphi }$ be the constant sequence $(\varphi )$ , where $\varphi $ is the strongly-density-like lscsm defined by $\varphi (\emptyset )=0$ and $\varphi (S)=1$ for all nonempty $S\subseteq \omega $ . Let also q be the constant sequence $(1)$ , $S_n=M_n$ , and $a_k:=\sup _n \mu _n(\{k\})$ for all $n \in \omega $ (note that $\sum _{k\in S_n}a_k=1$ for all $n \in \omega $ ). It follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \forall A\subseteq \omega^2,\quad \psi(A)=\sup_{n \in \omega}\sum_{k \in S_n}a_k \varphi(A_{(k)})=\sup_{n \in \omega}\mu_n(\{k \in S_n: A_{(k)}\neq \emptyset\})=\nu(A). \end{align*} $$

Therefore $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is a $\mathrm {DL}$ -ideal.⊣

Theorem 4.13. Let $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ be a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) such that $\inf _n c(\varphi _n)>0$ . Then $\psi $ is a density-like lscsm.

Proof. For each $k \in \omega $ define the lscsm $\tilde {\varphi }_k$ on $\omega ^2$ by

$$ \begin{align*} \forall A\subseteq \omega^2,\quad \tilde{\varphi}_k(A)=\varphi_k(A_{(k)}). \end{align*} $$

Then each $\tilde {\varphi }_k$ is a strongly-density-like lscsm such that $c(\tilde {\varphi }_k)=c(\varphi _k)$ . Moreover, for each $n \in \omega $ , define the lscsm $\psi _n$ by

$$ \begin{align*}\forall A\subseteq \omega^2,\quad \psi_n(A)=\left(\sum_{k \in S_n}a_k\tilde{\varphi}_k(A)^{q_n}\right)^{1/q_n}. \end{align*} $$

It follows by Proposition 4.7 that each lscsm $\psi _n$ is strongly-density-like with witnessing constant $c(\psi _n)=\frac {1}{2}\min \{c(\tilde {\varphi }_k): k \in S_n\}$ . Since $\inf _n c(\varphi _n)>0$ , we have also $\inf _n c(\psi _n)>0$ , which implies that $(\psi _n)$ is equi-density-like sequence of lscsms with pairwise disjoint supports (indeed $\mathrm {supp}(\psi _n)=\bigcup _{k \in S_n}\{k\}\times \mathrm {supp}(\varphi _n)\subseteq S_n \times \omega $ ). Therefore, thanks to Theorem 4.2, $\psi =\sup _n \psi _n$ is density-like.⊣

The following corollary is immediate.

Corollary 4.14. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be a $\mathrm {DL}$ -ideal isomorphic to $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ , where $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ is a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ such that $\boldsymbol {\varphi }$ is a constant sequence. Then $\mathcal {I}$ is density-like.

Note that, as it follows from the proof of Proposition 4.12, if $\mathcal {I}$ is an Erdős–Ulam ideal, then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is isomorphic to $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ , where $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ is a lscsm such that $\boldsymbol {\varphi }$ is a constant sequence. Therefore, thanks to Corollary 4.14, we obtain:

Corollary 4.15. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be an Erdős–Ulam ideal. Then $\widehat {\mathcal {I}}$ is a density-like ideal.

Note that Corollary 4.15 is also a consequence of Theorem 3.4; however, the proof of the latter uses Proposition 2.2, which in turn relies on [Reference Solecki and Todorcevic25, Lemma 3.1].

Note that, thanks to Proposition 4.7, $\psi $ is the pointwise supremum of strongly-density-like lscsms. Now we show that, under some additional hypotheses, the exhaustive ideal generated by $\psi $ is tall.

Proposition 4.16. Let $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ be a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) and assume that $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _n)$ is tall for all $n \in \omega $ , $M:=\sup _{n,k}\varphi _n(\{k\})<\infty $ , and $\max \{a_k^{1/q_n}: k \in S_n\}\to 0$ as $n\to \infty $ . Then $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ is tall.

Proof. Let $A\subseteq \omega ^2$ be an infinite set. If $A \in \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ then the claim is trivial. Hence, suppose hereafter that $A\in \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )^+$ , that is,

(8) $$ \begin{align} \|A\|_\psi=\inf_{F \in [\omega^2]^{<\omega}}\,\sup_{n \in \omega}\,\left(\sum_{k \in S_n}a_k \varphi_k^{q_n}(A_{(k)}\setminus F)\right)^{1/q_n}>0. \end{align} $$

Now, suppose that there exists $m \in \omega $ such that $A_{(m)}$ is infinite. Since $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _m)$ is tall, there exists an infinite set $B\subseteq A\cap (\{m\}\times \omega )$ such that $B_{(m)} \in \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _m)$ . It follows by the definition of $\psi $ that $B \in \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ .

Otherwise $A \in (\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}) \cap \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )^+$ , so that $A_{(m)}$ is finite for each $m \in \omega $ . Let B be an infinite subset of A such that $|B \cap \bigcup _{m \in S_n}A_{(m)}|\le 1$ for all $n \in \omega $ (which exists, otherwise A itself would be finite, contradicting (8)). It follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \|B\|_\psi&\le \inf_{m\in \omega} \|B\setminus \left(\bigcup_{i\le m}S_i \times \omega\right)\|_{\psi} \le \inf_{m \in \omega}\psi\left( B\setminus \left(\bigcup_{i\le m}S_i \times \omega\right)\right)\\ &\le \inf_{m \in \omega} \sup_{n\ge m}\,\left(\sum_{k \in S_n}a_k \varphi_k^{q_n}(B_{(k)})\right)^{1/q_n} \\ &\le M \, \limsup_{n\to\infty} \max\{a_k^{1/q_n}: k \in S_n\} =0. \end{split} \end{align*} $$

Therefore $B \in \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ , concluding the proof.⊣

As a consequence, we obtain that:

Corollary 4.17. Let $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ be a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) and assume that $\boldsymbol {\varphi }$ is the constant sequence $(\varphi )$ , q is a bounded sequence, $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ is tall, and $\lim _n a_n=0$ . Then $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ is tall.

Proof. First of all, we have $\sup _n \varphi (\{n\})<\infty $ : indeed, in the opposite case, there would exist an increasing sequence $(n_k)$ in $\omega $ such that $\varphi (\{n_k\}) \ge k$ for all k and every infinite subset of $\{n_k: k \in \omega \}$ would not belong to $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ , contradicting the hypothesis that $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ is tall. Moreover, since $Q:=\sup _n q_n <\infty $ , we obtain

$$ \begin{align*}\textstyle \lim_n \max \{a_k^{1/q_n}: k \in S_n\}\le \lim_n \max \{a_k^{1/Q}: k \in S_n\} =0. \end{align*} $$

The claim follows by Proposition 4.16.⊣

Theorem 4.18. Let $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi }, q, a, S)$ be a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) such that

$$ \begin{align*} \textstyle 0<\inf_{n \in \omega}\| \omega\|_{\varphi_n} \le \sup_{n \in \omega} \varphi_n(\omega) <\infty, \end{align*} $$

and $\max \{a_k^{1/q_n}: k \in S_n\} \to 0$ as $n\to \infty $ . Then $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ is not a generalized density ideal.

Proof. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )=\mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)$ , where $(\mu _n)$ is a sequence of lscsms on $\omega ^2$ with finite pairwise disjoint supports and set $M_n:=\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)$ for each n (note that $M_n \subseteq \omega ^2$ ). It follows by the standing assumptions that there exists a sequence $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}}$ such that

(9) $$ \begin{align} \forall n \in \omega,\quad \varphi_n(F_n) \ge \frac{\inf_{k \in \omega}\| \omega\|_{\varphi_k}}{2} \,\,\text{ and }\,\, X_n \cap \bigcup_{\substack{k \in \omega: \\ M_k \cap \,\bigcup_{i\le n-1}X_i \neq \emptyset}} M_k =\emptyset, \end{align} $$

where $X_n:=\{n\} \times F_n$ for each n.

Set $X:=\bigcup _n X_n$ . Then $X\notin \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ . Indeed

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \|X\|_\psi &=\inf_{F \in \mathrm{Fin}}\sup_{n \in \omega}(\sum_{k \in S_n} a_k \varphi_k^{q_n}(X_{(k)}\setminus F))^{1/q_n}\\ &\ge \inf_{F \in \mathrm{Fin}}\sup_{n \in \omega} \min_{k \in S_n}\{\varphi_k(X_{(k)}\setminus F)\} \ge \frac{\inf_{k \in \omega}\| \omega\|_{\varphi_k}}{2}>0. \end{split} \end{align*} $$

It follows that $X \notin \mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)$ , i.e., there exist $\varepsilon>0$ and an increasing sequence $(n_k)$ in $\omega $ such that $\mu _{n_k}(X)>\varepsilon $ for all $k \in \omega $ . However, thanks to (9), for each k there exists a unique $m_k \in \omega $ such that $X\cap M_{n_k}\subseteq X_{m_k}$ . Therefore $\mu _{n_k}(X_{m_k})>\varepsilon $ for all $k \in \omega $ . Let M be an infinite subset of $\{m_k: k \in \omega \}$ such that $|S_n \cap M|\le 1$ for all n. Define $Y:=\bigcup _{m \in M}X_m$ and note that $Y\notin \mathrm {Exh}(\sup _n \mu _n)$ .

Then necessarily $Y\notin \mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ . However, considering that there is at most one $k \in S_n$ such that $Y_{(k)}\neq \emptyset $ , we obtain

$$ \begin{align*} \|Y\|_\psi &\le \inf_{F \in [\omega^2]^{<\omega}}\sup_{n \in \omega} \max_{k \in S_n}\{a_k^{1/q_n}\varphi_k((Y\setminus F)_{(k)})\} \\ & \le \sup_{n \in \omega}\varphi_n(\omega) \limsup_{t\to \infty}\max_{k \in S_t}\{a_k^{1/q_t}\} = 0, \end{align*} $$

which is the wanted contradiction.⊣

With the same technique of Corollary 4.17, we obtain (details are omitted):

Corollary 4.19. Let $\varphi $ be a strongly-density-like lscsm on $\omega $ such that

(10) $$ \begin{align} 0<\|\omega\|_{\varphi}\le \varphi(\omega)<\infty. \end{align} $$

Moreover, let $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi },q,a,S)$ be a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) and assume that $\boldsymbol {\varphi }$ is the constant sequence $(\varphi )$ , q is a bounded sequence, and $\lim _n a_n=0$ . Then $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ is not a generalized density ideal.

Note that condition (10) has been already used in the literature, see e.g., [Reference Solecki22, Theorem 3.1].

Putting all together, we have the following:

Theorem 4.20. Let $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi }, q, a, S)$ be a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) such that:

  1. (i) $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _n)$ is tall for each $n \in \omega $ ;

  2. (ii) $\lim _n \max \{a_k^{1/q_n}: k \in S_n\}=0$ ;

  3. (iii) $\inf _n c(\varphi _n)>0$ ; and

  4. (iv) $0<\inf _{n}\| \omega \|_{\varphi _n} \le \sup _{n} \varphi _n(\omega ) <\infty $ .

Then $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ is a tall density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal.

Proof. Thanks to (iv), we have $\sup _{n,k}\varphi _n(\{k\})\le \sup _n \varphi _n(\omega )<\infty $ . The conclusion follows by Proposition 4.16 and Theorems 4.13 and 4.18.⊣

In the case where $\boldsymbol {\varphi }$ is a constant sequence and q is bounded, we can simplify the above conditions:

Corollary 4.21. Let $\varphi $ be a strongly-density-like lscsm on $\omega $ such that $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ is tall and satisfies (10). Moreover, let $\psi =\psi (\boldsymbol {\varphi }, q, a, S)$ be a lscsm on $\omega ^2$ as in (7) such that $\boldsymbol {\varphi }$ is the constant sequence $(\varphi )$ , q is bounded, and $\lim _n a_n=0$ .

Then $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ is a tall density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal.

Proof. It follows by Corollaries 4.14, 4.17, and 4.19.⊣

Thus, we answer Question 3, giving an alternative proof of Theorem 1.3.

Theorem 4.22. There exists a tall density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal.

Proof. Let $\mathcal {I}_d$ be the ideal of density zero sets, which is a tall ideal. Thanks to [Reference Farah6, Example 1.2.3(d), Theorem 1.13.3(a), and Lemma 1.13.9(Z3)], there exists a sequence $(\mu _n)$ of probability measures with finite pairwise disjoint supports such that $\mathcal {I}_d=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ , where $\varphi :=\sup _n \mu _n$ . In particular, $\varphi (\omega )=\|\omega \|_\varphi =1$ . The claim follows by Corollary 4.21.⊣

With the same spirit of Question 2, we ask:

Question 4. How many pairwise nonisomorphic tall density-like ideals which are not generalized density ideals are there?

We will show that, as in Theorem 3.7, there is a family of $2^\omega $ such ideals. To this aim, we need a preliminary lemma.

Lemma 4.23. There exists a family $\mathscr {A}$ of $2^\omega $ subsets of $\omega ^2$ such that

(11) $$ \begin{align} \forall (A,A^\prime) \in [\mathscr{A}]^2, \forall k \in \omega,\quad A_{(k)} \notin \mathrm{Fin} \,\,\,\text{ and }\,\,\, A \cap A^\prime \in \mathrm{Fin}. \end{align} $$

Proof. It is known that there exists a family $\mathscr {B}$ of $2^\omega $ subsets of $\omega $ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\forall (B,B^\prime) \in [\mathscr{B}]^2, \quad B \notin \mathrm{Fin} \,\,\,\text{ and }\,\,\, B \cap B^\prime \in \mathrm{Fin}, \end{align*} $$

see e.g., [Reference Albiac and Kalton1, Lemma 2.5.3]. Then, it is sufficient to see that $\{\,\bigcup _{n\in \omega } \{n\}\times (B\setminus n): B \in \mathscr {B}\}$ satisfies (11).⊣

Theorem 4.24. There are $2^\omega $ nonpathological and pairwise nonisomorphic tall density-like ideals which are not generalized density ideals.

Proof. Let $h: \omega ^2 \to \omega $ be the bijection defined in (1). Let also $\mathscr {M}=\{M_z: z \in \omega ^2\}$ be a partition of $\omega ^2$ into nonempty finite sets such that $M_{(n,m)}\subseteq \{n\}\times \omega $ for all $n,m\in \omega $ and

(12) $$ \begin{align} \forall n \in \omega, \quad m_{h^{-1}(n+1)}\ge (n+2)\sum_{i\le n}m_{h^{-1}(i)}, \end{align} $$

where $m_z:=|M_z|$ . Moreover, for each $(n,m) \in \omega ^2$ , let $\mu _{(n,m)}$ be the uniform probability measure given by $\mu _{(n,m)}(X)= |(\{n\}\times X)\cap M_{(n,m)}|/m_{(n,m)}$ for all $X\subseteq \omega $ .

Fix $(S_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}}$ such that $\lim _n |S_n|=\infty $ and let $\mathscr {A}$ be a family of $2^\omega $ subsets of $\omega ^2$ which satisfies (11) (existing by Lemma 4.23). For each $A \in \mathscr {A}$ , let $\psi _A$ be the lscsm on $\omega ^2$ defined by

$$ \begin{align*} \psi_A:=\sup_{n\in \omega} \sum_{k \in S_n}\frac{1}{|S_n|}\,\varphi_{A,k}, \,\,\,\text{ where }\,\,\,\varphi_{A,k}:=\sup_{t \in A_{(k)}} \mu_{(k,t)}, \end{align*} $$

for all $k \in \omega $ . It follows that, for each $A \in \mathscr {A}$ , the lscsm $\psi _A$ is of the type (7), where $q_n=1$ for all n and $a_k=1/|S_i|$ whenever $k \in S_i$ ; hence $\lim _n a_n=0$ . In addition, for each $A \in \mathscr {A}$ and $k \in \omega $ , the ideal $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{A,k})$ is tall and $\|\omega \|_{\varphi _{A,k}}=\varphi _{A,k}(\omega )=1$ . Lastly, thanks to Remark 4.5, each $\varphi _{A,k}$ is strongly-density-like with any witnessing constant $c(\varphi _{A,k})<1$ . In particular, . Therefore, by Theorem 4.20, each $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi _A)$ is a tall density-like ideal which is not a generalized density ideal. Also, by Remark 4.10, each $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi _A)$ is nonpathological.

At this point, we claim that, for all distinct $A,A^\prime \in \mathscr {A}$ , the ideals $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi _A)$ and $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi _{A^\prime })$ are not isomorphic. To this aim, fix distinct $A,A^\prime \in \mathscr {A}$ and suppose for the sake of contradiction that $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi _A)$ and $\mathrm {Exh}(\psi _{A^\prime })$ are isomorphic, witnessed by a bijection $f:\omega ^2 \to \omega ^2$ . Let $(x_n)$ be the enumeration of the infinite set $A\setminus A^\prime $ such that the sequence $(h(x_n))$ is increasing. Then, pick a sequence $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}}$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\forall n \in \omega,\quad F_n\subseteq M_{x_n}, \,\,\, |F_n|=\left\lfloor \frac{m_{x_n}}{2}\right\rfloor, \,\,\,\text{ and }\,\,\, F_{n+1}\cap \bigcup_{\substack{z \in \omega^2: \\ h(z)<h(x_{n+1})}}f[M_z]=\emptyset. \end{align*} $$

Note that this is really possible: indeed, letting U be the latter union, it follows by (12) that

$$ \begin{align*} |U|= \sum_{h(z)<h(x_{n+1})}m_z= \sum_{i\le h(x_{n+1})-1}m_{h^{-1}(i)} \le \frac{1}{2}\,m_{x_{n+1}}. \end{align*} $$

Set $F:=\bigcup _n F_n$ . It follows by construction that for all $k \in \omega $ , hence $F \notin \mathrm {Exh}(\psi _A)$ . On the other hand, we obtain by (12) that

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \forall (i,j) \in A^\prime \setminus A,\quad \mu_{(i,j)}((f^{-1}[F])_{(i)}) &=\frac{|F\cap f[M_{(i,j)}]|}{m_{(i,j)}} \\ &\le \frac{\sum_{n\in\{k:\ h(x_k)<h((i,j))\}}|F_n|}{m_{(i,j)}} \\ &\le \frac{\sum_{k\le h((i,j))-1}m_{h^{-1}(k)}}{m_{h^{-1}(h((i,j)))}} \le \frac{1}{h((i,j))+1}, \end{split} \end{align*} $$

which implies that $f^{-1}[F] \in \mathrm {Exh}(\psi _{A^\prime })$ . This contradiction concludes the proof.⊣

5 Characterization of generalized density ideals

In this section, we provide a characterization of generalized density ideals which resembles the one of density-like ideal given in Definition 1.2. This provides sufficient conditions for a density-like ideal to be necessarily a generalized density ideal,

Let $\mathscr {H}$ be the set of strictly increasing sequences in $\omega $ . Then, given a lscsm $\varphi $ and a real $\varepsilon>0$ , define

$$ \begin{align*} K_{s, F}:=\{(k_n) \in \mathscr{H}: \forall n\in \omega, \exists m \in \omega, \max F_{k_n}\le s_m < \min F_{k_{n+1}}\}, \end{align*} $$

for all $s=(s_n) \in \mathscr {H}$ and $F=(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {disj}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi , \varepsilon }$ (note that $K_{s, F}\neq \emptyset $ ).

Definition 5.1. A lscsm $\varphi $ on $\omega $ satisfies condition $\boldsymbol {\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {weak}}}$ if for all $\varepsilon>0$ there exist $\delta>0$ and a sequence $s \in \mathscr {H}$ such that, if $F=(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }$ and $k\in K_{s, F}$ , then $\varphi (\bigcup _{n} F_{k_n})<\varepsilon $ .

If the sequence $s \in \mathscr {H}$ can be chosen uniformly in $\varepsilon>0$ , we have the following:

Definition 5.2. A lscsm $\varphi $ on $\omega $ satisfies condition $\boldsymbol {\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}}$ if there exists a sequence $s \in \mathscr {H}$ for which for all $\varepsilon>0$ there exists $\delta>0$ such that, if $F=(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta }$ and $k\in K_{s, F}$ , then $\varphi (\bigcup _{n} F_{k_n})<\varepsilon $ .

It is clear that every lscsm $\varphi $ satisfying condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}$ satisfies also condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {weak}}$ . Thus, we state the main result of this section.

Theorem 5.3. Let $\mathcal {I}$ be an ideal. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. (A1) $\mathcal {I}$ is a generalized density ideal;

  2. (A2) every lscsm $\varphi $ such that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ satisfies condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}$ ;

  3. (A3) every lscsm $\varphi $ such that $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ satisfies condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {weak}}$ ;

  4. (A4) $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ for some lscsm $\varphi $ satisfying condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}$ ; and

  5. (A5) $\mathcal {I}=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ for some lscsm $\varphi $ satisfying condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {weak}}$ .

The proof is divided in some intermediate steps.

Lemma 5.4. Let $\varphi $ be a lscsm and assume that $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ is a generalized density ideal. Then $\varphi $ satisfies condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}$ .

Proof. Let us suppose for the sake of contradiction that $\varphi $ does not satisfy condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}$ . Thanks to Proposition 2.1, we can suppose without loss of generality that there exist a sequence $(\mu _n)$ of submeasures and a sequence $(S_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {int}}$ of consecutive intervals of $\omega $ such that $\varphi =\sup _n\mu _n$ and $S_n=\mathrm {supp}(\mu _n)$ for all $n \in \omega $ . In particular, $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )=\{A\subseteq \omega : \lim _n \mu _n(A)=0\}$ and $\mu _n(\omega )\not \to 0$ .

Define $s \in \mathscr {H}$ by $s_n:=\max S_n$ for all $n \in \omega $ . Since $\varphi $ does not satisfy condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}$ , there exists $\varepsilon>0$ such that for all nonzero $m\in \omega $ there are $F^m=(F^m_n)\in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\frac {\varepsilon }{2^m}}$ and $k^m=(k^m_n)\in K_{s,F^m}$ for which $\varphi (\bigcup _{n} F^m_{k_n^m})\geq \varepsilon $ . Since $\varphi $ is a lscsm, for each m there exists $\ell _m \in \omega $ such that .

Set $G_m:=\bigcup _{n\leq \ell _m} F^m_{k^m_n}$ and note that $G:=\bigcup _m G_m$ does not belong to $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ . To this aim, fix a nonzero $j\in \omega $ . Since $(k^j_n)\in K_{s,F^j}$ , there are at most j many sets $F^j_{k_n^j}$ which have nonempty intersection with the set $s_j+1$ and each of them has $\varphi $ -value smaller than $\varepsilon /2^{j}$ . Thus

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{split} \varphi(G\setminus (s_j+1)) \ge \varphi(G_j\setminus (s_j+1))\ge \varphi(G_j)-\varphi(G_j \cap (s_j+1))\ge \varepsilon-j \frac{\varepsilon}{2^j}\ge \frac{\varepsilon}{2}. \end{split} \end{align*} $$

Therefore . In particular, there exists a sequence $(j_i) \in \mathscr {H}$ such that for all $i\in \omega $ . Passing eventually to a subsequence, we can assume without loss of generality that

(13) $$ \begin{align} \forall i \in \omega, \quad s_{j_i}>\max G_{i+1}. \end{align} $$

At this point, define $X:=G\cap \bigcup _i S_{j_i}$ . Then by construction , so that $X\notin \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ . On the other hand, we will show that $\lim _n \mu _n(X)=0$ , reaching a contradiction. Taking into account (13), note that $S_{j_i}\cap X= S_{j_i} \cap \bigcup _{m>i}G_m$ for all i. Moreover, recall that, for all $i,m \in \omega $ , there exists at most one n such that $F^m_{k^m_n}\cap S_{j_i} \neq \emptyset $ . It follows that

$$ \begin{align*}\forall i \in \omega,\quad \varphi(S_{j_i}\cap X)=\mu_{j_i}\left(\bigcup_{m>i}G_m\right)\le \sum_{m>i}\mu_{j_i}(G_m) \le \sum_{m>i}\frac{\varepsilon}{2^m}=\frac{\varepsilon}{2^i}. \end{align*} $$

To conclude, we obtain that

$$ \begin{align*}\forall t \in \omega, \quad \varphi\left(X\setminus \bigcup_{i\le t}S_{j_i}\right)=\varphi\left(X\cap \bigcup_{i> t}S_{j_i}\right)\le \sum_{i>t}\varphi(S_{j_i} \cap X)\le \sum_{i>t}\frac{\varepsilon}{2^i}= \frac{\varepsilon}{2^t}, \end{align*} $$

which tends to $0$ as $t\to \infty $ . Hence $X \in \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ , which is the wanted contradiction.⊣

Now, we show that condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {weak}}$ implies (a variant of) condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {strong}}$ .

Lemma 5.5. Let $\varphi $ be a lscsm which satisfies condition $\mathrm {D}_{\mathrm {weak}}$ . Then there is a lscsm $\nu $ and a sequence $s \in \mathscr {H}$ such that for every $\varepsilon>0$ there is $\delta>0$ for which, if $F \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\nu ,\delta }$ and $k \in K_{s,F}$ , then $\nu (\bigcup _{n} F_{k_{2n}})<\varepsilon $ , and $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )=\mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ .

Proof. Let $(\varepsilon _k)$ be a strictly decreasing sequence such that $\lim _k \varepsilon _k=0$ . Then, for each k, there are $\delta _k>0$ and a sequence $s^k=(s_n^k) \in \mathscr {H}$ such that, if $F \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\varphi ,\delta _k}$ and $k \in K_{s^k, F}$ , then $\varphi (\bigcup _{n} F_{k_n})<\varepsilon _k$ . Without loss of generality, we can assume that $\delta _{k+1}<\delta _k<\varepsilon _k$ . Let us define $s=(s_n) \in \mathscr {H}$ as follows: $s_0:=s_0^0$ and, for each $n \in \omega $ , let $s_{n+1}$ be such that for all $m\leq n+1$ there is $\ell \in \omega $ such that $s_n\leq s^m_\ell <s_{n+1}$ . Then, set $S_0:=[0,s_0]$ and $S_{n+1}:=(s_{n},s_{n+1}]$ for all $n\in \omega $ .

Also, let $\psi $ be the lscsm defined by $\psi (\emptyset )=0$ and, for each nonempty $A\subseteq \omega $ , $\psi (A):=\delta _k$ , where k is the minimal integer such that $A\cap S_k\neq \emptyset $ . At this point, set $\nu :=\max \{\varphi ,\psi \}$ . Then $\nu $ is a lscsm such that $\mathrm {Exh}(\nu )=\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ . Indeed, on the one hand, $\nu \geq \varphi $ , hence $\mathrm {Exh}(\nu )\subseteq \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ . On the other hand, fix $A\in \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ and $\varepsilon>0$ , hence there is $n_0\in \omega $ such that $\mu (A\setminus n)<\varepsilon $ for all $n\geq n_0$ . Also, there is $n_1\in \omega $ such that $\delta _n<\varepsilon $ for all $n\geq n_1$ . Thus, for each n such that $n\geq n_0$ and $\bigcup _{i<n_1}S_i\subseteq n$ we have $\nu (A\setminus n)<\varepsilon $ . Therefore $A\in \mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ , which proves the opposite inclusion $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )\subseteq \mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ .

Lastly, we show that $\nu $ satisfies the condition in the statement. Fix $\varepsilon>0$ and let m be the minimal integer such that $\varepsilon _m\leq \varepsilon $ . We claim that $\delta :=\delta _m$ witnesses this condition. Fix $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\nu ,\delta }$ , $k \in K_{s,F}$ , and $j\in \omega $ . Then there exist $\ell ^\prime ,\ell ^{\prime \prime } \in \omega $ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\max F_{k_{2j}}\leq s_{\ell^\prime}<\min F_{k_{2j+1}}\leq\max F_{k_{2j+1}}\leq s_{\ell^{\prime\prime}}<\min F_{k_{2(j+1)}}. \end{align*} $$

Note that $m<\ell ^\prime <\ell ^{\prime \prime }$ , where the former inequality follows by the fact that $F_n \cap \bigcup _{i\le m}S_i =\emptyset $ for all n (by the definition of $\nu $ and the hypothesis $(F_n) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\nu ,\delta }$ ) and the latter since $s\in \mathscr {H}$ . Thus, there exists $\ell \in \omega $ such that

$$ \begin{align*}s_{\ell^\prime}\leq s^m_\ell<s_{\ell^\prime+1}\leq s_{\ell^{\prime\prime}}. \end{align*} $$

It follows that $\max F_{k_{2j}}\leq s^m_{\ell }<\min F_{k_{2(j+1)}}$ , so that $(k_{2n})\in K_{s^m, F}$ . Therefore $\varphi (\bigcup _{n} F_{k_{2n}})<\varepsilon _m\leq \varepsilon $ . It is also easy to see that $\psi (\bigcup _{n} F_{k_{2n}})\leq \delta =\delta _m<\varepsilon _m\leq \varepsilon $ . Putting all together, we conclude that $\nu (\bigcup _{n} F_{k_{2n}})<\varepsilon $ .⊣

Lemma 5.6. Let $\nu $ be a lscsm as in Lemma 5.5. Then $\mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ is a generalized density ideal.

Proof. Define $S_0:=[0,s_0]$ and $S_{n+1}:=(s_n,s_{n+1}]$ for all $n\in \omega $ . Let $\boldsymbol {\mu }=(\mu _n)$ be the sequence of lscsms defined by

$$ \begin{align*}\forall n \in \omega, \forall A\subseteq \omega,\quad \mu_n(A):=\nu(A\cap S_n). \end{align*} $$

We claim that $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})=\mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ , where $\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }}:=\sup _n \mu _n$ .

It is clear that $\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }} \le \nu $ , hence $\mathrm {Exh}(\nu )\subseteq \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ . Conversely, fix $A\in \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})$ and $\varepsilon>0$ , hence there is $\delta>0$ such that, if $F=(F_n)\in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\nu ,\delta }$ and $k\in K_{s,F}$ , then . There exists $n_0\in \omega $ such that $\mu _n(A)<\delta $ for all $n\geq n_0$ . Define $F_n:=A\cap S_{n+n_0}$ for all $n\in \omega $ . Then $\nu (F_n)=\mu _{n+n_0}(A)<\delta $ for all $n \in \omega $ . Thus $(F_n)\in \mathcal {F}_{\mathrm {incr}} \cap \mathcal {G}_{\nu ,\delta }$ and for each $k \in K_{s,F}$ we have . Note the sequences $(n)$ and $(n+1)$ belong to $K_{s,F}$ , so that and . Define $m:=\min S_{n_0}$ . Then for each $m\geq m_0$ we have

$$ \begin{align*}\nu(A\setminus m) \le \nu(A\setminus m_0)=\nu\left(\bigcup_{n \in \omega} F_n\right) \le \nu\left(\bigcup_{n\in \omega} F_{2n}\right)+\nu\left(\bigcup_{n\in \omega} F_{2n+1}\right) <\varepsilon. \end{align*} $$

We conclude that $A\in \mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ , therefore $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi _{\boldsymbol {\mu }})\subseteq \mathrm {Exh}(\nu )$ .⊣

We are finally ready to prove Theorem 5.3, cf. Figure 1 below.

Figure 1 Relationship between generalized density ideals and density-like ideals, assuming $\mathcal {I}$ is an analytic P-ideal.

Proof of Theorem 5.3. (A1) $\implies $ (A2) follows by Lemma 5.4. The implications (A2) $\implies $ (A3) $\implies $ (A5) and (A2) $\implies $ (A4) $\implies $ (A5) are obvious. Lastly, (A5) $\implies $ (A1) follows by Lemmas 5.5 and 5.6.⊣

6 Concluding remarks

Differently from the case of density-like lscsms, if $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are two lscsms such that $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )=\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ and $\varphi $ is strongly-density-like, then $\psi $ is not necessarily strongly-density-like.

Indeed, let $\varphi $ be the strongly-density-like lscsm defined in Example 4.6. Then, with the same notations, it is easily seen that $A\in \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ if and only if $A\cap X_n\in \mathrm {Fin}$ for all $n \in \omega $ , hence $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ is isomorphic to $\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}$ . However, $\emptyset \times \mathrm {Fin}$ is a generalized density ideal and, thanks to Remark 4.5, there exists a strongly-density-like lscsm $\psi $ such that $\mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )=\mathrm {Exh}(\psi )$ . We conclude with an open question.

Question 5. Does there exist a density-like ideal $\mathcal {I}$ such that $\mathcal {I}\neq \mathrm {Exh}(\varphi )$ for each strongly-density-like lscsm $\varphi $ ?

Acknowledgments

The authors are grateful to an anonymous reviewer for his careful reading of the manuscript and constructive suggestions, and to Jacek Tryba (University of Gdańsk, PL) for several useful comments and for pointing out reference [Reference Oliver20]. P.L. thanks PRIN 2017 (grant no. 2017CY2NCA) for financial support.

References

Albiac, F. and Kalton, N. J., Topics in Banach Space Theory, second ed., Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 233, Springer, Cham, 2016.Google Scholar
Balcerzak, M., Das, P., Filipczak, M., and Swaczyna, J., Generalized kinds of density and the associated ideals . Acta Mathematica Hungarica, vol. 147 (2015), no. 1, pp. 97115.Google Scholar
Balcerzak, M. and Leonetti, P., On the relationship between ideal cluster points and ideal limit points . Topology and its Applications, vol. 252 (2019), pp. 178190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borodulin-Nadzieja, P. and Farkas, B., Analytic P-ideals and Banach spaces . Journal of Functional Analysis, vol. 279 (2020), no. 8, Article no. 108702, p. 31.Google Scholar
Borodulin-Nadzieja, P., Farkas, B., and Plebanek, G., Representations of ideals in Polish groups and in Banach spaces , this Journal, vol. 80 (2015), no. 4, pp. 12681289.Google Scholar
Farah, I., Analytic quotients: theory of liftings for quotients over analytic ideals on the integers . Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 148 (2000), no. 702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farah, I., How many Boolean algebras ${\ P\left(\mathbb{N}\right)/ \mathcal{I}\ }$ are there? Illinois Journal of Mathematics, vol. 46 (2002), no. 4, pp. 9991033.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farah, I., Examples of $\epsilon$ -exhaustive pathological submeasures . Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 181 (2004), no. 3, pp. 257272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farah, I., Analytic Hausdorff gaps. II. The density zero ideal . Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 154 (2006), pp. 235246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Filipów, R., Mrożek, N., Recław, I., and Szuca, P., Ideal convergence of bounded sequences , this Journal, vol. 72 (2007), no. 2, pp. 501512.Google Scholar
Hrušák, M., Combinatorics of filters and ideals , Set Theory and Its Applications (L. Babinkostova, A. E. Caicedo, S. Geschke, and M. Scheepers, editors), Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 533, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2011, pp. 2969.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Just, W. and Krawczyk, A., On certain Boolean algebras ${\ P\left(\omega \right) /\ I}$ . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 285 (1984), no. 1, pp. 411429.Google Scholar
Kalton, N. J. and Roberts, J. W., Uniformly exhaustive submeasures and nearly additive set functions . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 278 (1983), no. 2, 803816.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kwela, A., Erdős–Ulam ideals vs. simple density ideals . Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, vol. 462 (2018), no. 1, pp. 114130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kwela, A., Popławski, M., Swaczyna, J., and Tryba, J., Properties of simple density ideals . Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, vol. 477 (2019), no. 1, pp. 551575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leonetti, P., Limit points of subsequences . Topology and its Applications, vol. 263 (2019), pp. 221229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Louveau, A. and Veličković, B., A note on Borel equivalence relations . Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 120 (1994), no. 1, pp. 255259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Louveau, A. and Veličković, B., Analytic ideals and cofinal types . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 99 (1999), nos. 1–3, pp. 171195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mátrai, T., More cofinal types of definable directed orders. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, to appear.Google Scholar
Oliver, M. R., Continuum-many Boolean algebras of the form ${\ P\left(\omega \right) /\ \mathcal{I}}$ , $\mathcal{I}$ Borel, this Journal, vol. 69 (2004), no. 3, pp. 799816.Google Scholar
Schmeidler, D., Cores of exact games. I . Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, vol. 40 (1972), pp. 214225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solecki, S., Analytic ideals and their applications . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 99 (1999), nos. 1–3, pp. 5172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solecki, S., Tukey reduction among analytic directed orders . Zbornik Radova (Beograd), vol. 17 (2015), no. 25, pp. 209220, Selected topics in combinatorial analysis.Google Scholar
Solecki, S. and Todorcevic, S., Cofinal types of topological directed orders . Annales de l’Institut Fourier, vol. 54 (2004), no. 6, 18771911.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solecki, S. and Todorcevic, S., Avoiding families and Tukey functions on the nowhere-dense ideal . Journal of the Institute of Mathematics of Jussieu, vol. 10 (2011), no. 2, pp. 405435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talagrand, M., Maharam’s problem . Annals of Mathematics. Second Series, vol. 168 (2008), no. 3, pp. 9811009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uzcátegui Aylwin, C., Ideals on countable sets: a survey with questions . Revista Integración, Temas de Matemáticas, vol. 37 (2019), no. 1, pp. 167198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 Relationship between generalized density ideals and density-like ideals, assuming $\mathcal {I}$ is an analytic P-ideal.