Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T12:44:58.773Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bioethics and International Human Rights

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Increasingly, the world seems to shrink due to our ever-expanding technological and communication capacities. Correspondingly, our awareness of other cultures increases. This is especially true in the field of bioethics because the technological progress of medicine throughout the world is causing dramatic and challenging intersections with traditionally held values. Think of the use of pregnancy monitoring technologies like ultrasound to abort fetuses of the “wrong” sex in India (where a female's dowry can be a tremendous burden to the family), the sale of human organs in and between countries, or the disjunction between the haves and the have-nots in South America when it comes to bone marrow transplants, while thousands of other children die for want of fundamental goods and services like clean water, basic inoculations, and food itself.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

See Ocloo, E., “Chronic Undernutrition and the Young,” Proceedings of the Nutrition Society, 52 (1993): 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Blackhall, L., “Ethnicity and Attitudes Toward Patient Autonomy,” JAMA, 274 (1995): 844–45; and Murphy, S.T., “Ethnicity and Advance Care Directives,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 24 (1996): 108–17.Google Scholar
See Pellegrino, E.D., “Intersections of Western Biomedical Ethics and World Culture: Problematic and Possibility,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 1 (1992): 191–96.Google Scholar
Engelhardt, H.T. Jr., “Understanding Faith Traditions in the Context of Health Care: Philosophy as a Guide for the Perplexed,” in Marty, M.E. Vaux, K.L., eds., Health/Medicine and the Faith Traditions (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1982): 163–84.Google Scholar
Norris, P.F., “Culture and Religion: Their Role in Ethics,” Health Care Ethics USA, 4, no. 1 (1996): At 5.Google Scholar
See generally Veatch, R., ed., Cross Cultural Perspectives in Medical Ethics (Boston: Jones and Bartlett, 1989).Google Scholar
“Human Rights Took a Beating in 1992: Group Condemns 110 Nations for Torture,” Chicago Tribune, July 9, 1993, at 2.Google Scholar
See “UN Paper on Rights is Criticized,” Chicago Tribune, June 3, 1993, at 20.Google Scholar
See “Human Rights Watch Looks Within,” The New Yorker, 64 (1993): 5354.Google Scholar
See generally Finkielkraut, A., The Defeat of the Mind, trans. by Friedlander, J. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995).Google Scholar
Without secular protections, religious bigotry all too often results. Consider the Rushdie affair. Salman Rushdie wrote The Satanic Verses, which was highly critical of the Prophet Muhammed, and sexually offensive to Moslem leaders. Rushdie was condemned to death by Iran and the Ayatollah. This led to international withdrawals of embassies by Western European countries. Internal debates about the freedom of the press and the freedom of expression occurred especially in England and the United States. Workers at mall-based book stores were threatened by calls and bomb scares. And the book was kept off the shelves. Full-page advertisements were taken out by Waldenbooks defending its decision to sell the book. Similar advertisements were taken out by Moslems defending their religion and their religious sensibilities. A similar occurrence involved the writings of Taslima Nasrin of Bangladesh, a physician and nonbeliever who is critical of Moslem views of women and marriage. She is now in hiding in Sweden. As she said of her own life, “They've taken everything from me … my innocence, my youth, now my freedom.” See Weaver, M.A., “A Fugitive from Injustice,” The New Yorker, 70 (1989): At 60. Much of the Western reflection on the Rushdie and Nasrin affairs betrayed a note of cultural superiority. We admonished fundamentalist Moslems because they had not entered the golden era of responsible, international citizenship. Amnesty International took up the authors' causes. Protests were lodged by Western governments with Iran and Bangladesh. Some countries threatened to cut off economic assistance. Yet, not that long ago, the power of Christianity was allied to the state for almost 1,000 years, during which time many persons were tortured and killed, put on racks and burned at the stake, for being different or refusing to follow Christianity. We escaped the “medieval and violent darkness” of Christianity, in the words of one commentator, “by depriving Christian religious authorities of political and legal power over the community.” See Dyer, G., “The Secularizing Evolution that Includes Islam,” Chicago Tribune, Mar. 20, 1989, at 13.Google Scholar
“Human Rights Watch Looks Within,” supra note 9, at 54.Google Scholar
A report of blows exchanged at a news conference at the 50th session of the United Nations Commission on Human Rights demonstrates just how difficult the process of developing a human rights basis for international and intercultural bioethics will be. A representative of the Sudanese National Islamic Front had just finished an extended interruption of a report on conditions in the Sudan, when he was attacked by a rival group member. In the words of a columnist, this “disorderly exchange at the usually somber commission lifted the thin veneer of decorum over the confrontations between victims and perpetrators….” The most heinous violations of human rights occur in the areas of the world we ignore most. See Brown, B.A., “Human-Rights Abuse is ‘Business as Usual’ in Much of the World,” Chicago Tribune, Apr. 15, 1994, at 19.Google Scholar
Early-sixteenth-century Spanish theologians Francesco de Vitoria and Dominic Suarez both proposed an international law based on the laws and customs of countries (jus gentium) and on laws that transcend individual nations (jus naturale). These ideas were codified by Grotius at that time. Human rights spread more widely with the American Revolution, and most explicitly with the French Revolution's Declaration of Individual and Civil Rights (August 24, 1789). There was tremendous progress during the next two centuries, continuously extending human rights, even into international law.Google Scholar
See Possenti, V., “Human Rights and Human Nature,” Contemporary Philosophy, 17 (1995): 410. Vittorio Possenti distinguishes two traditions in human rights, the secular and the religious, the latter deriving human rights from a law built into human nature by a Creator God. Thus Thomas Aquinas, in the latter tradition, can derive human rights from inclinations of human nature—persistence in being, union between man and woman, generation and education of children, social character of human nature, and the desire for the truth. From these he argues for fundamental human rights respectively to life, to have a family, to procreate and educate one's children, to have a place in society and a useful job, and to develop one's own intelligence in a search for truth. See Aquinas, , de lege, in his Summa Theologiae, 1,2ae, QQ 93–105.Google Scholar
Evolutionary biology is the notion that the specific nature of, for instance, a horse or a human being evolves and changes over eons.Google Scholar
See Atlas, T., “China Dismal on Rights, U.S. Admits,” Chicago Tribune, Mar. 7, 1996, at 1, 16.Google Scholar
See Boudreau, D., “International Medical Community Condemns Death Row Donations in China,” Nephrology News & Issues, 29 (1995): 12.Google Scholar
See Anonymous, “China: BBC Wrong About Inmate Organs,” Chicago Tribune, Nov. 24, 1994, at 28. In this wire service story, Chinese officials said that the British Broadcasting Corporation's (BBC) documentary on use of prisoners' organs was fabricated. The BBC claimed that 90 percent of executed criminals are organ donors, while the Chinese said that they are rarely donors, and only with prisoners' or their relatives' consent.Google Scholar
See Schmetzer, U., “U.S. Trade Visit Spurs China Dissidents,” Chicago Tribune, Aug. 27, 1994, at 1, 6.Google Scholar
See Boudreau, , supra note 19.Google Scholar
See Anonymous, supra note 20.Google Scholar
See Levine, R.J., “Informed Consent: Some Challenges to the Universal Validity of the Western Model,” Law, Medicine & Health Care, 19 (1991): 207–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Thayil, J., “Kidneys for Sale,” Asiaweek, Apr. 22, 1994, at 40–49.Google Scholar
Gostin, L., “Informed Consent, Cultural Sensitivity, and Respect for Persons,” JAMA, 274 (1995): At 844–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Marshall, P. Thomasma, D. Jhabar, A., “Marketing Human Organs: The Autonomy Paradox,” Theoretical Medicine, 17 (1996): 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Other strategies included birth control pills, intrauterine devices, and the like. About 90 million children are born each year, contributing to urgency.Google Scholar
Rowley, S.M., “Count on Controversy at Population Forum: Religious, Cultural, Economic Clashes Abound on Eve of UN Session in Cairo,” Chicago Tribune, Sept. 4, 1994, at 3.Google Scholar
Regarding efforts to reach a compromise with the Vatican on reproductive statements at the Egyptian conference, U.S. Vice President Al Gore remarked that there likely would never be “full agreement [with the Vatican] on contraception and the American woman's right to choose.” Rowley, S.M., “U.S., Vatican Seeking Compromise on Abortion,” Chicago Tribune, Sept. 7, 1994, at 1, 12. Although the Vatican recognizes the difficulties women have carrying a child to term, it emphasizes counseling, free medical care, social support, and adoption. About women's challenges today, the Vatican says, “Such difficulties do not warrant the violation of the right to life.” Id. at 12.Google Scholar
See Evans, J.R., “International Challenges and Opportunities in Health,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 21 (1993): 1015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colwell, R.R. Pramer, D., “Back to the Future with UNESCO,” Science, 265 (1994): At 1047.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ironically, within scientifically based civilizations, there is an increasing rapprochement between science and religion. See Somerville, M., “Genetics, Reproductive Technologies, Euthanasia, and the Search for a New Social Paradigm,” Social Science and Medicine, 42 (1996): Ix–xii.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowley, S.M., “Stirring Call to Empower Every Woman,” Chicago Tribune, Sept. 6, 1994, at 1.Google Scholar
This commercialization extends to animal body parts. A good example is Baxter Healthcare Corporation's alliance with a biotechnology company to produce pigs with hearts and other organs that can be readily transplanted into human beings. DNX Corporation, the partner, has already used pig livers to filter the blood of human patients with terminal liver disease, and has bioengineered pigs with human hemoglobin as part of their blood. This is now an experimental therapy. After all, if we can eat pigs, and already use their heart valves for transplant, the reasoning goes, why not use them to save lives in other ways as well?Google Scholar
See News and Comment, “Rules on Embryo Research Due Out,” Science, 265 (1994): 1024–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cross-species fertilization includes creating human beings using cow eggs and the like. Pigs and cows have already been created with human immunosystems. The creation of research embryos has not been ruled out in the United States, nor has human cloning, although these have been condemned by political leaders and other countries. See Neikirk, W., “Senate Opts Not to Vote on Proposed Cloning Ban,” Chicago Tribune, Feb. 12, 1998, at 4; and Beck, J., “Cloning is Not the Path to Immortality,” Chicago Tribune, Jan. 15, 1998, at 23.Google Scholar
See generally FitzGerald, K., “Proposals for Human Cloning: A Review and Ethical Evaluation,” in Monagle, J. Thomasma, D., eds., Health Care Ethics: Critical Issues for the 21st Century (Gaithersburg: Aspen, 1997): Ch. 1.Google Scholar
See “Canadian Commission Issues Recommendations on New Reproductive Technologies,” Professional Ethics Report, 7 (1994): 1, 7.Google Scholar
See Gergen, K., “Social Understanding and Conceptions of the Self,” in Stigler, J.W. Shroder, R.A. Herdt, G., eds., Cultural Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990): 569606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Bahm, A.J., “What Philosophy Does the World Need?,” Contemporary Philosophy, 17 (1995): 1, 1213.Google Scholar
See, for example, how Anthony Powell developed this idea in his writings. See Treglown, J., “Class Act,” The New Yorker, Dec. 18. 1995, 108–11, esp. 110.Google Scholar
That is, as Jacques Derrida argues, the opposite of “what is” is not “what is not,” but rather the difference itself. This approach keeps the individual rooted in circumstances, family, society, and culture. See Derrida, J., “Differences,” in his The Margins of Philosophy, trans. by Bass, A. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982): 127.Google Scholar
Derrida goes on to note that, by emphasizing difference, one deconstructs all efforts of establishing a kingdom. In his thinking, there can be no capital letters, not even I. No one perspective, for instance, autonomy, could govern our ethics. Rather the individual would be defined by his/her cultural context. In the post-modern view, even being as Is-ness is simply a choice. Being's privileged place does not rest on some objective truth, but on a choice to emphasize being over nonbeing. Applying that to Western emphasis on the individual, autonomy is not a side constraint of all ethics, but simply a choice to overemphasize human difference to the exclusion of our immanent ties to all things that are.Google Scholar
See generally Engelhardt, H.T. Jr., Bioethics and Secular Humanism (Philadelphia: Trinity Press International, 1992).Google Scholar
Parens, E., “The Pluralist Constellation,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 4 (1995): At 197.Google Scholar
See “Conference Resolves Dispute Over Rights,” Chicago Tribune, June 20, 1993, at 14.Google Scholar
See Washington Post News Service, “U.N. Parley Backs Human Rights Office,” Sacramento Bee, June 26, 1993, at A10.Google Scholar
See Marshall, P.A. Koenig, B.A., “Anthropology and Bioethics: Perspectives on Culture, Medicine, and Morality,” in Johnson, T. Sargent, C., eds., Medical Anthropology: Contemporary Theory and Method (Westport: Praeger, 2nd ed., 1996): 349–73.Google Scholar
See generally Loewy, E., Suffering and the Beneficent Community: Beyond Libertarianism (New York: State University of New York Press, 1991).Google Scholar
See generally Engelhardt, H.T. Jr., The Foundations of Bioethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
See generally Yearley, L.H., Mencius and Aquinas: Theories of Virtue and Conceptions of Courage (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990).Google Scholar
See generally Engelhardt, H.T. Jr., The Foundations of Bioethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 2nd ed., 1995); and as co-editor of Christian Bioethics: A Non-Ecumenical Journal.Google Scholar
See Poteat, W.H. Langford, T.A., Intellect and Hope: Essays in the Thought of Michael Polanyi (Durham: Duke University Press, 1968): At 18.Google Scholar
See Winston, D., “New Virtues for a New World of Diversity,” Chicago Tribune, July 7, 1995, at 8.Google Scholar
Dunne, J., The Way of All the Earth (New York: MacMillan, 1972): At 1.Google Scholar
Bawer, B., “St. Francis of Assisi,” in Elie, P., ed., A Tremor of Bliss: Contemporary Writers on the Saints (New York: Riverhead Books, 1995): At 7.Google Scholar
Cotliar, S., “Arab Americans Cope with Bias in Suburbs,” Chicago Sun-Times, Feb. 6, 1995, at 4.Google Scholar
A brief note about traditional Chinese xenophobia bears on this point. Chinese xenophobia is so entrenched that the story is told of the 200-year-old diplomatic failure of the British mission there. The British Crown sent Lord George McCartney to Peking in 1792 to exchange ambassadors and to improve how the Chinese were treating British merchants. McCartney was accompanied by huge warships and a retinue of 100. Yet the Emperor of the Ming dynasty treated the British as vassals, as he would Mongolians and Tibetans, and the gifts they brought as tribute. When McCartney arrived in Peking, according to Alain Peyrefitte, as a representative of King George III, he was herded together with many other subordinates to bring tribute for the Emperor's birthday! The British simply did not understand the degree to which the Chinese regarded their empire as the center of the world (even though by then it had become quite poor and backward), or the degree to which the Chinese scorned business and businessmen. See generally Peyrefitte, A., The Collision of Two Civilizations (London: Harvill, 1993).Google Scholar
Taylor, C., Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989): At 518–19.Google Scholar
See generally Finkielkraut, , supra note 11.Google Scholar
Perkins, H.S., “Cultural Differences and Ethical Issues in the Problem of Autopsy Requests,” Texas Medicine, 87, no. 5 (1991): At 72.Google Scholar
Marshall, P.A., “Anthropology and Bioethics,” Medical Anthropology Quarterly, 6 (1992): At 62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See generally Koch, T., “The Gulf Between: Surrogate Choices, Physician Instructions, and Informal Network Responses,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 4 (1995): 185–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Agich, G.J., “Authority in Ethics Consultation,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 23 (1995): 273–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brueggemann, W., “‘Othering’—Random Thoughts on Covenant,” Explorations (World Alliance of Interfaith Organizations), 9 (1995): At 8.Google Scholar
See Freeman, W.L., “Making Research Consent Forms Informative and Understandable: The Experience of the Indian Health Service,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 3 (1994): 510–21; and Carrese, J. Rhodes, L., “Western Bioethics and the Navajo Reservation,” JAMA, 274 (1995): 826–29.Google Scholar
See Marshall, P.A. Thomasma, D.C. Bergsma, J., “Intercultural Reasoning: The Challenge for International Bioethics,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 3 (1994): 321–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See generally Dewey, J., Logic, The Theory of Inquiry (New York: Holt, 1938).Google Scholar
See generally Lasch, C., The Revolt of the Elites and the Betrayal of Democracy (New York: Norton, 1995).Google Scholar
See generally Annas, G.J. Grodin, M.A., eds., The Nazi Doctors and the Nuremburg Code: Human Rights in Human Experimentation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).Google Scholar
See Samei, E. Kearfott, K.J., “A Limited Bibliography of the Federal Government-Funded Human Radiation Experiments,” Health Physics, 69 (1995): 885–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Chen, Y.-F., “Japanese Death Factories and the American Cover-Up,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 6 (1997): 240–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See generally Gelpi, D.L., ed., Beyond Individualism: Toward a Retrieval of Moral Disclosure (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1989).Google Scholar
See Rorty, R., Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989): 6061; and Martinez, S., “Indifference Within Indignation: Anthropology, Human Rights, and the Haitian Bracero,” American Anthropologist, 98 (1996): 17–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See MacIntyre, A., Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990): At 225.Google Scholar
See Lundin, R., “Diversity and Desire,” in his The Culture of Interpretation (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1993): 730.Google Scholar
See generally Good, B.J., Medicine, Rationality, and Experience: An Anthropological Perspective (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994).Google Scholar