Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T03:21:22.271Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Formal development of ordinal number theory1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Steven Orey*
Affiliation:
Cornell University and University of Minnesota

Extract

In this paper we shall develop a theory of ordinal numbers for the system ML, [6]. Since NF, [2], is a sub-system of ML one could let the ordinal arithmetic developed in [9] serve also as the ordinal arithmetic of ML. However, it was shown in [9] that the ordinal numbers of [9], NO, do not have all the usual properties of ordinal numbers and that theorems contradicting basic results of “intuitive ordinal arithmetic” can be proved.

In particular it will be a theorem in our development of ordinal numbers that, for any ordinal number α, the set of all smaller ordinal numbers ordered by ≤ has ordinal number α; this result does not hold for the ordinals of [9] (see [9], XII.3.15). It will also be an easy consequence of our definition of ordinal number that proofs by induction over the ordinal numbers are permitted for arbitrary statements of ML; proofs by induction over NO can be carried through only for stratified statements with no unrestricted class variables.

The class we shall take as the class of ordinal numbers, to be designated by ‘ORN’, will turn out to be a proper subclass of NO. This is because in ML there are two natural ways of defining the concept of well ordering. Sets which are well ordered in the sense of [9] we shall call weakly well ordered; sets which satisfy a certain more stringent condition will be called strongly well ordered. NO is the set of order types of weakly well ordered sets, while ORN is the class of order types of strongly well ordered sets. Basic properties of weakly and strongly well ordered sets are developed in Section 2.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1955

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

The material of this paper was part of a Ph.D. thesis presented to the Faculty of Cornell University in September, 1953. I wish to express my sincere thanks to Prof. J. B. Rosser for his suggestions and advice in connection with the writing of that thesis.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

[1]Kamke, E., Mengenlehre, Walter de Gruyter & Co., Berlin, 1928, 159 pp.Google Scholar
[2]Quine, W. V., New foundations for mathematical logic, American mathematical monthly, vol. 44 (1937), pp. 7080.Google Scholar
[3]Quine, W. V., On Cantor's theorem, this Journal, vol. 2 (1937), pp. 120124.Google Scholar
[4]Quine, W. V., Mathematical logic, first printing, W. W. Norton and Co., New York, 1940, xiii + 348 pp.Google Scholar
[5]Quine, W. V., On ordered pairs, this Journal, vol. 10 (1945), pp. 9596.Google Scholar
[6]Quine, W. V., Mathematical logic, rev. ed., Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1951, xii + 346 pp.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7]Rosser, J. B., The Burali-Forti paradox, this Journal, vol. 7 (1942), pp. 117.Google Scholar
[8]Rosser, J. B., The axiom of infinity in Quine's New Foundations, this Journal, vol. 27 (1952), pp. 238242.Google Scholar
[9]Rosser, J. B., Logic for mathematicians, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1953, xiv + 530 pp.Google Scholar
[10]Sierpinski, W., Leçons sur les nombres transfinis, Gautiers-Villars et Cie., Paris, 1928, 240 pp.Google Scholar
[11]Specker, E. P., The axiom of choice in Quine's New Foundations for Mathematical Logic, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, vol. 39 (1953), pp. 972975.Google Scholar