Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T06:08:29.809Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Use of Nonhuman Animals in Biomedical Research: Necessity and Justification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Discourse about the use of animals in biomedical research usually focuses on two issues. The first, which I will refer to as the “necessity issue,” is empirical and asks whether the use of nonhumans in experiments is required in order to gather statistically valid information that will contribute in a significant way to improving human health. The second, which I will refer to as the “justification issue,” is moral and asks whether the use of nonhumans in biomedical research, if necessary as an empirical matter, can be defended as a matter of ethical theory.

If it is not necessary as an empirical matter to use animals in research, then there is no need to inquire about moral justification. Therefore, I examine the necessity issue first. The argument that it is necessary to use nonhumans in biomedical research, though flawed, is at least plausible, unlike our necessity arguments for other animal uses. I then discuss the justification issue and conclude that we cannot morally justify using nonhuman animals in research.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

For a further discussion of the necessity of various animal uses and of the material in this section, see Francione, G. L., Introduction to Animal Rights: Your Child or the Dog? (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 2000): 149. Discussions of the necessity of animal use outside the context of research do not usually ask whether it is necessary to use animals at all for a particular purpose, but whether particular instances of pain or suffering are necessary even if the general use of animals in that context is not necessary. For reasons that I discuss later in this essay and in my other work (see, e.g., id., at 50–80), that understanding of necessity is problematic. In the context of biomedical research, the necessity analysis focuses more on whether it is necessary to use animals at all for this purpose.Google Scholar
For a general discussion of animal welfare laws, including anticruelty laws and statutes such as the Animal Welfare Act, see Francione, G. L., Animals, Property, and the Law (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1995).Google Scholar
For a discussion of the variety of uses of nonhumans in vivisection, including product testing and education, see Francione, supra note 1, at 45–49. I do not discuss experiments intended to address health concerns of domestic nonhuman animals as I argue that if we took animal interests seriously, we would not continue to facilitate the production of domesticated nonhumans for human use. See Francione, supra note 1, at 153–154.Google Scholar
For a discussion of these campaigns, see Francione, supra note 2, at 72–78, 179–183.Google Scholar
Id., at 165–250.Google Scholar
Bailey, J., “Non-human Primates in Medical Research and Drug Development: A Critical Review,” Biogenic Amines 19, no. 4–6 (2005): 235255, at 247–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LaFollette, H. and Shanks, N., “Animal Experimentation: The Legacy of Claude Bernard,” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8, no. 3 (1994): 195210, at 204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Bailey, supra note 6, at 249.Google Scholar
Enterline, P. E., “Asbestos and Cancer,” in Gordis, L., ed., Epidemiology and Health Risk Assessment (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988): 8284.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Çetinkaya, H. Domjan, M., “Sexual Fetishism in a Quail (Coturnix japonica) Model System: Test of Reproductive Success,” Journal of Comparative Psychology 120, no. 4 (2006): 427432; Jenkins, J. A. Williams, P. Kramer, G. L. Davis, L. L. and Petty, F., “The Influence of Gender and the Estrous Cycle on Learned Helplessness in the Rat,” Biological Psychology 58 (2001): 147-158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, M. T., “Savages, Drunks and Lab Animals: The Researcher's Perception of Pain,” Society and Animals 1 (1993): 6181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
For a further discussion of the basic right of humans not to be treated exclusively as means to the ends of others, see Francione, supra note 1, at 90–98, 156–157.Google Scholar
For a further discussion of the reasons that have been offered to justify animal use, see id., at 103–129.Google Scholar
For a discussion of modern philosophers who apparently adopt the Cartesian position, see id., at 104–106.Google Scholar
Darwin, C., The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981): at 105, 76, 77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, e.g., Bekoff, M. and Jamieson, D., eds., Readings in Animal Cognition (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996); Griffin, D. R., Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to Consciousness (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001); Hauser, M. D., The Evolution of Communication (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996); Hauser, M. D., Wild Minds: What Animals Really Think (New York: Owl Books, 2001); Ristau, C. A., ed., Cognitive Ethology: The Minds of Other Animals: Essays in Honor of Donald R. Griffin (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1991); Savage-Rumbaugh, S. and Lewin, R., Kanzi: The Ape at the Brink of the Human Mind (New York: Wiley, 1994).Google Scholar
For example, Frans de Waal states that “honesty, guilt, and the weighing of ethical dilemmas are traceable to specific areas of the brain. It should not surprise us, therefore, to find animal parallels. The human brain is a product of evolution. Despite its larger volume and greater complexity, it is fundamentally similar to the central nervous system of other mammals.” de Waal, F., Good-Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996): at 218.Google Scholar
I argue that sentience alone is sufficient for full membership in the moral community, which involves the right not to be treated as a resource. See Francione, supra note 1, at 92–100, 116–119.Google Scholar
I maintain that any being who is sentient is necessarily self-aware. Id., at 114, 137–142.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P., The Animals Issue: Moral Theory in Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992): at 181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J., A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 1971): at 505.Google Scholar
Id., at 512.Google Scholar
Cohen, C., “The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research,” New England Journal of Medicine 315 (1986): 865870, at 866.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Francione, supra note 1, at 122–123.Google Scholar
See Rawls, supra note 21, at 512.Google Scholar
See Carruthers, supra note 20, at 98–121.Google Scholar
Id., at 114.Google Scholar
Id., at 114–115.Google Scholar
Id., at 117.Google Scholar
See Cohen, supra note 23, at 866.Google Scholar