Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T21:12:36.052Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justice, Virtue, and Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 February 2016

Extract

The purpose of this paper is to examine the relationship of justice understood as a virtue to law and public policy. Is justice adequately understood in terms of virtue, or does the former also include certain rules—or laws—which constitute criteria of justice in human community? If the concept of justice includes the notion of rules as well as virtue, how are the two ideas related? At a more fundamental level, is justice, indeed, a viable concept in modern, pluralistic society?

In an effort to explore these questions we turn, first, to three contemporary ethicists who have attempted to ground morality in public life fundamentally upon the notion of virtue. The first of these writers—Alasdair MacIntyre—is a philosopher; the remaining two—Stanley Hauerwas and James M. Gustafson—are theologians. While each is deeply influenced by Aristotle and Aquinas, all three fail to give adequate attention to the relation of justice conceived as a virtue to law in the latter, particularly in Aquinas. The ensuing section of the paper is devoted to an analysis of the structures of justice as a requirement of collective forms of human life. Consideration of the structures of justice leads, in turn, to the question of the relationship of justice to law. Finally, it is argued that, from a theological perspective, justice is most adequately understood as a form of covenant and that the ultimate norm of justice is reconciling love. Justice is a human task which aims finally at the reconciliation of broken community and the achievement of new forms or levels of the common good.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. MacIntyre, , After Virtue 227 (1981)Google Scholar.

2. Id. at 143.

3. Id. at 236.

4. Id. at 244-45.

5. Id. at 245.

6. Id. at 237.

7. Id. at 237.

8. Id. at 194-205.

9. If MacIntyre's proposal concerning the construction of local forms of community had been stated in theological terms, it would have represented a form of “Christ Against Culture” morality described by Niebuhr, H. Richard in Christ and Culture, 4582 (1951)Google Scholar. Hauerwas' ethic also resembles this type of theological ethics; Gustafson's, on the other hand, is more closely akin to the Thomistic synthesis of morality based on faith and reason as well as the synthesis of virtue and law.

10. Hauerwas, , A Community of Character 128 (1981)Google Scholar [hereinafter cited as Community of Character; cf. Hauerwas, , Vision and Virtue 228240 (1974)Google Scholar [hereinafter cited as Vision and Virtue.

11. Community of Character, supra note 10, at 36-52.

12. Id. at 109; cf. Hauerwas, , The Peaceable Kingdom 99102 (1983)Google Scholar.

13. Community of Character, supra note 10, at 109.

14. Vision and Virtue, supra note 10, at 240 n.41.

15. Community of Character, supra note 10, at 254 n.42.

16. Vision and Virtue, supra note 10, at 219.

17. Hauerwas, supra note 12, at 104, 114.

18. Vision and Virtue, supra note 10, at 231-240.

19. Community of Character, supra note10, at 3.

20. Id. at 3, 128.

21. Id. at 100.

22. Hauerwas, , Character and the Christian Life 1416 (1975)Google Scholar.

23. Gustafson, , Can Ethics be Christian? 156–57 (1975)Google Scholar.

24. Gustafson, , Protestant and Roman Catholic Ethics 95137 (1978)Google Scholar.

25. Gustafson, supra note 23, at 164.

26. Gustafson, , Christian Ethics and the Community 153-63, 202 (1971)Google Scholar.

27. Gustafson, , The Church as Moral Decision-Maker, 172-75, 202 (1970)Google Scholar.

28. MacIntyre, supra note 1, at 226.

29. This essay was completed before the appearance of Gustafson's, Ethics from a Theocentric Perspective, Volume II: Ethics and Theobgy (1984)Google Scholar. In this volume Gustafson provides four illustrations of the manner in which ethical reflection upon different areas of human experience (marriage and family, suicide, population and nutrition, and the allocation of biomedical research funding) is informed by a theocentric perspective.

30. Aristotle, , The Nicomachean Ethics 138 (Weldon, J.E.C. ed. 1930)Google Scholar.

31. Vecchio, Del, Justice: An Historical and Philosophical Survey 54 (1956)Google Scholar. Del Vecchio further notes that this characteristic of justice has been “reasserted by all subsequent writers who have thought deeply on the subject.” Id.

32. Aristotle, supra note 29.

33. Id. at 143.

34. 2 Aquinas, T., The Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas 830 (Pegis, Anton C. ed. 1944)Google Scholar.

35. 37 Aquinas, T., Summa Theologiae 31 (Gilby, Thomas ed. 1975)Google Scholar.

36. Id. at 33.

37. Id, at 51.

38. T. Aquinas, supra note 33, at 460-61.

39. Pieper, , The Four Cardinal Virtues 7075 (1966)Google Scholar.

40. Id, at 54-63.

41. Id. at 99.

42. Id. at 89.

43. Eterovich, F., Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics: Commentary and Analysis 9091 (1980)Google Scholar.

44. Pieper, supra note 38, at 46.

45. Aristotle, supra note 29, at 134.

46. Id. at 156-57, 163-164.

47. Id, at 159.

48. Id. at 160.

49. Aristotle, , Politics 149 (Modern Library, 1943)Google Scholar.

50. Id. at 320-337.

51. Aquinas, supra note 34, at 21.

52. Id. at 27.

53. Id. at 49.

54. See Perelman, C., The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument 6178 (1963)Google Scholar.

55. As Pieper observes, recognition of the primacy of the right led Aquinas to place his discussion of the latter before his treatise on justice in the SUMMA THEOLOGIAE (PIEPER, supra note 38, at 46).

56. Aristotle, , Nichomachean Ethics 170–73Google Scholar.

57. Id. at 246.

58. Id. at 252-61.

59. Pieper, supra note 38, at 104-13.

60. Cf. Aquinas, supra note 33, at 4-61.

61. Del Vecchio, supra note 30, at 148. See also Perelman, supra note 53, at 60: “An imperfect [system of] justice, without charity, is no justice.” Since all existing systems of justice are imperfect, they need to “draw fresh inspiration” from the more immediate and spontaneous values, the chief of which is charity.

62. MacIntyre, , After Virtue 195, 203Google Scholar.

63. Gustafson,s theocentric ethics contain a broad basis for community grounded in creation and also for an affirmation of pluralism. In his account of justice, however, he does not take sufficient account either of the relativities of history or the dynamics of human conflict.

64. See Niebuhr, H. Richard, The Idea of the Covenant and American Democracy, 23 Church History 126135 (1954)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Niebuhr, Radical Monotheism and Western Culture 3848 (1960)Google Scholar; Ball, M., The Promise of American Law: A Theological, Humanistic View of Legal Process (1981)Google Scholar; Bellah, R., The Broken Covenant: American Civil Religion in Time of Trial (1975)Google Scholar; Ramsey, P., Basic Christian Ethics (1950)Google Scholar; Ramsey, , Christian Ethics and the Sit-In (1961)Google Scholar; Allen, J., LOVE & Conflict: A Covo Enantal Model of Christian Ethics (1984)Google Scholar.

65. Niebuhr, The Responsible Self 6165 (1963)Google Scholar.

66. Schrey, Heinz-Horst, Biblical Doctrine of Justice and Law 182–83 (1955)Google Scholar.