Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T14:27:04.587Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Non-null implication1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

David Nelson*
Affiliation:
The George Washington University, Washington, D.C.

Extract

An implication A ⊃ B is said to be null in case A is false in all instances. This note describes several formal systems for first-order predicate logic and arithmetic in which null implications do not occur. In fact, the most restrictive systems avoid the occurrences of any formulas which represent null predicates. The precise sense of this avoidance is explained below.

An intuitionistic negation is a statement of the form A ⊃ F where F is a contradiction. The absence of null implications among true statements entails the absence of intuitionistic negations, and hence systems described here might be called negationless intuitionistic systems.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Acknowledgment is given for support by The Office of Naval Research, Grant Nonr (G)-00065–64.

References

[1]Freudenthal, H., Zur intuitionistischen Deutung logischer Formeln, Compositio mathematica, vol. 4 (1937), pp. 112116.Google Scholar
[2]Gilmore, P. C., The effect of Griss' criticism of the intuitionistic logic on deductive theories formalized within the intuitionistic logic (Dissertation, Amsterdam, 1953), Amsterdam; also Koninklijke Nederlandsche Akademie van Wetenschappen, Proceedings of the section of sciences, vol. 56 (1953), pp. 162–174; 175–186.Google Scholar
[3]Griss, G. F. C., Negationless intuitionistic mathematics. I, Koninklijke Nederlandsche Akademie van Wetenschappen, Proceedings of the section of sciences, Vol. 49 (1946), pp. 11271133; Indagationes mathematicae, vol. 8 (1946), pp. 675–681.Google Scholar
[4]Heyting, A., Intuitionism. An introduction, Amsterdam (North-Holland), 1956.Google Scholar
[5]Kleene, S. C., Introduction to metamathematics, Amsterdam (North-Holland), Groningen (Noordhoff), New York and Toronto (Van Nostrana), 1952.Google Scholar
[6]Kleene, S. C., Realizability, Constructivity in mathematics (edited by Heyting, A.), Amsterdam (North-Holland), 1959, pp. 285289.Google Scholar
[7]Nelson, D., Recursive functions and intuitionistic number theory, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 61 (1947), pp. 307368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[8]Nelson, D., Review of [2], this Journal, Vol. 21 (1956), p. 91.Google Scholar
[9]Valpola, V., Ein System der negationslosen Logik mit ausschliesslich realisierbaren Prädikaten, Acta Philosophica Fennica, Fasc. IX, Helsinki, 1955.Google Scholar
[10]Vredenduin, P. G. J., The logic of negationless mathematics, Compositio mathematica, vol. 11 (1953), pp. 204277.Google Scholar