Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-06T11:59:47.813Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Distinction, physiologically and psychologically considered, between Perception, Memory; Sensation, and Intellect

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 February 2018

W. G. Davies*
Affiliation:
Joint Counties' Asylum, Abergavenny

Extract

Perception we define to be the intellectual and presentative consciousness of objects of any kind, internal or external, and the primary gateway of knowledge. In every perception the object is a most prominent feature. It is in the invariable presence of the object in perception, and its absence from memory and imagination, that we behold the striking difference which there is between it and the latter; and it is on this distinction the universal assurance is grounded that what we perceive is different from what we remember or imagine. In every perception there is an intellectual and a sensational element, and memory proper is the persistence of the intellectual element after the sensational element has disappeared from consciousness, or after the peripheral nerves have ceased to excite the sense-centre. In no instance have we been able, by any amount of effort, to make an act of memory or imagination seem a perception; yet Hume divided perceptions into two classes, as distinguished by their different degrees of force and vivacity. The less lively he named thoughts and ideas; the more lively, impressions. Professor Bain seems to take the same view of the question. In reference to the recalling of past feelings, he says:—“The renewed feeling occupies the very same parts, and in the same manner, as the original feeling, and no other parts, nor in any other manner that can be assigned.” It is the opinion of some, then, that memory and imagination only differ from perception in being less lively. The latter is a vivid picture, the former are faint reproductions of it. We fail to see that this is precisely the case. In every perception there is an object present, and cognized as distinct from the consciousness of it—in special instances, as even distinct from the perceiver altogether. When we gaze at a picture, the picture is regarded as one thing, the knowing of it as another; whereas when we only think of the picture, we do not recognize any object as really distinct from thought itself. An imagined external object is still detected to be a mental object. “A representation considered as an object is logically, not really, different from a representation considered as an act. Here object and act are merely the same indivisible mode of mind viewed in two different relations… The same may be said of image and imagination.” “Imagination, regarded as a product, may be defined, the consciousness of an image in the mind resembling and representing an object of intuition.” Though we do not exactly hold with these opinions, we quote them in order to show what view is taken by some psychologists in reference to the distinction between presentative and representative consciousness, or between knowing a thing immediately in perception, and knowing it mediately through an image of the mind's collecting. How is it possible, when contemplating a mountain which one is on the point of ascending—albeit the mountain is to us, as immediately known, in a sense-centre—to regard it as identical, except in vivacity, with the recollection which we afterwards have of it? Perception is, so to speak, a bi-une fact, a synthesis of cognition and object, whereas memory and imagination are not bi-une, for the object is not present in them, in the same manner, at least, as it is in perception. But let us now proceed to adduce facts and deductions confirmatory of this view of the question.

Type
Part I.—Original Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal College of Psychiatrists, 1868 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

“The Senses and the Intellect,” p. 883, § 10.Google Scholar

“Hamilton's Reid,” p. 809, § 10.Google Scholar

“Prolegomena Logica,” Prof. Mansel, 2nd edit, p. 13.Google Scholar

“The Physiology and Pathology of the Mind,” Dr. Maudsley, p. 87, et seq. “Lewes's Biographical History of Philosophy,” Cabains, Condillac, and DarwinGoogle Scholar

“Hamilton's Reid,” p. 861, note.Google Scholar

“Journal of Mental Science,” Oct., 1867.Google Scholar

§ “Muller's Physiology,” pp. 692–696, English translation.Google Scholar

The writer of this has frequently succeeded, even while eating, in singing some air with which he was familiar The motory ganglia most largely concerned in this experiment seem to be those pertaining to the respiratory organs. This subdued operation of the motory centres appears to be indispensable to an act of thinking.Google Scholar

Griesinger on “Mental Diseases,” English translation by Dre. Robertson and Rutherford, p. 29, § 2. “The Physiology and Pathology of the Mind,” p. 113 (b).Google Scholar

“Hamilton's Reid,” p. 878, note. See also Mr. Lookhart Clarke, “Medical Critic and Psychological Journal,” Vol. II., p. 675, et seq.Google Scholar

“The Physiology and Pathology of the Mind,” p. 94.Google Scholar

“Hamilton's Reid,” p. 878, § 6.Google Scholar

“Prolegomena Logica," chap. I.Google Scholar

In the “Alphabet of Thought” (Williams and Norgate), part II., chap. 1 and 2, this will be found treated more at length, but requiring correction in one or two instances.Google Scholar

Quain's “Anatomy,” 7th edit, part IH., p. cxlvii. See ”Hamilton's Reid,” p. 872. School of Boerhaave.Google Scholar

“Hamilton's Reid,” p. 862. Note.Google Scholar

The method of knowing is that of existence, namely, beginning with the simple, and developing out of this superior and more complex results. Thus the first step in knowing seems to be the realization of the ego in extension plus time by means of the extended sensorium minus the tactual centre; then, in correlation with the extended ego, the extended non-ego by means of the tactual centre and the motory centres; then, on the basis of these, coloured extension by means of the visual centre, and its relative motory centres, &c. By the time, however, that the senses are fully in operation, an object is known by the conjoint agency of them all. A sensation experienced in one of the sense-centres unavoidably suggests all that it presupposes in other centres, and also possibly suggests what is simply contingently related to it.Google Scholar

We only remember that which has already existed in consciousness, which involves that the present consciousness should be precisely similar to the past Memory, therefore, comes wholly under the law of similarity; like recalls like, but unlike has no power of recalling unlike. Cell-action which is different to any previous action, must be original, and therefore excludes the past, whereas memory implies present consciousness known together with the re presentation of a past similar to it. When we think of Charles the First, and then of Cromwell, it may appear that unlike has called up unlike, but this is not the case, for it is part of a previous state of consciousness that has recalled the whole of the previous state, which it could only do in so far as the states reproduced are similar to the past states. Indeed, the very terms which we are forced to use— “re-calling,” “re-producing,” “re-collecting,” “re-membering”—point to the fact of a repetition of a former state of consciousness ; therefore, in memory like recalls like, but unlike has no recalling power.Google Scholar

Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.