Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T17:13:58.689Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Pluralism, Secularism and The European Court of Human Rights

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 April 2015

Extract

The Article 9 religious freedom jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights most basically concerns the question of religious pluralism. The “principle of pluralism seems to be the main—the core—principle” guiding the Court's religious freedom jurisprudence, argues one of the Court's judges. Assessing the Court's work in the area of religious freedom therefore requires considering its treatment of pluralism, which is the concept most often employed to interpret Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rights. The Court's approach to religious pluralism is still heavily indebted to the decision in Kokkinakis v. Greece, a 1993 case involving a Jehovah's Witness who had been repeatedly arrested and jailed for violating Greece's prohibition on proselytism. In the majority opinion finding that Mr. Kokkinakis's Article 9 rights had been violated, the Court writes the following:

Type
Aals Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. See Nieuwenhuis, Aernout, The Concept of Pluralism in the Case-Law of the European Court of Human Rights, 3 Eur. Constit. L. Rev. 368 (2007)Google Scholar. Nieuwenhuis notes that

The concept of pluralism plays a prominent part in the case-law of the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR). The Court considers “pluralism” as one of the main characteristics of a democratic society. That is to say that pluralism is an important factor determining the scope and impact of a number of fundamental rights such as the right to freedom of speech and the right to freedom of association. Id. at 368.

2. Tulkens, Françoise, The European Convention on Human Rights and Church-State Relations: Pluralism vs. Pluralism, 30:6Cardozo L. Rev. 2579 (2009)Google Scholar.

3. Article 9 provides that:

1. Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion or belief, and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief, in worship, teaching, practice and observance. 2. Freedom to manifest one's religion or beliefs shall be subject only to such limitations as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic society in the interests of public safety, for the protection of public order, health or morals, or the protection of the rights and freedoms of others. The European Convention on Human Rights and its Five Protocols, Council of Eur., Nov. 4, 1950.

4. Kokkinakis v. Greece, App. No. 14307/88, 260 Eur. Ct. H.R., § 31 (1993).

5. See concurring opinion of Judge Pettiti, Wingrove v. U.K., App. No. 19/1995/525/611, 24 Eur. Ct. H.R. 1 (1997).

6. Bessarabia v. Mold, App. No. 45701/99, 35 Eur. H.R. Rep. 13, § 116 (2001).

7. Holy Synod of the Bulg. Orthodox Church & Others v. Bulg., App. No. 35677/04, Eur. Ct. H.R., § 103 (2009); Religionsgemeinschaft der Zeugen Jehovas & Others v. Austria, App. No. 40825/98, § 61 (2008). See also Lang v. Austria, App. No. 28648/03, Eur. Ct. H.R., § 24 (2009) (“Observing that religious communities traditionally exist in the form of organised structures, the Court has repeatedly found that the autonomous existence of religious communities is indispensable for pluralism in a democratic society and is, thus, an issue at the very heart of the protection which Article 9 affords”); Church of Scientology Moscow v. Russ., App. No. 18147/02, Eur. Ct. H.R., § 72 (2007) (“the autonomous existence of religious communities is indispensable for pluralism in a democratic society and is thus an issue at the very heart of the protection which Article 9 affords.”).

8. Bessarabia v. Mold., App. No. 45701/99, 35 Eur. H.R. Rep. 13, § 119 (2001).

9. Ouranio Toxo v. Greece, App. No. 74989/01, 45 Eur. H.R. Rep. 277, § 35 (2005).

10. United Communist Party of Turk. v. Turk., App. No. 133/1996/752/951, 26 Eur. H.R. Rep. 121, § 43 (1998).

11. See, e.g., Ouranio Toxo v. Greece, App. No. 74989/01, 45 Eur. H.R. Rep. 277, § 35 (2005) (pluralism described as involving “genuine recognition of, and respect for, diversity and the dynamics of traditions and of ethnic and cultural identities”); 97 Members of the Gldani Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses & 4 Others v. Ga., App. No. 71156/01, 46 Eur. H.R. Rep. 613, § 132 (2007) (pluralism ensures that competing groups “tolerate each other”).

12. Lovin, Robin W., Religion and Political Pluralism, 27 Miss. C. L. Rev. 91, 91 (2007)Google Scholar.

13. See, e.g., Religionsgemeinschaft der Zeugen Jehovas & Others v. Austria, App. No. 40825/98 (2008); 97 Members of Gldani Congregation of Jehovah's Witnesses & 4 Others v. Ga., App. No. 71156/01, 46 Eur. H.R. Rep. 613 (2007); Holy Synod of the Bulg. Orthodox Church & Others v. Bulg., App. No. 35677/04, Eur. Ct. H.R., § 103 (2009); Church of Scientology Moscow v. Russ., App. No. 18147/02 (2007).

14. Dahlab v. Switz., App. No. 42393/98, Eur. Ct. H.R. (2001).

15. Id. at § 1.

16. Id. at § 4.

17. Id. at §4.

18. Leyla Şahin v. Turk., App. No. 44774/98, Eur. Ct. H.R. (2004).

19. Id. at § 106.

20. Id. at § 108.

21. Dogru v. Fr., App. No. 27058/05,49 Eur. H.R. Rep. 8 (2009).

22. Id. at §64.

23. It has been widely noted that the Court's approach to religious freedom favors established majority religions. See, e.g., Danchin, Peter G., Of Prophets and Proselytes: Freedom of Religion and the Conflict of Rights in International Law, 49 Harv. Int'l L.J. 249 (2008)Google Scholar. See also, Renucci, Jean-François, Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rights: Freedom of Thought, Conscience and Religion 1516 (Council of Europe Publ'g 2005)Google Scholar.

24. Lautsi v. Italy, App. No. 30814/06, Eur. Ct. H.R. (2009).

25. Id. at § 47.

26. Id. at § 55-56.

27. A theme that emerges in the Article 9 cases is the Court's understanding of religious freedom as involving a balancing of the individual rights of the minority against the perceived group interests of the majority. Danchin, supra note 23, at 286-87. Yet the inequitable manner in which this principle is applied ought to be troubling. It is particularly notable that the majority's interest in Lautsi (to preserve and express an aspect of religious culture and ethical significance) was not deemed sufficiently important in Lautsi to outweigh the right of students from minority religions to be free of religious symbols, yet the interest of the majority in the headscarf cases (to uphold a secular culture) was deemed sufficient to restrict the conduct of religious minorities.

28. Bayatyan v. Arm., App. No. 23459/03, Eur. Ct. H.R. (2009).

29. Id. at § 49.

30. Evans, Carolyn, Freedom of Religion Under the European Convention on Human Rights 200 (Oxford Univ. Press 2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31. Fuhrmann, Willi, Perspectives on Religious Freedom from the Vantage Point of the European Court of Human Rights, Byul. Rev. 829, 838 (2000)Google Scholar.

32. Gülalp, Haldun, Secularism in Europe, as Refracted Through the Prism of the European Court of Human Rights: Comparative Analysis of State-Church Relations and the State Regulation of Religion 26, available at http://wwwjuristras.eliamep.gr/wp-content/uploads/2009/09/secularism-in-europeas-refracted-ttothe-prism-of-the-european-court-of-human-rights.pdfGoogle Scholar. Gülalp proposes that

historically ingrained cultural assumptions about not only the division between Christianity and Islam but also between Western and Eastern Christianity have played a part in the reasoning of the judges of the ECtHR. One could never prove this definitively, although it goes without saying that people normally behave according to received and dominant cultural knowledge. What appears as incoherence to Carolyn Evans … can be made sensible if this knowledge is taken into account.

33. Ingvill Plesner argues that the Dalab and Şahin decisions support “the impression that the Court at least accepts fundamentalist secularism as one legitimate state approach to religion.” See Plesner, , “The European Court on Human Rights between fundamentalist and liberal secularism,” Paper for the seminar on The Islamic head scarf Controversy and the Future of Freedom of Religion or Belief, Strasbourg, France 28-30 07 2005, available at http://www.strasbourgconference.org/papers/index.phpGoogle Scholar.

34. Neuhaus, Richard John, Secularizations, 190 First Things 24 (02 2009)Google Scholar.

35. Islam represents a particular difficulty for Europe, given the extent to which it challenges “some deeply held European assumptions” about the private nature of faith. Davie, Grace, Is Europe an Exceptional Case, The Hedgehog Rev. 32 (2006)Google Scholar.

36. Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe, Recommendation 1804 (2007), § 6, available at http://assembly.coe.int/main.asp?Link=/documents/adoptedtext/ta07/erecl804.htm.

37. Norris, Pippa & Inglehart, Ronald, Uneven Secularization in the United States and Western Europe, in Democracy and the New Religious Pluralism 34 (Banchoff, Thomas ed., Oxford Univ. Press 2007)Google Scholar.

38. See Davie, supra note 35, at 23.

39. Willaime, Jean-Paul, European Integration, Laïcité and Religion, in Religion, Politics and Law in the European Union 2425 (Leustean, Lucian N. & Madeley, John T.S. eds., Routledge 2010)Google Scholar.

40. Heven Boeve, God Interrupts History: Theology in a Time of Upheaval 21 (Continuum 2007).

41. Boeve, Lieven, Europe in Crisis: A Question of Belief or Unbelief? Perspectives from the Vatican, 23 Modern Theology 206 (2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

42. Carle, Robert, Pope Benedict XVI Confronts Religious Relativism, 45 Culture & Soc'y 549, 554 (2008)Google Scholar.

43. Ratzinger, Joseph & Pera, Marcello, Without Roots: The West, Relativism, Christianity, Islam 128 (Basic Books 2006)Google Scholar. See also Carle, supra note 40.

44. Id. at 128.

45. See, e.g., Pope Benedict XVI, Freedom Comes Before Equality, available at http://www.guardian.co.uk/cornmentisfree/belief/2010/feb/01/pope-benedict-equality-legislation; “The religious rights of Christians are treated with disrespect,” available at http://www.telegraph.co.uk/cornment/letters/7528487/The-religious-rirespect.html; “Labour has erased God from political life, warns Bishop of Durham,” available at http://www.timesonline.co.uk/tol/comment/faith/article7017240.ece.

46. “Address of His Holiness Benedict XVI to the Participants in the 56th National Study Congress Organized by the Union of Italian Catholic Jurists,” Dec. 9, 2006, available at http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/speeches/2006/december/documents/hf_ben_xvi_spe_20061209_giuristi-cattolici_en.html.

47. Tariq Ramadan, What I Believe 83 (Oxford Univ. Press 2010)Google Scholar.

48. Elshtain, Jean Bethke, While Europe Slept, 191 First Things 33 (2009)Google Scholar.

49. Weiler, Paul, ‘Human Rights,’ ‘Religion’ and the ‘Secular’: Variant Configurations of Religion(s), States(s) and Society(ies), in Does God Believe in Human Rights? Essays on Religion and Human Rights 151 (Ghanea-Hercock, Nazila, Stephens, Alan & Walden, Raphael eds., Martinus Nijhoff Pubslishers 2007)Google Scholar.

50. Rowan Williams describes this process in terms of the “secular government [assuming] a monopoly in terms of defining public and political identity.” Williams, Rowan, Civil and Religious Law in England: A Religious Perspective, 10 Ecclesiastical L.J. 265 (2008)Google Scholar.

51. A number of scholars have explored the ways in which a certain conception of the secular is pregnant with Christian theology. See, e.g., Markus, Robert, Christianity and the Secular (Univ. Notre Dame Press 2006)Google Scholar. Michael Horton argues that modernity's “appeal to universal foundations that bypassed appeals to revelation” arose, in part, from the failure of Christianity to fully exploit the resources of the Reformation doctrine of the two kingdoms. Horton, Michael, In Praise of Profanity: A Theological Defense of the Secular, in Evangelicals and Empire: Christian Alternatives to the Political Status Quo 262–63 (Benson, Bruce Ellis & Heltzel, Peter Goodwin eds., Brazos Press 2008)Google Scholar.

52. Kristin Deede Johnson summarizes this development in writing that “liberal invocations of tolerance have their roots in a very distinct epistemology, which includes a belief that through the use of reason all people can be unified around a body of common truths and morals.” Johnson, Kristin Deede, Theology, Political Theory and Pluralism: Beyond Tolerance and Difference 2 (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007)Google Scholar. The common morality, in turn, depended on the creation of a new liberal anthropology. John Milbank argues that liberalism invented

a wholly artificial human being who has never really existed…. This is the pure individual, thought of in abstraction from his or her gender, birth, associations, beliefs and also, crucially … from the religious or philosophical beliefs of the observer of this individual, as to whether he is a creature made by God, or only material, or naturally evolved and so forth.

Milbank, John, The Gift of Ruling, 85 New Blackfriars 212–39 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

53. Ratzinger & Pera, supra note 43, at 62.

54. Witte, John Jr., Law, Religion and Human Rights, Colum. Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 56 (1996)Google Scholar.

55. Putnam, Hilary, Monotheism and Humanism, in Humanity Before God: Contemporary Faces of Jewish, Christian and Islamic Ethics 2 (Schweiker, William, Johnson, Michael & Jung, Kevin eds., Fortress Press 2006)Google Scholar.

56. Henkin, Louis, Religion, Religions, and Human Rights, in Does Human Rights Need God 146–47 (Bucar, Elizabeth M. & Barnett, Barbra eds., Eerdmans 2005)Google Scholar.

57. Ignatieff, Michael & Amy Gutmann, Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry 8384 (Princeton Univ. Press 2001)Google Scholar.

58. Weisel, Elie, The Perils of Indifference: Lessons Learned from a Violent Century, (04 12, 1999), available at http://www.pbs.org/eliewiesel/resources/millenniura.htmlGoogle Scholar.

59. Weigel, George, The Cube and the Cathedral: Europe, America, and Politics Without God 53 (Basic Books 2005)Google Scholar. See also Weigel, George, Europe's Problem—and Ours, 140 First Things 118–25 (02 2004)Google Scholar.

60. Pierre Manent remarks that “one has the impression today that the greatest ambition of the Europeans is to become the inspectors of American prisons.” Manent, Pierre, Current Problems of European Democracy, Modern Age 15 (Winter 2003)Google Scholar.

61. Williams, Rowan, Civil and Religious Law in England: A Religious Perspective, 10 Ecclesiastical L.J. 262, 272–73 (2008)Google Scholar. Williams invokes this phrase in discussing the possibility of English law recognizing the jurisdiction of religious law, but we might equally think of the “secular legal monopoly” as applying to formulations about the relation between and the law and idea of human rights.

62. Martinez, Javier, “Beyond Secular Reason”: Some Contemporary Challenges for the Life and Thought of the Church as Seen from the West 35 (2004), available at http://www.thedivineconspiracy.org/Z5205F.pdfGoogle Scholar.

63. Haldun Gülalp, supra note 32, at 23.

64. Williams, supra note 61, at 270.

65. Perry, Michael J., The Idea of Human Rights: Four Inquiries 7 (Oxford Univ. Press 1998)Google Scholar.

66. McConnell, Michael, Old Liberalism, New Liberalism and People of Faith, in Christian Perspectives on Legal Thought 23 (McConnell, Michael J., Cochran, Robert F. Jr. & Cannella, Angela C. eds., Yale Univ. Press 2001)Google Scholar.

67. Lovin, supra note 12, at 101.

68. Id. at 212-13.

69. Carozza, Paolo, The Catholic Intellectual Tradition and Human Rights, 2St. Michael's College (03 7, 2005)Google Scholar.

70. Johnson, supra note 52, at 224. Charles Mathewes similarly observes that “certainly Christian engagements with various exemplary modern secular Western thinkers reveals both deep continuities in affirmations about the worth of the individual, and fundamental differences in understandings of the human project.” Mathewes, Charles, Theology of Public Life 137 (Cambridge Univ. Press 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

71. Novak, David, In Defense of Religious Liberty 106 (ISI Books 2009)Google Scholar.

72. Kamali, Mohamaad Hashim, Shari'ah Law: An Introduction 206 (Oneworld 2008)Google Scholar.

73. Williams, supra note 61, at 271. Williams writes that,

if the reality of society is plural—as many political theorists have pointed out—this is a damagingly inadequate account of common life, in which certain kinds of affiliation are marginalized or privatized to the extent that what is produced is a ghettoized pattern of social life, in which certain kinds of affiliation are marginalized or privatized …

74. Mathewes, supra note 70, at 112.

75. This encounter is not one way but rather creates an occasion for religion to stand under the critical judgment of a tradition outside itself. Charles Taylor has written, for instance, of the ways in which “the secularist affirmation … of universal and unconditional rights” led to a prolongation of the gospel. In other words, it took the modern idea of human rights, born of “the break with Christendom,” for Christianity to discover new understandings about the authentic meaning of the Gospel. See Taylor, Charles & James Heft, A Catholic Modernity? 2526 (Oxford Univ. Press 1999)Google Scholar.

76. Tanner, Kathryn, The Politics of God: Christian Theologies and Social Justice 223 (Fortress Press 1992)Google Scholar.

77. In discussing the idea of “humbly confessed particularism,” Mathewes writes:

[O]ur understanding of the epistemological implications of those beliefs should make us always eager to engage other positions in dialogue. We are confident of the tradition's basic story: humanity is in self-dividing revolt from God, and God has become incarnate in Christ, and continues to act in the world in the Holy Spirit, in order to restore us to our proper end.

That we know the story only in a mirror darkly “gives us a fundamentally Christian motive for engagement—caritas—a practice that synthesizes confession and dogmatism into a unitary yet triune action charged with faith, hope, and love.” Mathewes, supra note 70, at 135-36.

78. Johnson, supra note 52, at 224.

79. Carter, Stephen, Liberal Hegemony, Religious Resistance, in Christian Perspectives on Legal Thought 33 (McConnell, Michaelet. al eds., Yale Univ. Press 2001)Google Scholar.

80. Ouranio Toxo v. Greece, App. No. 74989/01, 45 Eur. H.R. Rep. 277, § 35 (2005).

81. As one commentator writes in discussing the Court's jurisprudence, “religious disagreement can be a sign that people are taking that pursuit seriously; but, more importantly, it can be a sign that individuals and religious communities are being accorded those political liberties necessary to foster the good of religion.” Tollefsen, Christopher O., Is there Value in Religious Pluralism?, Public Discourse (06 12, 2009), available at http://www.thepublicdiscourse.com/2009/06/270Google Scholar.

82. Bessarabia v. Mold., App. No. 45701/99, 35 Eur. H.R. Rep. 13, § 116 (2001).

83. Stackhouse, Max, Why Human Rights Needs God: A Christian Perspective, in Does Human Rights Need God 3132 (Mrs.Bucar, Elizabeth M. & Mrs.Barnett, Barbra eds., Eerdmans Pub. 2005)Google Scholar.

84. Johnson, supra note 52, at 222-26. The Court, moreover, has not only worked within a secular paradigm but “been instrumental in shaping the meaning and normative content of secularism.” Gülalp, supra note 32, at 24.

85. Modak-Truran, Mark C., Beyond Theocracy and Secularism (Part I): Toward a New Paradigm for Law and Religion, 27 Miss. C. L. Rev. 201 (2007)Google Scholar.

86. See, e.g., Smith, Steven D., Law's Quandary (Harv. Univ. Press 2004)Google Scholar.

87. See generally, O'Donovan, Oliver, The Ways of Judgment (Eerdmans Pub. 2005)Google Scholar.

88. Brague, Remi, Are Non-Theocratic Regimes Possible?, Intercollegiate Rev. 1011 (2006)Google Scholar. Javier Martinez similarly questions whether human rights can “found a real sociality or a true humanity.” Martinez, supra note 62, at 6. Along similar lines, John Milbank argues that “the Church needs boldly to teach that the only justification for democracy is theological. Since ‘the people’ is potentially the ecclesia, and since nature always anticipates grace, truth ultimately lies dispersed among the people … because the Holy Spirit speaks through the voice of all.” Milbank, , Liberalism Versus Liberalism, in The Future of Love 245 (Cascade 2009)Google Scholar.

89. Mathewes, supra note 70, at 108.