Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T23:19:30.623Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ethical and Legal Aspects of Sperm Retrieval after Death or Persistent Vegetative State

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Several methods have been reported for extracting sperm from a man after he dies or enters a persistent vegetative state (PVS). Although such sperm retrieval could be performed for nonprocreative purposes, such as research, in this paper I focus on cases involving procreative intent. Since 1980, more than ninety cases have occurred in which family members requested sperm retrieval from patients who died or were irreversibly unconscious, with the intent that a wife, girlfriend, or other woman would be inseminated. Recently, the first report of pregnancy and birth following postmortem sperm retrieval appeared in the media.

In these cases, death or PVS typically is caused by anoxic injuries, trauma, or rapidly progressing infections.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

One method involves surgically exposing the vas deferens and irrigating them to obtain sperm. See Rothman, C.M., “A Method for Obtaining Viable Sperm in the Postmortem State,” Fertility and Sterility, 34 (1980): 512. Another approach involves rectal insertion of a probe to induce electroejaculation. See Ohl, D.A., “Electroejaculation,” Urology Clinics of North America, 20 (1993): 181–88. For further discussion of these and other techniques, see, for example, Chung, P.H., “Assisted Fertility Using Electroejaculation in Men with Spinal Cord Injury—A Review of Literature,” Fertility and Sterility, 64 (1995): 1–9; and Kerr, S.M., “Postmortem Sperm Procurement,” Journal of Urology, 157 (1997): 2154–58.Google Scholar
In the future, postmortem ovum retrieval may be possible, perhaps by removing ovaries and maturing the primary oocytes. I focus on sperm retrieval because, currently, it is technologically feasible and thus there is greater urgency to address it.Google Scholar
See Ohl, D.A., “Procreation after Death or Mental Incompetence: Medical Advance or Technology Gone Awry?,” Fertility and Sterility, 66 (1996): 889–95; Iserson, K.V., “Sperm Donation from a Comatose, Dying Man,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 7 (1998): 209–17; Pozda, R., “Sperm Collection in the Brain-Dead Patient,” Dimensions of Critical Care Nursing, 15 (1996): 98–104; Kerr, supra note 1; and Rothman, supra note 1.Google Scholar
See Allen, J.E., “Woman Pregnant By Sperm From Corpse,” AP Online, July 15, 1998; and Lota, L., “Baby Born from Dead Father's Sperm,” AP Online, Mar. 26, 1999.Google Scholar
Horner, J.S. Letter, , “Reply from Chairman of BMA's Medical Ethics Committee,” British Medical Journal, 313 (1996): 1477, at 1477. A version of this view is advocated by Sandra M. Webb, who states, “surely the collection and cryopreservation of sperm from these men should not be carried out unless they had given their prior consent for this, or appointed a proxy.” Webb, S.M., “Raising Sperm from the Dead,” Journal of Andrology, 17 (1996): 325–26, at 325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Brahams, D., “Widow Appeals over Denial of Right to Husband's Sperm,” Lancet, 348 (1996): 1164; and Davis, D.S., “Legal Trends in Bioethics,” Journal of Clinical Ethics, 8 (1997): 204–07, at 206.Google Scholar
See Webb, supra note 5, at 325.Google Scholar
See A.B. 8043, 1999–2000 Reg. Sess. (N.Y. 1999); S.B. 1121, 1999–2000 Reg. Sess. (N.Y. 1999); and Andrews, L.B., “The Sperminator,” New York Times Magazine, Mar. 28, 1999, at 62–65.Google Scholar
I am not claiming that, absent explicit prior consent, the inferred approval of the patient is necessary for the ethical justifiability of organ procurement. Rather, I am pointing out that if there is reasonably inferred approval, then organ procurement is respectful of the autonomy of the previously existing person.Google Scholar
See Strong, C., Ethics in Reproductive and Perinatal Medicine: A New Framework (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997): at 13–14.Google Scholar
See id. at 14, 96, 100–01; and Strong, C., “Cloning and Infertility,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 7 (1998): 279–93.Google Scholar
See, for example, Laucks, E.C., The Meaning of Children: Attitudes and Opinions of a Selected Group of U.S. University Graduates (Boulder: Westview, 1981); Arnold, F., The Value of Children: A Cross-National Study (Honolulu: East-West Population Institute, 1975); and Pohlman, E., “Motivations in Wanting Conceptions,” in Peck, E. and Senderowitz, J., eds., Pronatalism: The Myth of Mom and Apple Pie (New York: Crowell, 1974): at 159–90.Google Scholar
See, for example, Kahn, A., “Clone Mammals … Clone Man?,” Nature, 386 (1997): 119.Google Scholar
For more discussion of these six reasons, see Strong, supra note 10, at 18–22.Google Scholar
See id. at 27–40.Google Scholar
In the text, I do not address the special reasons why freedom not to procreate is important to women, because my focus is the freedom of men not to have their sperm retrieved. However, it should be noted that freedom not to procreate is particularly significant for women, based on the importance of the goal of gaining social and economic equality. Achievement of this goal requires, among other things, increased integration of women into positions of influence and authority. Because gestation and child rearing require much time and energy, the more heavily one is occupied with these activities, the more difficult it is to pursue education and careers leading to positions of authority. Society generally has put little pressure on men to assume their fair share of the task of child rearing. Given these considerations, procreative freedom for women is essential to the goal of gaining equality. A related but distinct consideration is that freedom not to procreate is important for women because bodily self-determination is implicated, and women bear the bodily burdens of gestation. See id.Google Scholar
This appears to have been a feature of the French case involving Alain and Corinne Parpalaix. See Hecht v. Superior Court, 16 Cal. App. 4th 836, 855–57 (1993). See also Shapiro, E.D. and Sonnenblick, B., “The Widow and the Sperm: The Law of Post-Mortem Insemination,” Journal of Law and Health, 1 (1986–87): 229–48, at 247.Google Scholar
Robertson, J., “Posthumous Reproduction,” Indiana Law Journal, 69 (1994): 1027–65, at 1032.Google Scholar
I am indebted to William H. Kutteh, M.D., for pointing out this.Google Scholar
It is conceivable that an inferred approval of the choice of recipient could be based on the man's prior selection of a person to make that choice for him. For example, a single man might designate a family member to make decisions for him concerning postmortem sperm retrieval and insemination, including decisions about selection of a procreative partner.Google Scholar
See Allen, J.E., “Woman Pregnant By Sperm From Corpse,” AP Online, July 16, 1998.Google Scholar
This type of scenario could take several forms: perhaps none of the family members can offer evidence concerning the man's wishes; or the wife and other family members may offer conflicting evidence. For an example of the latter type, see Andrews, supra note 8, at 64.Google Scholar
See Cohen, C.B., “Unmanaged Care: The Need to Regulate New Reproductive Technologies in the United States,” Bioethics, 11 (1997): 348–65.Google Scholar
See Feinberg, J., Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984): at 31–64; and Feinberg, J., “Wrongful Life and the Counterfactual Element in Harming,” Social Philosophy and Policy, 4 (1987): 145–78.Google Scholar
See Strong, supra note 10, at 90–94.Google Scholar
For a more thorough discussion of whether it is wrong to bring children into existence who will experience disadvantages, see id. at 90–96.Google Scholar
It should be noted that there are legal issues for which it would make a difference whether the man is brain dead or in PVS. In some jurisdictions, determinations of paternity and inheritance could differ, depending on whether conception occurs before or after the death of the genetic father. However, the main issues discussed in this section, concerning the ethical justifiability of sperm retrieval and insemination, do not seem to hinge on how these legal issues are resolved. For example, the ethics of carrying out a retrieval when it is reasonable to infer the man's consent and the wife has requested it would not typically depend significantly on how the question of legal paternity would be resolved.Google Scholar
See Kerr, supra note 1; and Allen, supra note 4.Google Scholar
See Blood, D., “Response to the Consultation Document of Professor McLean,” Human Reproduction, 13 (1998): 2654–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
A somewhat different statement was put forward by the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. See Ethics Committee, American Society for Reproductive Medicine, “Ethical Considerations of Assisted Reproductive Technologies,” Fertility and Sterility, 67, Supp. 1 (1997): 8S–9S. Specifically, it states, “A spouse's request that sperm or ova be obtained terminally or soon after death without the prior consent or known wishes of the deceased spouse need not be honored.” Id. at 9S (emphasis added). I am arguing for the stronger policy that requests should not be honored absent explicit prior or reasonably inferred consent.Google Scholar
One version of this problem might involve a wealthy patient's girlfriend who misrepresents the patient's wishes in an attempt to give birth to a child who would receive an inheritance. However, current laws concerning paternity and inheritance pose substantial obstacles for the girlfriend. If the patient is dead at the time of conception, then she faces the difficulty that many U.S. states have paternity laws that do not address posthumous conception. A few states have adopted the Uniform Parentage Act, which holds that the deceased man would be presumed to be the father of the child provided the couple had been married and the birth occurred within 300 days of the man's death. Thus, in no state does current law provide a basis for presuming that the deceased would be the legal father of a girlfriend's child. See, for example, Gibbons, J.A., “Who's Your Daddy? A Constitutional Analysis of Post-Mortem Insemination,” Journal of Contemporary Health Law and Policy, 14 (1997): 187210. A child conceived after the father's death could not inherit under current law, unless the decedent explicitly provided for such inheritance in a will. See Gilbert, S., “Fatherhood from the Grave: An Analysis of Postmortem Insemination,” Hofstra Law Review, 22 (1993): 521–65. A posthumously conceived child not provided for in a will could file suit against the father's estate, but it is unclear how the courts would handle such cases. If the patient is in a persistent vegetative state (and hence alive) at the time of conception, and the girlfriend is unmarried (not a common law wife), then similar legal conclusions would hold. Current law would not presume that the patient is the legal father, and the child would not inherit unless provided for in a will or a claim in court were successful.Google Scholar
It might be asked whether a signed card would constitute explicit prior consent. In reply, consent ordinarily is understood as involving several elements that would not be present in simply signing a card. First, consent is regarded as an agreement given to one or more specific identifiable parties, usually an identifiable physician. Thus, typically there is a meeting of the minds, which would not be present in simply signing a card. Second, for consent to be valid, the consenter must be adequately informed by the receiver of consent concerning the nature of the proposed procedure, its chances of success, its costs, and other information relevant to informed consent. Moreover, in cases involving other types of prior signed statements, courts have refrained from regarding the statements as constituting consent. In particular, living wills have not been regarded as consent documents, but as evidence used in making substituted judgments about withholding life-preserving treatment from now-incompetent patients. See 49 A.L.R. 4th 812, 815 (1986).Google Scholar
See 25A C.J.S. Dead Bodies § 3 (1966).Google Scholar
See id. § 2.Google Scholar
See O'Carroll, T.L., “Over My Dead Body: Recognizing Property Rights in Corpses,” Journal of Health and Hospital Law, 29 (1996): 238–45, at 239. See also 54 A.L.R. 4th 1214, 1216 (1987).Google Scholar
See O'Carroll, , id. at 239.Google Scholar
See 22 Am. Jur. 2d Dead Bodies § 32 (1988); and 18 A.L.R. 4th 858, 862 (1982).Google Scholar
See 25A C.J.S. Dead Bodies § 2 (1966); and O'Carroll, supra note 35, at 239.Google Scholar
See 25A C.J.S. Dead Bodies §§ 2, 3.Google Scholar
See Uniform Anatomical Gift Act, 8A U.L.A. § 4 (Supp. 1991).Google Scholar
See 7 A.L.R. 3d 747, 749–50 (1966); and 54 A.L.R. 3d 1037 (1973).Google Scholar
For a discussion of this issue, see Robertson, supra note 18, 1041–42.Google Scholar
See 49 A.L.R. 4th 812, 815 (1986); Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 So. 2d 160 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 1978), aff'd 379 So. 2d 359 (Fla. 1980); and Kennedy Hospital v. Bludworth, 452 So. 2d 921 (Fla. 1984).Google Scholar
See 46 A.L.R. 5th 793, 803–04 (1997).Google Scholar
See id. at 804–05. The best interest standard also applies when the next of kin consents to a medical procedure on an incompetent for the benefit of a third party. See 4 A.L.R. 5th 1000 (1992).Google Scholar