Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T07:30:20.665Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Navigator in Antiquity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 January 2010

Extract

The problem of navigation, reduced to its very simplest terms, is how to get from X to Y. But this statement appears at first sight to require the proviso ‘given the means of transport available’, whether camel, ship, plane or rocket. Each sets up its special limitations to free movement, but in effect merely determines that XY must be broken up into segments, X Y1, Y1 Y2 and so on. Further reflection would probably add two additional considerations, the navigator must get safely and expeditiously from X to Y. But this again can only break down the route into fresh segments whereby dangers and difficulties are avoided. It is still for the navigator just the problem of getting from X, where he is, to a designated Y, where he wishes to be.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Navigation 1948

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 103 note * ‘The Arte of Navigation demonstrateth how, by the shortest good way, by the aptest direction, and in the shortest time, a sufficient ship … be conducted’, wrote John Dee in 1570.

page 104 note * In early sailing Manuals we find distances given in ‘kennings’ (veues in French), e.g. ‘Scylley is a kenning …. from the very Westeste Point of Cornewaulle.’