Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T16:25:38.287Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chimeras, Moral Status, and Public Policy: Implications of the Abortion Debate for Public Policy on Human/Nonhuman Chimera Research

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Moral status is the moral value that something has in its own right, independently of the interests or concerns of others. Research using human embryonic stem cells (hESCs) implicates issues about moral status because the current method of extracting hESCs involves the destruction of a human embryo, the moral status of which is contested. Moral status issues can also arise, however, when hESCs are transplanted into embryonic or fetal animals, thereby creating human/ nonhuman stem cell chimeras (“chimeras” for short). In particular, one concern about chimera research is that it could confer upon an animal the moral status of a normal human adult, but then impermissibly fail to accord the animal the protections it merits in virtue of its enhanced status. Understanding the public policy implications of this ethical conclusion is complicated by the fact that certain views about the moral status of the embryo cannot legitimately be used to justify public policy decisions. Arguments like those employed in the abortion debate for the conclusion that abortion should be legally permissible even if abortion is not morally permissible also support, to a more limited degree, a liberal policy on hESC research involving the creation of chimeras.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

For brevity, I omit “nonhuman” from “nonhuman animals.”Google Scholar
For a full discussion of all of the extant ethical arguments regarding chimeras, see Streiffer, R., s.v. “Human/Nonhuman Chimeras,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, available at <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/chimeras/> (last visited March 24, 2010).Google Scholar
I say “novel” to set aside traditional animal ethics issues arising from straightforward harms to the interests of animals.Google Scholar
Streiffer, R., “At the Edge of Humanity: Human Stem Cells, Chimeras, and Moral Status,” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 15, no. 4 (2005): 347370, at 354 [hereinafter cited as At the Edge of Humanity].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
It is often claimed that those opposing hESC research adopt a potentiality view of moral status, according to which being an organism with the potential to develop into a person is sufficient for full moral status. Undoubtedly some opponents do hold such a view, but it has also become clear from the pro-life community's rejection of altered nuclear transfer and somatic cell nuclear transfer that potentiality views strike many of them as unacceptably inegalitarian, failing to secure basic rights for all human beings regardless of their developmental potential. For further discussion see Streiffer, R., “An Ethical Evaluation of Altered Nuclear Transfer-Cdx2,” World Stem Cell Report (2008): 115118 and Hyun, I., Kung, K., “Human Research Cloning, Embryos, and Embryo-Like Artifacts,” Hastings Center Report 36, no. 5 (2006): 3441.Google Scholar
Because we are assuming that animals have a lower degree of moral status than normal adult humans, it follows that animals do not currently posses those capacities, for if they did, they would already have full moral status.Google Scholar
National Research Council and Institute of Medicine of the National Academies, Committee on Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research, Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research (Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press, 2005) at 33 [hereinafter cited as the National Academies' Guidelines]; see At the Edge of Humanity, supra note 4, at 356.Google Scholar
For a full defense of this principle, see At the Edge of Humanity, supra note 4, at 358361.Google Scholar
Robert, J. S., “The Science and Ethics of Making Part-Human Animals in Stem Cell Biology,” The FASEB Journal 20, no. 7 (2006): 838845, at 842.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, R., Ethics and Regulations of Clinical Research 2nd ed. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986): at 6793.Google Scholar
James, D., Noggle, S., Swigut, T., and Brivanlou, A., “Contribution of Human Embryonic Stem Cells to Mouse Blastocysts,” Developmental Biology 295, no. 1 (2006): 90102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
“Following from our work, it is feasible that mouse/human chimeras could be generated in which hESCs are engrafted into pre-implantation stage mouse embryos and distributed throughout the host anatomy through gastrulation. This may allow for chimeras in which hESC derivatives are ‘seeded’ into an array of developmental niches within a viable mouse, which would be of considerable value for the modeling of human development and disease in live animals.” And “[I]n order to further explore the utility of embryonic chimeras as a vehicle for examining the emergence and behavior of human cell types, we must characterize the extent to which human cells can contribute to a viable mouse–human chimera. Allowing progression of chimeras to later developmental time points would indicate whether hESC derivatives are capable of integrating functionally into host anatomy.” Id., at 100.Google Scholar
See the National Academies' Guidelines, supra note 7, at 41.Google Scholar
Greene, M. et al., “Moral Issues of Human Non-Human Primate Neural Grafting,” Science 309, no. 5733 (2005): 385386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
International Society for Stem Cell Research, “Guidelines for the Conduct of Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research,” December 21, 2006, available at <http://www.isscr.org/guidelines/ISSCRhESCguidelines2006.pdf> (last visited March 25, 2010).+(last+visited+March+25,+2010).>Google Scholar
Hyun, I., Taylor, P., Testa, G., Dickens, B., Jung, K., McNab, A., Robertson, J., Skene, L., and Zoloth, L., “Ethical Standards for Human-to-Animal Chimera Experiments in Stem Cell Research,” Cell Stem Cell 1, no. 2 (2007): 159163, at 162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
National Institutes of Health, National Institutes of Health Guidelines for Human Stem Cell Research, 2009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brownback, S., “Human-Animal Hybrid Prohibition Act of 2009,” S. 1435, available at <http://frwebgate.access.gpo.gov/cgi-bin/getdoc.cgi?dbname=111_cong_bills&docid=f:s1435is.txt.pdf> (last visited March 25, 2010).Google Scholar
Wertheimer, R., “Understanding the Abortion Argument,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1, no. 1 (1971): 6795, at 94 [hereinafter cited as Understanding the Abortion Argument].Google Scholar
Id., at 92.Google Scholar
Id., at 94.Google Scholar
Gutmann, A. and Thompson, D., “Moral Conflict and Political Consensus,” Ethics 101, no. 1 (1990): 6488, at 73. Note that it is standard in the philosophy literature to use “fetus” to refer to the conceptus, the product of fertilization, from conception to delivery.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Understanding the Abortion Argument, supra note 19, at 94.Google Scholar
Ronald Green has also persuasively argued that fertilization is an event with indeterminate temporal boundaries. But such vagueness is quickly resolved as fertilization proceeds beyond any reasonable cut-off point, whereas the kind of indeterminacy being discussed here would persist throughout the organism's lifetime. See Green, R., The Human Embryo Research Debates: Bioethics in the Vortex of Controversy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Sapontzis, S. F., Morals, Reason, and Animals (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1987): at 2746.Google Scholar
See Understanding the Abortion Argument, supra note 19, at 77.Google Scholar
Prentice, E., Crouse, D., and Mann, M., “Scientific Merit Review: The Role of the IACUC,” ILAR News 34, no. 1–2 (1992): 1519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Streiffer, R., “Academic Freedom and Academic-Industry Relationships in Biotechnology,” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 16, no. 2 (2006): 129149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See the National Academies' Guidelines, supra note 7, at 46.Google Scholar
For an argument that great apes are borderline persons, and consequently that a large range of research on them is impermissible, see DeGrazia, D., “Human-Animal Chimeras: Human Dignity, Moral Status, and Species Prejudice,” Metaphilosophy 38, nos. 2–3 (2007): 309329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, R., Life's Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom (New York: Vintage Books, 1993) [hereinafter cited as Life's Dominion].Google Scholar
Id., at 154159.Google Scholar
Id., at 153.Google Scholar
Id., at 151153.Google Scholar
Brighouse, H., School Choice and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000): at 7–8; Streiffer, R. and Hedemann, T., “The Political Import of Intrinsic Objections to Genetically Engineered Food,” Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 18, no. 2 (2005): 191210, at 197–198. It should be noted that by “purpose” and “intent,” I am not speaking of the beliefs motivating particular legislators, but rather of the rational reconstruction of the aim of the policy. Much of Life's Dominion consists of empirical arguments about how to best interpret the beliefs actually motivating the various parties to the abortion debate. Such sociological arguments are relevant to whether legislators are acting permissibly in supporting legislation, but they do not settle the question of whether there are, in fact, legitimate justifications for banning abortion. The presence of an illegitimate motive, unlike the presence of an illegitimate intent or purpose, does not entail that the legislation is illegitimate.Google Scholar
Rawls, J., Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), at 199–200 [hereinafter cited as Political Liberalism].Google Scholar
Stroud, S., “Dworkin and Casey on Abortion,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, no. 2 (1996): 140170, at 152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robertson, J. A., “Autonomy's Dominion: Dworkin on Abortion and Euthanasia,” Law & Social Inquiry 19, no. 2 (1994): 457486, at 472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Streiffer, R., “Informed Consent and Federal Funding for Stem Cell Research,” Hastings Center Report 38, no. 3 (2008): 4047.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, J., “Abortion,” Boston Review 20, no. 3 (1995): 1115, available at <http://bostonreview.net/BR20.3/thomson.html> (last visited March 31, 2010). Thomson does not explicitly say that no other grounds are available that would justify banning abortion and which could not also be reasonably rejected, but if the argument is to be valid, then something similar to that principle must be added.Google Scholar
Rawls, J., “Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus,” in Copp, D., Hamptom, J., and Roemer, J., eds., The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993): 233255; see Rawls, , supra note 36; Cohen, J., “Moral Pluralism and Political Consensus,” in Copp, D., Hampton, J., and Roemer, J., eds. The Idea of Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993): 270291.Google Scholar
Rawls, J., “The Idea of Public Reason,” in Bohman, J. and Rehg, W., eds., Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997): 93141, at 97.Google Scholar
Gutmann, A. and Thompson, D., “Moral Conflict and Political Consensus,” Ethics 101, no. 1 (1990): 6488, at 73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Rawls, , supra note 36, at xlvi, 50, 137, and 226. See Scanlon, T., “Contractualism and Utilitarianism,” in Sen, A. and Williams, B., eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982): 103128, at 111, for why the principle should be articulated in terms of “cannot reasonably reject” instead of Rawls's more common locution of “can reasonably accept.”Google Scholar
Thomson, J. J., “Judith Jarvis Thomson Replies,” Boston Review 20, no. 5 (1995), available at <http://bostonreview.net/BR20.4/Thomson.html> (last visited March 31, 2010).Google Scholar
Rawls, J., “The Idea of Public Reason,” in Bohman, J., Rehg, W., eds., Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1997): 93141, at 9495.Google Scholar