Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-06T01:23:12.645Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Ethical Health Lawyer: When Doing the Right Thing Means Breaking the Law – What is the Role of the Health Lawyer?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

What happens when being a good doctor requires being a bad citizen? What should a doctor do when living up to the requirements of a professional code of ethics or staying true to deeply held personal values requires breaking the law? What should a health care professional do when the appropriate conduct in a particular case is inconsistent with a more generalized principle that has been incorporated into law? Further, what is the role of the ethical health lawyer who advises a health care provider facing such a dilemma?

As health care lawyers advising individuals and institutions, is it our job to advise our clients of all the options available to them, and all the potential legal consequences, or is our role simply to keep our clients acting within the law? Are we information providers, policy counselors, risk managers, or some combination of these?

Type
JLME Column
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Weber, D. R., Civil Disobedience in America: A Documentary History (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1978).Google Scholar
See Brown, J. M., Gandhi and Civil Disobedience: The Mahatma in Indian Politics, 1928–34 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977) for an account of historically justified civil disobedience.Google Scholar
42 U.S.C. § 1305, Pub. L 104 – 193 § 1 et seq., August 22, 1996.Google Scholar
Dawson, S. M., “The Promise of Opportunity – and Very Little More: An Analysis of the New Welfare Law's Denial of Federal Public Benefits to Most Illegal Immigrants,” St. Louis University Law Journal 41 (1997): 10531079; Note, “Welfare Reform – Treatment of Legal Immigrants – Congress Authorizes States to Deny Public Benefits to Noncitizens and Excludes Legal Immigrants from Federal Aid Programs,” Harvard Law Review 110 (1997): 1191–1196. The law does make some exceptions for outpatient prenatal care and some services provided to children under some limited circumstances, and for services paid entirely by state resources in states that have explicitly authorized those payments by formal legislative action taken after the effective date of the Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act. Our client, alas, does not fall squarely within the relevant exceptions.Google Scholar
The Latin “Primum non nocere” was never part of the venerable Hippocratic Oath, but seems to have been a principle expressed by Galen. Today the Oath of Geneva prepared by the World Medical Association expresses a related principle: “The health of my patient will be my first consideration.” World Medical Association, International Code of Medical Ethics, available at <http://www.wma.net/e/policy/c8.htm> (last visited June 9, 2006).+(last+visited+June+9,+2006).>Google Scholar
The American Medical Association's Principles of Medical Ethics were amended in 2001 to add a new principle that reflects this notion: “A physician shall, while caring for a patient, regard responsibility to the patient as paramount.” American Medical Association's Principles of Medical Ethics VIII (2001).Google Scholar
See American College of Physicians, Ethics Manual (5th ed.); Annals of Internal Medicine 142, no. 7 (2005): 560–582, at 561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 571.Google Scholar
See 18 U.S.C. § 2 (a) (“Whoever commits an offense against the United States or aids, counsels, commands, induces, or procures its commission, is punishable as a principal.”)Google Scholar
“Lying Doctors,” CBS News: This Morning, October 21, 1999.Google Scholar
Hilzenrath, D., “Ethics: The Moral Dilemmas of Managed Care,” Washington Post, April 9, 1998, at H1.Google Scholar
See Ethics Manual, supra note 7, “Medicine and the Law.”.Google Scholar
For a general discussion of this possibility, see LaFave, W. R., Criminal Law (St. Paul: West, 2003): at 631.Google Scholar
For a discussion of the value of this trust, and its explicit recognition, see Hall, M. A., “Law, Medicine and Trust,” Stanford Law Review 55 (2002): 463527.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, for example, Canterbury v. Spence, 464 F.2d 772 (D.C. Cir. 1972) (adding the obligation to arrange for “informed consent” to the physician's obligation to diagnose and treat).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Wickline v. State, 192 Cal.App.3d 1630 (1986) (suggesting that yet another additional obligation of a physician might be to advocate for a patient to arrange for payment for medical care, at least under some circumstances).Google Scholar
Johnson, D., “Kevorkian Sentenced to 10 to 25 years in Prison,” N. Y. Times, April 14, 1999, at A1.Google Scholar
Thoreau, H. D., Political Writings, Rosenblum, Nancy L., ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
See 42 U.S.C. § § 1320A-7b.Google Scholar
See American Medical Association's Code of Medical Ethics, Sec. E-102, in Code of Medical Ethics: Annotated Current Opinions Including Principles of Medical Ethics, Fundamental Elements of the Physician-Patient Relationship and Rules of the Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs (Chicago: American Medical Association, 2004).Google Scholar
See Meier, D. E. Emmons, C. Quill, T., and Cassel, C. K., “A National Survey of Physician-Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the United States,” New England Journal of Medicine 338 (1998): 11931201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Federman, A., “Can't We Just Drop the Copay?” Virtual Mentor 8 (2006): 130134, available at <http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/category/15948.html> (last visited June 9, 2006).Google Scholar
Lachs, M. S. Sindelar, J. L., and Horwitz, R. I., “Forgiveness of Coinsurance: Charity or Cheating?” New England Journal of Medicine 322 (1990): 15991602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar