Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T21:03:26.147Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Coercing Future Freedom: Consent and Capacities for Autonomous Choice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

In this paper I examine some of the significant moral concerns inherent in cases of treatment refusal involving patients with psychotic disorders. In particular, I explore the relevance of the principle of autonomy in such situations. After exploring the concept of autonomy and explaining its current and historical significance in a health care setting, I argue that because autonomous choice depends for its existence upon certain human functions such as the ability to reason, judge, and assess consequences, patients cannot be said to be making free and autonomous decisions if these capacities are compromised. I contend further that because psychotic disorders have the potential to compromise these functions in the future, it is appropriate, in some limited cases, to coerce patients with psychotic disorders to undergo treatment in order to preserve their future decisionmaking capacities and to protect their ability to recognize and respect the autonomy of others.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Lamb, R. and Weinberger, L., “Mental Health Courts as a Way to Provide Treatment to Violent Persons with Severe Mental Illness” JAMA 300, no. 6 (2008): 772–724.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 772.Google Scholar
Id., at 772.Google Scholar
I cover much of this information about the importance of autonomy in health care and the ways in which these notions are complicated with respect to mental illness in Epright, M. C., “Caring about Mental Illness: Autonomy, Freedom and Care,” (Re) Interpretations: The Shapes of Justice in Women's Experience (Newcastle-upon-Tyne, U.K.: Cambridge Scholar's Press, 2008): 243344.Google Scholar
See especially Beauchamp, T. and Childress, J., The Principles of Biomedical Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994).Google Scholar
I outline this concern at length in Epright, M. C., “Bioethics and Justice: Economics, Care, and Conflict,” Biomedical Ethics Humanist Perspectives (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2006).Google Scholar
For an excellent collection of essays on the Cowart case, see Kliever, L. D., Dax's Case: Essays in Medical Ethics and Human Meaning (Dallas: Southern Methodist University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
This conversation occurred during an ethics consultation. The physician in question was an oncologist who honestly wanted to do what was best for his patient. When I pointed out that his claim was paternalistic, he stated that “I didn't go into medicine to kill my patients.” Such an example indicates that although we have come a long way, there is more work to be done with respect to teaching physicians the importance of patient autonomy.Google Scholar
Amador, X. F. et al., “Assessment of Insight in Psychosis,” American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 6 (June 1993): 873879, at 873.Google Scholar
Pini, S. et al., “Insight Into Illness in Schizophrenia, Schizoaffective Disorder, and Mood Disorders with Psychotic Features,” American Journal of Psychiatry 158, no. 1 (January 2001): 122125, at 122. See also, Young, D. A. et al., “Further Parameters of Insight and Neuropsychological Deficit in Schizophrenia and Other Chronic Mental Diseases,” Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases 186, no. 1 (1998): 44–50; Amador, X. F. et al., “Awareness of Illness in Schizophrenia, Schizoaffective and Mood Disorders,” Archives of General Psychiatry 51, no. 10 (1994): 826–836; and David, A. et al., “Insight and Psychotic Illness: Cross-Sectional and Longitudinal Associations,” British Journal of Psychiatry 167, no. 5 (1995): 621–628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Amador, et al., supra note 8.Google Scholar
Id., at 877 See Pini, et al., supra note 10, at 123–124.Google Scholar
Lamb, R. H. and Weinberger, L. E., “Mental Health Courts as a Way to Provide Treatment to Violent persons with Severe Mental Illness,” JAMA 300, no. 6 (2008): 772–724. See also, Elbogen, E. B. et al., “The Impact of Perceived Need for Treatment on Risk of Arrest and Violence among People with Severe Mental Illness,” Criminal Justice Behavior 34, no. 2 (2007): 197–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id. (Lamb and Weinberger), at 722. See also, Pia, L. and Tarnietto, M., “Unawareness in Schizophrenia: Neuropsychological and Neuroanatomical Findings,” Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 60, no. 5 (2006): 531537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yen, C.-F. et al., “Correlates of Insight Among Patients with Bipolar I Disorder in Remission,” Journal of Affective Disorders 78, no. 1 (2004): 5760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinstock, R., Copelan, R., and Bagheri, A., “Competence to Give Informed Consent for Medical Procedures,” Bulletin of the American Academy of Psychiatry Law 12, no. 2 (1984): 117125; Roth, L. H., Meisel, A., and Lidz, C. W., “Tests of Competency to Consent to Treatment,” American Journal of Psychiatry 134 (1977): 279–284.Google Scholar
It must be noted that most of the data that I will cite is derived not from studies of patients who like Hyde, have schizoaffective disorder, but from patient's with mood disorders (of which schizoaffective disorder is one), bipolar disorder, or schizophrenia (both of which are related to schizoaffective disorder). Few neuroimaging studies have been done specifically upon patients with schizoaffective disorder, but the disorders mentioned above are directly related to this disorder, particularly with respect to psychotic features, which are the object of my argument.Google Scholar
See especially, Sung, L., Lyoo, I. K. et al., “Regional Cerebral Cortical Thinning in Bipolar Disorder,” Bipolar Disorders 8, no. 1 (2006): 65–74 and Strakowski, S. M., “The Functional Neuroanatomy of Bipolar Disorder: A Review of Neuroimaging Findings,” Molecular Psychiatry 10, no. 1(2005): 105–116.Google Scholar
See especially, Drevets, W. et al., “Subgenual Prefrontal Cortex Abnormalities in Mood Disorders,” Nature 386, no. 6627 (1997): 824827; Lim, K. O. et al., “Cortical Gray Matter Deficit in Patients with Bipolar Disorder,” Schizophrenia Research 40, no. 3 (1999): 219–227; Coffman, J. A. et al., “Cognitive Impairment and Cerebral Structure in Bipolar Disorder,” Biological Psychiatry 27, no. 11 (1990): 1188–1196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rajkowska, G., “Cell Pathology in Bipolar Disorder,” Bipolar Disorders 4, no. 3 (2002): 105116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agartz, I. et al., “Abnormal Brain White Matter in Schizophrenia: A Diffusion Tensor Imaging Study,” Clinical Neuroscience and Neuropathology 12, no. 10 (2001): 22512254, and Zipursky, R. B. et al., “Widespread Cerebral Gray Matter Volume Deficits in Schizophrenia,” Archives of General Psychiatry 49, no. 3 (1992): 40–47, and Gur, R. E. et al., “Reduced Dorsal and Orbital Prefrontal Gray Matter Volumes in Schizophrenia,” Archives of General Psychiatry 57, no. 8 (2000): 761–768.Google Scholar
Cotter, D. R. et al., “Glial Cell Abnormalities in Major Psychiatric Disorders: The Evidence and Implications,” Brain Research Bulletin 55, no. 5 (2001): 585595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rajkowska, G., “Cell Pathology in Bipolar Disorder,” Bipolar Disorders 4, no. 5 (2002): 105116; Bearden, C. E. et al., “Greater Cortical Gray Matter Density in Lithium-Treated Patients,” Biological Psychiatry 62, no. 1 (2007): 7–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pfenning, A. et al., “Neurocognitive Impairment and Dementia in Mood Disorders,” Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 19, no. 4 (2007): 373382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart discusses the problems associated with the so-called autonomous decision to sell one's self into a situation whereby one would never have the ability to make future decisions. See On Liberty, at 106–107 in The Basic Writings of John Stuart Mill (New York: Random House, Inc., 2002).Google Scholar
Elbogen, E. B. et al., “the Impact of Perceived Need for Treatment on Risk of Arrest and Violence among People with Severe Mental Illness,” Criminal Justice Behavior 34, no. 2 (2007): 197210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar