Id. at 5–6. The ASBH report does not rely on a specific ethical theory to support the ethics facilitation approach (notwithstanding the assumptions that may be identified in the report or the implications that may follow from it). However, a similar model of clinical ethics consultation is based on the discourse ethics of Jürgen Habermas. See
Casarett, D.J. Daskal, F., and
Lantos, J.,
“Experts in Ethics? The Authority of the Clinical Ethicist,” Hastings Center Report,
28,
no. 6 (
1998):
6–
11 (arguing that discourse ethics grounds consensus and consensus building in moral theory). Habermas describes discourse ethics as an effort “to reformulate Kant's ethics by grounding moral norms in communication.” Habermas J., Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. Lenhardt C. and Nicholsen S.W. (Cambridge: MIT Press,
2nd ed., 1990): at 195. Two principles are central to that effort. The first is the basic principle of discourse ethics which posits that “only those norms may claim to be valid that could meet with the consent of all affected in their role as participants in a practical discourse.”
Id. at 197. The second is the corresponding “principle of universalization,” which functions as a rule of argumentation and states: “For a norm to be valid, the consequences and side[-] effects of its general observance for the satisfaction of each person's particular interests must be acceptable to all.”
Id. This rule, according to Habermas, replaces Kant's formulation of the categorical imperative (“‘Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law’”), but, like the categorical imperative, “plays the part of a principle of justification that discriminates between valid and invalid norms in terms of their universalizability.”
Id. Accordingly, Habermas defends discourse ethics as an ethics, with an affinity to Kantian ethics, that is deontological, cognitivist, formalist, and universalist. See
id. at 195–211 (examining Kantian ethics and discourse ethics in terms of Hegel's critique of Kant's moral philosophy). Although discourse ethics is the foundation for Casarett, Daskal, and Lantos's model of ethics consultation, Dewey's philosophy underpins Moreno's bioethical naturalism, see
supra note 21, and clinical pragmatism, see
supra notes 22–27 and accompanying text and
infra note 57. The philosophies of Habermas and Dewey warrant comparison and further reflection in terms of their implications for bioethics. For example, if their respective philosophies each support an appeal to consensus, then one may ask whether consensus can be defined as a mid-level principle according to the criteria that Tom Beauchamp and James Childress use to define autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, and justice as mid-level principles; namely, principles that are part of the common morality and accepted in different ethical theories. See
Beauchamp and Childress,
supra note 3, at 100–02, 110. Although this kind of analysis would contribute to consensus theory and be germane to my article, a fuller discussion of Dewey and Habermas exceeds the scope of this article.
CrossRefGoogle Scholar