Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T03:51:43.368Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Autonomy and Connectedness: A Re-evaluation of Georgetown and its Progeny

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

In the late twentieth century the United States experienced a wave of cases concerning compelled obstetric interventions, cases which attracted much legal and philosophical interest. Behind and alongside them, however, lies a little known strand of authorities which concerns a parent wishing to refuse life-sustaining treatment and a hospital seeking to prevent this on the basis of the State's interest in protecting innocent third parties, usually the patient's dependent minor children. This issue appears to be unique to the United States. Although the leading case in point was influential in cases concerning compelled obstetric intervention, it has received little examination in its own right. This is a shame, since it spawned an intriguing line of cases worthy of reflection today.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Perhaps the most notable U.S. case was Re A.C. 533 A.2d 611 (D.C. App. 1987); 573 A.2d 1235 (D.C. App. 1990).Google Scholar
See, for example, Scott, R., Rights, Duties and the Body: Legal and Philosophical Reflections on Refusing Medical Treatment during Pregnancy (Oxford: Hart Publishing, forthcoming).Google Scholar
See, for example, Re A.C. (1987 and 1990) and Re Fetus Brown, 294 Ill. App. 3d 159 (Ill. App. 1 Dist. 1997).Google Scholar
Rather, it has often been considered by writers concerned with the problem of “maternal-fetal conflict,” See, for example, Rhoden, N., “The Judge in the Delivery Room: The Emergence of Court-Ordered Cesareans,” 74 California Law Review (1986) 19512030; Nelson, L. Buggy, B. Weil, C., “Forced Medical Treatment of Pregnant Women: ‘Compelling Each to Live as Seems Good to the Rest,’” 37 Hastings Law Journal. (1986) 703–763. For examples of literature touching on the Georgetown line of cases but not otherwise mentioned in this note, see, for example, Koehne, J., “Witnesses on Trial: Judicial Intrusion upon the Practices of Jehovah's Witness Parents,” (1993) 21 Florida State University Law Review 205–222; Rillo, T., “Case Comment: Constitutional Law: The Limits of a Patient's Right to Refuse Medical Treatment” (1994) 46 Florida Law Review 347–354.Google Scholar
331 F.2d 1000 (1964); 331 F.2d 1010 (1964).Google Scholar
Wons v. Public Health Trust of Dade County, 500 So .2d 679, 683 (Fla. App. 3 Dist, 1987), per Justice Newbold, as cited by Justice Hubbart.Google Scholar
211 N.Y. 125, 129–130 (1914).Google Scholar
464 F.2d 772 (1972).Google Scholar
Notably Re Quinlan, 355 A.2d 647 at 663, which gave the right to refuse medical treatment a privacy grounding, based on Roe v. Wade, 35 L.Ed 2d 147 (1973).Google Scholar
In Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health, 111 L.Ed.2d 224 (1990) the U.S. Supreme Court assumed the right to refuse treatment, but shifted the analysis away from privacy reasoning, holding that the question whether a person's right to refuse medical treatment is protected by the federal Constitution is properly analyzed in terms of the person's liberty interest under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, rather than in terms of a generalized right of privacy. Subsequent cases have gone both ways, adopting either the more traditional privacy analysis or the Cruzan approach; although some have suggested that there is no such liberty interest at all, holding that it was assumed in Cruzan: See, for example, Washington et al. v. Glucksberg et al., 138 L.Ed 772 (1997).Google Scholar
For instance in the 1977 case of Superintendent of Belchertown State School v. Saikewicz (370 N.E.2d at 425) Justice Liacos observes: “As distilled from the cases, the State has claimed an interest in: (1) the preservation of life; (2) the protection of the interests of innocent third parties; (3) the prevention of suicide; and (4) maintaining the ethical integrity of the medical profession.”Google Scholar
331 F.2d at 1008.Google Scholar
49 L.Ed. 643 (1904).Google Scholar
331 F.2d at 1008.Google Scholar
One set of academics has described the judge's conclusions as “lack[ing] any precedential foundation.” See Nelson, L. supra note 4 at 758.Google Scholar
Judge Washington filed a concurring statement. Judge Danaher voted to dismiss the petition for lack of a case or controversy. Judge Miller filed a dissenting opinion in which Judges Bastian and Burger concurred. Chief Justice Burger filed a statement in which Judges Miller and Bastian concurred.Google Scholar
331 F.2d at 1016, note 4.Google Scholar
Judge Miller, in his opinion dissenting from the court's decision to deny the petition for rehearing observed, at 1014: “These procedural defects are … fatal to the validity of the purported orders entered September 17 by a single judge when no appeal had actually been filed. … I object to the order which merely denies the petition for rehearing, without more, because it leaves in effect the two orders of September 17 as orders of this court which may be cited hereafter as precedents… for the summary administration of blood transfusions against the will of the patient. …”Google Scholar
Writing shortly after the case, one academic speculated as to the reasons for a finding of incompetence: “That an individual's choice is seemingly inconsistent with the general mores of society should not, in itself, afford a basis for a finding of non composmentis.” Case Comment: “Constitutional Law—Transfusions Ordered for Dying Woman over Religious Objections,” 113 University of Pennsylvania Law Review (1964) 290–297, 294. This is a notorious and pervasive problem in determinations of competence generally.Google Scholar
Kennedy, I. Grubb, A., Medical Law: Text with Materials (London: Butterworths, 2nd edition, 1994) at 372–374.Google Scholar
Re Osborne, 294 A.2d 372 (1972) at 375; Wons v. Public Health Trust of Dade County, 500 So.2d at 686; Re Dubreuil, 629 So.2d 819 at 824.Google Scholar
For a less favorable interpretation of the case, see Annas, G., “Forced Cesareans: The Most Unkindest Cut of All,” 12 Hastings Center Report (June 1982) 16, 17. He argues that Georgetown is illustrative of the poor quality of emergency judicial decisionmaking and notes that Judge Burger cited Justice Cardozo on judicial restraint. In a further article he suggests that when a judge is called upon to make a decision in an emergency situation, “he or she is acting much more like a lay person than a jurist”: “Protecting the Liberty of Pregnant Patients,” 316 New Engl. J. Med. (1987) 1213–1214, 1213. N. Rhoden notes two of the reasons I have cited in this paragraph—relating to patients' rights and the competence of the patient in Georgetown—and hence queries the precedential value of Georgetown (and other early cases), 1973 supra note 4.Google Scholar
Public Health Trust v. Wons, 541 So.2d 96 (S.Ct Fla 1989) at 97.Google Scholar
Wons v. Public Health Trust of Dade County, 500 So.2d at 683. Cited by Overton J, (diss.) in Public Health Trust v. Wons, 541 So.2d at 102.Google Scholar
331 F.2d at 1008, per Justice Wright.Google Scholar
Fosmire v. Nicoleau 551 N.E. 2d 77 (N.Y. C.A. 1990) at 83.Google Scholar
629 So.2d 819 (1993).Google Scholar
Id. at 829.Google Scholar
120 L.Ed.2d 674 (1992).Google Scholar
Id. at 698–699. See also the opinion of Justice Blackmun.Google Scholar
As noted by Judge Warner (dissenting) in the Court of Appeal of Florida in Re Dubreuil, 603 So.2d 538, 544 (1992).Google Scholar
603 So.2d at 545, citing J.V. v. State, 516 So.2d 1133 (Fla. 1st DCA 1987).Google Scholar
Case Comment, supra note 19 at 294.Google Scholar
294 A.2d 372 (D.C. C.A. 1972).Google Scholar
541 So.2d 96 (S.Ct Fla 1989).Google Scholar
500 So.2d 679 at 688, per Judge Hubbart.Google Scholar
564 N.E.2d 1017 (Sup. Jud. Ct Mass, 1991). In this case, which concerned a mother's decision to refuse a blood transfusion, the court found that there would be no abandonment of the minor child because the father, his sister and brother-in-law all supported her decision and were willing and able to take care of the child.Google Scholar
541 So.2d at 98.Google Scholar
529 A.2d 404 (N.J. S.Ct 1987).Google Scholar
Id. at 413, per Judge Garibaldi.Google Scholar
541 So.2d at 102.Google Scholar
500 So.2d 679 at 688, per Judge Hubbart.Google Scholar
551 N.E.2d 77 (N.Y. C.A. 1990).Google Scholar
Id. at 84.Google Scholar
Id. at 83.Google Scholar
In this regard, one academic has made the point that overriding parents' treatment refusals in order to prevent “abandonment” is unfair when other parents are allowed to “abandon” their children, for instance by putting them into foster care. Rhoden, N. supra note 4, 1974–5. The same argument is made by K. Lomond in “An Adult Patient's Right To Refuse Medical Treatment For Religious Reasons: The Limitations Imposed By Parenthood” (1993) 31 University of Louisville Journal of Family Law: At 665–683, who suggests that allowing a parent to have his/her child or children adopted could be a solution in the case where otherwise a child will have no family members to care for it (at 680).Google Scholar
551 N.E.2d at 83.Google Scholar
Id. at 84.Google Scholar
N. Rhoden made a similar point some four years earlier, supra note 4 at 1975.Google Scholar
551 N.E.2d at 84.Google Scholar
370 N.E.2d at 426, per Justice Liacos, footnote omitted. The case concerned an incompetent patient and the application of the substituted judgment doctrine.Google Scholar
“Running through all of these decisions, however, is the court's deeply imbedded belief, rooted in our constitutional traditions, that an individual has a fundamental right to be left alone so that he is free to lead his private life according to his own beliefs, free from unreasonable governmental interference.” 500 So.2d at 686–7, per Judge Hubbart, cited by Judge Ehrlich at 541 So.2d 98.Google Scholar
On this aspect see also Norwood Hospital v. Munoz, 564 N.E.2d 1017 in which Chief Justice Liacos cited his passage from Saikewicz and also cited a passage from Brophy v. New England Sinai Hospital, 497 N.E.2d 626 (1986), as follows: “The duty of the State to preserve life must encompass a recognition of an individual's right to avoid circumstances in which the individual [herself] would feel that efforts to sustain life demean or degrade [her] humanity.” At 1023.Google Scholar
541 So.2d at 103.Google Scholar
Id. at 104.Google Scholar
Id. at 100.Google Scholar
Id. at 102.Google Scholar
Raz, J., The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986): At 256.Google Scholar
Id. at 247.Google Scholar
Raz, J., “Right-based Moralities,” (1982) in Waldron, J., Theories of Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984): 182200, at 191.Google Scholar
Raz, J., “Rights and Individual Well-Being,” first published in 5 Ratio Juris 2 (July 1992), repr. in his Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994) 4459, 58–59.Google Scholar
603 So.2d 538 (1992); 629 So.2d 819 (1993).Google Scholar
“In this day and age where we have long since abandoned the notion that a wife is the husband's ‘property,’ I would think that it would be universally recognized that he cannot overrule her conscious decisions regarding her own body.” 603 So.2d 538 at 542; 602 So.2d 819 at 827.Google Scholar
603 So.2d at 541.Google Scholar
629 So.2d at 823.Google Scholar
Id. at 827.Google Scholar
Id. It might be noted that Chief Justice Barkett observed that “although not intended by the district court, its rationale could be read by some to perpetuate the damaging stereotype that a mother's role is one of caregiver, and the father's role is that of an apathetic, irresponsible, or unfit parent.” Id. at 828.Google Scholar
629 So.2d at 826.Google Scholar
Rhoden, N. supra note 4 at 1974.Google Scholar
See, for example, Grubb, A. “Treatment Decisions: Keeping it in the Family,” in Grubb, A. (ed.), Choices and Decisions in Health Care (Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, 1993): 3796, discussing other medical decision-making contexts.Google Scholar
For support for this view see, for example, the U.S. Supreme Court's decision in Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health, 111 L.Ed.2d 224 (1990). The court considered that a competent person has a constitutionally protected liberty interest in refusing medical treatment. Justice O'Connor (who concurred with the joint opinion) stressed that the liberty guaranteed by the Due Process Clause protects, “if anything,” a person's “deeply personal” decision to refuse unwanted medical treatment (at 249). See also the Court's abortion decision in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 120 L.Ed.2d 674 (1992), in which the joint opinion (Justices O'Connor, Kennedy and Souter) stressed that intimate decisions such as that of abortion, which concern the “meaning of procreation” are the subject of reasonable disagreement, stating that “… reasonable people will have differences of opinion about these matters.” In contrasting different views about abortion, the joint opinion emphasized that “[t]hese are intimate views with infinite variations” and stressed “their deep, personal character.” At 699, first emphasis in original; second added.Google Scholar
See Scott, R. supra note 2, chapter 7, regarding the issue of compelled caesareans.Google Scholar
As other scholars have noted, although it may sound rhetorical, in fact it is not rhetorical to describe the procedure of a compelled caesarean, or compelled donation of an organ by a parent to a born child, in these terms: “We describe the implications… this way, not as an exercise in inflammatory rhetoric, but to make evident the very harsh implications for pregnant women or parents of accepting the view in question.” Callahan, J.C. Knight, J.W., “Women, Fetuses, Medicine and the Law,” Holmes, H.B. Purdy, L., eds., Feminist Perspectives in Medical Ethics (Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1992): 224239 at 233.Google Scholar
114 Daily Wash Law Rptr. 2233 (D.C. Super.Ct. July 26, 1986). Published as appendix to Re A.C., 573 A.2d 1235, 1262 (D.C.App. 1990).Google Scholar
632 N.E.2d 326, 335 (Ill. App. 1 Dist. 1994), per Presiding Judge DiVito.Google Scholar
573 A.2d at 1244, note 8.Google Scholar
632 N.E.2d at 335. The point is also aptly put by Elias, S. Annas, G., in their Reproductive Genetics and the Law, who ask: “Do we really want to restrain, forcibly medicate, and operate on a competent, refusing adult? Such a procedure … is certainly brutish and not what one generally associates with medical care.” (At 259.)Google Scholar
294 Ill. App. 3d 159 (Ill. App. 1 Dist. 1997).Google Scholar
632 N.E.2d at 333.Google Scholar
For a detailed discussion applying Casey in the treatment context, see Scott, R. supra note 2, chapter 4.Google Scholar
For a different analysis, see Binder, N., “Note: Taking Relationships Seriously: Children, Autonomy, And The Right To A Relationship” (1994) 69 New York University Law Review 11501175. Binder argues that although the parent's interest is more compelling, protecting the parent's autonomy by allowing him/her to refuse medical treatment denies the “emergent autonomy interest” of the child (at 1174). Binder's concern is apparently with the child's “relational interest” with its parent. In the most obvious senses, clearly this cannot continue once a parent has died. But my analysis has tried to suggest that the recognition of the value and meaning of the individual parent's life can itself contribute both to the child's understanding of that relationship (though clearly age will be relevant here) and to the child's developing and future autonomy. Overall, however, Binder argues that it is primarily through the family that autonomy develops such that the value of the family inheres in the way it can promote the autonomy of all of its members. This is not inconsistent with my approach.Google Scholar
Lomond, K. supra note 47, who suggests that allowing a parent to have his/her child or children adopted could be a solution which would satisfy the State's interest in cases where otherwise a child will have no family members to care for it (at 680).Google Scholar
On rights as common goods see Raz, J. supra note 64.Google Scholar