Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T22:59:46.282Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The limits of generality for constitutional design

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 August 2023

Andrew T. Young*
Affiliation:
Rawls College of Business, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, TX, USA
*
Corresponding author. E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

James Buchanan was a fervent advocate of a non-discriminatory politics. However, he translated his views on constitutional political economy into (de jure) constitutional design in an insufficiently thoughtful way. Simply writing non-discriminatory politics into a Constitution is unlikely to have the desired effect. All Constitutional language is open to interpretation and political entrepreneurs will be ready to push interpretation in their favoured directions. The history of US Constitutional law bears this out. This does not necessarily discount Buchanan's quest for constitutionalized non-discriminatory politics. However, it does mean that it must be tempered by realistic concerns regarding constitutional design. With this in mind, I suggest that focusing on procedural, rather than substantive, Constitutional provisions may be more fruitful.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Millennium Economics Ltd.

Introduction

The idea of a generality principle features prominently in constitutional political economy (Buchanan, Reference Buchanan2000 [1975]; Buchanan and Congleton, Reference Buchanan and Congleton2003 [1998]; Congleton, Reference Congleton, Rowley and Schneider2004; Salter and Young, Reference Salter and Young2019). For Nobel Laureate James Buchanan, it provides the normative bridge between individual and collective action: when ‘carried out only after general agreement, collective action is essentially voluntary action’ (Buchanan, Reference Buchanan1959: 134).Footnote 1 A generality principle underlies the argument for unanimity (or something very close to it) in the choice of a de jure (or ‘big-C’) Constitution; likewise, it motivates ‘Article V’-type rules that insist upon large supermajorities for Constitutional amendments.Footnote 2 In terms of a positive theory of governance, generality characterizes situations where the benefits and costs are, respectively, enjoyed and borne broadly.

A generality principle informs not only Buchanan's views on how a Constitution should be adopted and amended, but also his preferences for Constitutional content. For example, Buchanan (Reference Buchanan2005) argues that generality, in its broadest sense, should be explicitly incorporated into the US Constitution by means of a ‘non-discriminatory politics’ amendment. He references his 1978 interview of Friedrich Hayek, during which the latter argued for adding the following Constitutional text: ‘Congress shall make no law authorizing government to take any discriminatory measures of coercion.’ Hayek (and by implication Buchanan) believed that this amendment would ‘make all the other [Constitutional] rights unnecessary’.Footnote 3

However, Buchanan has a tendency to neglect the ‘nitty-gritty’ of real-world constitutional design. In his (Reference Buchanan2005) essay for Cato Unbound, he advocated three specific amendments to the US Constitution, including the non-discriminatory politics amendment. This was a rare instance of Buchanan stating what his Constitutional preferences might actually look like in Constitutional text. The essay was published with three responses, including two by distinguished legal scholars (Amar, Reference Amar2005a; Kozinski, Reference Kozinski2005; Niskanen, Reference Niskanen2005). The responses are fascinating. All of those authors (including Niskanen, an economist) at times seem non-plussed by Buchanan's perfunctory consideration of how Constitutional provisions are put into effect, interpreted, and subsequently exploited by political entrepreneurs.

The above authors are largely concerned with critiquing Buchanan's advocacy of three specific amendments to the US Constitution. However, other authors – many writing in the public choice tradition – embrace Buchanan's advocacy of generality-based Constitutional reform specifically, or more generally believe that Buchanan's contributions are directly relevant to Constitutional design (recently, e.g. Congleton, Reference Congleton2014; Dougherty and Edward, Reference Dougherty and Edward2011; Dove and Young, Reference Dove and Young2019; Ginsburg, Reference Ginsburg, Farber and O'Connell2010a; Lehto and Meadowcroft, Reference Lehto and Meadowcroft2021; Meadowcroft, Reference Meadowcroft2020; Voigt, Reference Voigt2020). These latter scholars take Buchanan's contributions – including those with coauthors, e.g. Buchanan and Tullock Reference Buchanan and Tullock1962; Brennan and Buchanan Reference Brennan and Buchanan1980 – as serious guides for Constitutional design. In this paper, I aim to highlight ways in which Buchanan's neglect of the ‘nitty-gritty’ of Constitutional design is problematic in ways that are ignored by many scholars.

Before doing so, I note one potential problem that I will not concern myself with in this paper: to wit, the possibility that Constitutions are simply irrelevant. Many scholars are dismissive of what James Madison referred to as ‘parchment barriers’. For example, Wenzel (Reference Wenzel2010: 65) ‘emphatically reject[s] the notion that good constitutional parchment is sufficient for successful constitutionalism’. This is a fundamental objection: Constitutions do not matter or are, at the very least, an order of magnitude less important than a society's informal constitutional conventions and norms.Footnote 4 And recent studies on the ‘de jure-de facto gap’ (or ‘constitutional underperformance’) provide empirical evidence that this objection needs to be taken seriously, at least in regard to many countries (e.g. Chilton and Versteeg, Reference Chilton and Versteeg2016; Gutmann et al., Reference Gutmann, Metelska-Szaniawska and Voigt2022; Law and Versteeg, Reference Law and Versteeg2013; Voigt, Reference Voigt2021).

However, Buchanan is clearly concerned with the US Constitution and that document – albeit imperfectly – does bind political agents.Footnote 5 Why is this the case in the US and in many other countries? The most compelling explanation put forth is that a Constitution can serve as a coordination device (e.g. Hadfield and Weingast, Reference Hadfield, Weingast, Galliani and Sened2014; Hardin, Reference Hardin, Grofman and Wittman1989; Ordeshook, Reference Ordeshook1992; Weingast, Reference Weingast1997). By codifying rules in a shared document, a Constitution can provide ‘a focal solution […] so that citizens gain the ability to act in concert and police their government’ (Weingast, Reference Weingast2005: 105). In similar fashion, it can coordinate political agents in policing one another (Young, Reference Young2021).Footnote 6

Of course, a Constitution cannot coordinate citizens and political agents around just anything. A constitutional order is ultimately shaped by shared beliefs (conventions and norms) regarding the rules of the game for political agents. On the one hand, codifying rules that are blatantly at odds with individuals' expectations will be for naught. On the other hand, codifying rules that everyone already accepts is redundant. Reality, though, is always somewhere between that first hand and the other: the extent to which beliefs are shared will vary. A Constitution can coordinate agents around a specific subset of the feasible norms and conventions (Salter and Furton, Reference Salter and Furton2018; Young, Reference Young2019).Footnote 7 By providing a common point of reference, the codification increases the extent to which that specific subset of beliefs is shared.Footnote 8

Even while accepting that Constitutions can matter, important problems remain with Buchanan's belief that generality can be straightforwardly written into them. These have to do with the inescapable ambiguities of language – the essential means of codification – and the endogeneity of Constitutional provisions to political entrepreneurship. Due to these ambiguities and endogeneity, provisions may be adopted that are ultimately inconsistent with generality. Furthermore, those inconsistencies can become entrenched over time. As such, a Constitutional provision aimed at ensuring generality may actually result in durable rules that facilitate discriminatory politics.

In section ‘The limits of generality in constitutional design’, I outline the limitations in trying to straightforwardly codify any principle into Constitutional text. I pay especial attention to the limitations in codifying generality. In section ‘Legal scholars respond to Buchanan’, I then illustrate how those limitations are inherent in the critical responses to Buchanan's (Reference Buchanan2005) call for a non-discriminatory politics amendment. Based on the limits of generality, I argue in section ‘Substance versus procedure’ that an emphasis on the procedural aspects of constitutional design is more likely to promote generality than substantive Constitutional text. Concluding remarks are in section ‘Conclusion’.

The limits of generality in Constitutional design

A generality principle suggests that Constitutional provisions should facilitate governance for which the costs and benefits are borne and enjoyed broadly. If generality is a lodestar for Constitutional design, then Buchanan and Hayek's non-discriminatory politics amendment (‘Congress shall make no law authorizing government to take any discriminatory measures of coercion’) is prima facie desirable. However, in this section, I discuss reasons why such a de jure amendment may fail to promote generality or, worse, end up entrenching rules that are decidedly inconsistent with it.

In what follows I will discuss Constitutional text and its interpretation generally; however, the arguments apply specifically to Buchanan's quest for a non-discriminatory politics amendment.

Ambiguity of rules

Thomas Reid (Reference Reid1852: 1) began his Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man by stating: ‘There is no greater impediment to the advancement of knowledge than the ambiguity of words.’Footnote 9 This is certainly relevant to Constitutional design. While not concerned with the advancement of knowledge per se, the ambiguity of words is an unavoidable – which is not to say immitigable – constraint on effective codification of any convention. Any Constitutional provision, therefore, must be interpreted, both when adopted and then over time.

Constitutional interpreters include not only judges (in societies with judicial review) but also the citizenry and their political agents. All of these interpreters are relevant as to how certain words translate into the de facto constitutional order. For examples, US legislators make choices regarding the laws they will pass; presidents then make choices regarding which of those laws they will veto rather than sign, and also which of them they will enforce ex post; and all of those choices are based, in part, on the relevant agents' understandings of what lies within the four corners of the Constitution.Footnote 10 Furthermore, in making those choices, all of those agents are subject to pressure from their constituents, whom have their own understandings of the Constitutional text.Footnote 11

Inconsistencies in those understandings will inevitably arise – across both types of agents and time – because the conventions which drafters attempt to codify in a Constitution are unavoidably characterized by what Friedrich Waismann (Reference Waismann1945) felicitously terms ‘open texture’.Footnote 12 Such conventions ‘are not delimited in all possible directions’ (p. 122). Trying to provide text that exhaustively conveys the same thing to all minds is futile; ‘we can never exclude altogether the possibility of some unforeseen situation arising in which we shall have to modify our definition’ (pp. 122–123). Reading the examples provided by Waismann, it is clear that the ‘unforeseen situation[s]’ are in reference to looking across individuals as well as time.Footnote 13 The ambiguity of words means that drafters have a Herculean task in providing a convention with an exhaustive definition, either interpersonally or intertemporally.Footnote 14

To illustrate the above points, consider Williams (Reference Williams2017)'s comparative examples of ‘freedom of expression’ provisions in the Icelandic and Polish Constitutions.

Freedom of expression may only be restricted by law in the interests of public

order or the security of the State, for the protection of health or morals, or for

the protection of the rights or reputation of others, if such restrictions are

deemed necessary and in agreement with democratic traditions. (Iceland; Article 73)

versus …

The freedom to express opinions, to acquire and to disseminate information

shall be ensured to everyone. (Poland; Article 54)

Beyond the straightforward difference in the textual length between the two provisions, Williams emphasizes the use of adjectives/adverbs (e.g. ‘necessary’), conditional conjunctions (e.g. ‘if’; ‘and’; ‘or’), and indeterminate modal verbs (e.g. ‘may’) in the Icelandic case. Greater use of such ‘indeterminate parts of speech’ (Williams, Reference Williams2017: 1) introduces vagueness and makes interpretation more difficult and/or open.

The Icelandic and Polish provisions also fundamentally differ in that Iceland's takes the form of freedom can only be restricted when; as opposed to Poland's freedom shall be ensured. The Icelandic provision provides an itemization of specific cases when restriction is permissible, leaving latent the general freedom shall be ensured (i.e. not restricted). Alternatively, the Polish provision makes the general protection of expression explicit while remaining silent on specific exceptions, which undoubtedly exist. (Some are found elsewhere within Poland's Constitution [e.g. Article 13 prohibits ‘political parties and other organizations […] whose programmes or activities sanction racial or national hatred’] and some are based on the legislature's interpretation of what exceptions remain implicit [e.g. sections of the criminal code that extend Article 13-type prohibitions to individuals].)

An implication of this differential constitutional language is that the de jure role of Iceland's government is relatively vague. For example, it ‘may only’ restrict expression in certain cases (whereas Poland's simply ‘shall not’); when such restrictions are ‘necessary’ and/or ‘in agreement with democratic traditions’ (whereas Poland's provision contains no such conditionality). Furthermore, such language opens up broad possibilities for constitutional interpretation de facto. As Williams (Reference Williams2017: 4) notes: Poland's ‘protection of free speech is far less elastic and liable to elite dominance’ than Iceland's. Stated more generally, Iceland's language provides greater latitude for political agents and their constituents to offer plausible interpretations of the provision. This makes the constitutional constraint itself endogenous to that interpretation in practice.

The ambiguity, both de jure and then de facto, opens up possibilities for constitutional political entrepreneurship (Salter and Wagner, Reference Salter and Wagner2018; see section ‘Political entrepreneurship’ below), the results of which are likely to be inconsistent with generality. This is where Williams (Reference Williams2017) is concerned with ‘elite dominance’, but it applies to any organized special interest. A constitutional constraint (or, for that matter, mandate) provides for generality only to the extent that it cannot be perverted and captured by special interests. Alternatively, if it is de jure ambiguous and therefore de facto endogenous to how agents interpret it, then generality cannot be ensured.

Worse, constitutional provisions designed ostensibly to ensure generality may lead to decidedly contrary outcomes. Consider the Icelandic constitutional provision on free expression from above. Not only is it positive and conditional relative to the Polish provision – expression can only be restricted when rather than expression will be ensured (not restricted) – but its use of vague language (adjectives/adverbs; conditional conjunctions; indeterminate modal verbs) opens up broad avenues for interpretation.

Time-invariance of rules

Constitutional provisions are likely to contain words or phrases, the understood meanings of which are inherently subject to change as the environment – technological, economic, social, and/or political – changes. When the meanings of these words and phrases change, this reshapes the Constitutional rules in which they are embedded.

Consider the much-debated Second Amendment to the US Constitution: ‘the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall not be infringed’. To begin with, the term ‘Arms’ meant something different in the late eighteenth century than it does today. This difference in meaning was unavoidable with the passing of time. For one thing, technology changed: even limiting ‘Arms’ to mean ‘guns’, the underlying technologies are today vastly more accurate and deadly. (Alternatively, a Constitutional right to own and use muskets specifically would seem patently absurd today.)

Even holding technology constant, social changes over time have led to a different understanding of ‘to bear Arms’. The term had a decidedly military connotation to eighteenth-century individuals. (As such, the ‘well regulated Militia’ in the first clause of the Second Amendment did not then seem incongruous with the switch to ‘people’ in the second.) To someone in the eighteenth century, ‘a deer hunter or target shooter carries a gun[;] he does not, in the strictest sense, bear arms’ (Amar, Reference Amar2005b: 322). The loss of this connotation contributed to the development over time of a new, decidedly individualistic, understanding of the ‘right to bear Arms’.Footnote 15

The time-invariance of the Second Amendment's meaning does not necessarily have much directly to do with generality. However, consider another example: the Commerce Clause of Article I, giving the US Congress ‘the power to regulate commerce with foreign nations, and among the several states, and with the Indian tribes’. As Epstein (Reference Epstein1987: 1387) notes:

[It is] the clause in the Constitution to which most federal power can be traced in today's general welfare state. The labor statutes, the civil rights statutes, the farm and agricultural statutes, and countless others rest on […] a construction of the commerce clause that grants the federal government jurisdiction so long as it can show (as it always can) that the regulated activity burdens, obstructs, or affects interstate commerce, however indirectly.

But the tracing of present-day federal powers to the Commerce Clause is tied to the evolution of the meaning of ‘commerce’ as US society and the economy changed over time.Footnote 16

Epstein (Reference Epstein1987) marshals evidence regarding the US Constitutional text and how contemporaries (to its adoption) would have interpreted the word ‘commerce’. In particular, contemporaries would have deemed ‘commerce’ to be ‘closer to the idea of ‘trade’ than to other economic activities’ (p. 1389; also see Barnett, Reference Barnett2001). Consistent with this, Chief Justice John Marshall's opinion in Gibbons v. Ogden (1824) referred to it as ‘intercourse’.Footnote 17 As Barnett (Reference Barnett2001: 128) notes, Samuel Johnson's Dictionary of the English Language (6th edition, 1785) defined ‘intercourse’ as ‘1. Commerce; exchange’.Footnote 18 The meaning ascribed to ‘commerce’ in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries can be contrasted with how it today is equated to economic activity broadly. For example, consider the US Department of Commerce's stated mission (‘to create the conditions for economic growth and opportunity for all communities’) and its strategic goals (‘Innovation, equity, and resilience’).Footnote 19

This evolution in the meaning of ‘commerce’ corresponded to a substantive change in the interpretation of the Commerce Clause. In Gibbons, the issue at hand was state-granted monopoly rights to navigation of interstate waters. The Marshall Court ruled against those monopolies to prevent state governments from interference with interstate trade. (Note the two specific words: interstate and trade.) Combined with the Supremacy Clause (Article VI, clause 2), the Marshall Court determined that Congress' power to regulate interstate commerce amounted to states' lack of power to interfere with it.Footnote 20 The Commerce Clause was then a shield against state governments creating an unlevel economic playing field. Furthermore, decades later, ‘[d]uring the Progressive Era, the Supreme Court rejected a broad conception of commerce […] in favor of a more limited conception […] as “trade and exchange”’ (Barnett, Reference Barnett2001: 129). This limited the federal government's own role to defining the level playing field.

Fast-forward three more decades and ‘the Commerce Clause […] in its New Deal incarnation expanded the powers of the federal government far beyond any level that it had previously held’ (Epstein, Reference Epstein2014: 167). How? It was at this point that ‘commerce’ became interpreted to mean essentially any economy activity. In watershed cases like Nebbia v. New York (1934) and Wickard v. Filburn (1942), the Supreme Court established its deference to Congress regarding legislation when ‘the public interest [is] deemed to require’ it, and/or when legislation affects an industry that ‘exerts a substantial economic effect on interstate commerce’ (Barnett, Reference Barnett2004: ch. 11; Epstein, Reference Epstein2006: 64–81).Footnote 21 Unsurprisingly, given deference to Congress' (subjective) evaluation of public interest and substantial effect, it enjoyed essentially carte blanche throughout the latter part of the twentieth century and into the twenty-first.Footnote 22

Political entrepreneurship

All Constitutional provisions are open to interpretation, at least to an extent. As elaborated on above, this is necessarily so because, first and foremost, language is inherently ambiguous; furthermore, interpretations of any Constitutional provision are likely to change as the environment (technological, economic, social, political) changes. For any provision, then, the range of interpretation provides a window of opportunity for political entrepreneurs who stand to gain via constitutional change.

As Salter and Wagner (Reference Salter and Wagner2018: 281) recognize, ‘societies rarely entail universal agreement about constitutional provisions’. It follows that ‘there will exist margins of contestation where political entrepreneurship is active in seeking support for alternative constitutional interpretations’ (p. 281). A political entrepreneur's contestation of status quo interpretations may, of course, be disingenuous and self-serving; but to affect constitutional change his alternative interpretations must be compelling to a broad swath of the society.

Theorizing in constitutional political economy typically begins from a two-stage framework. First, the rules of the game for political agents are chosen. Second, political agents proceed to operate within those rules. To wit, there is a ‘constitutional moment’ which establishes the framework within which ‘ordinary politics’ then plays out over time (Buchanan, Reference Buchanan1975; Buchanan and Tullock, Reference Buchanan and Tullock1962; Brennan and Buchanan, Reference Brennan and Buchanan1980). While the stylized two-stage framework is often very useful, that does not change the fact that ordinary politics is tied up with the constitutional contestation in any society (Salter and Wagner, Reference Salter and Wagner2018: 282; also see Runst and Wagner, Reference Runst and Wagner2011).

Hence, the potential for special interest capture (Stigler, Reference Stigler1971; Tullock, Reference Tullock1967) is relevant at the constitutional – as well as the ordinary – level of politics (Boudreaux and Pritchard, Reference Boudreaux and Pritchard1993; Landes and Posner, Reference Landes and Posner1975). Given an unchanging Constitutional text, political entrepreneurs, seeking to further the special interests that they embody or represent, can promote change in constitutional norms and conventions. They can, by exerting direct or indirect influence on judicial review, lead to changes in the interpretation of unchanged text. While no formal Constitutional amendment occurs, political entrepreneurship can lead to constitutional capture in favour of certain special interests (Salter, Reference Salter2017; Salter and Furton, Reference Salter and Furton2018).Footnote 23

Consider the Seventeenth Amendment to the US Constitution. In the original document, selection of US senators was via states' legislatures. (This can be contrasted to membership in the House of Representatives, which was based on popular elections.) The insulation of the Senate from direct popular input into its membership was designed to prevent the excesses of democracy, including calls for federal government growth at the expense of individual liberties (Garrett et al., Reference Garrett, Kozak and Rhine2010; Holcombe and Lacombe, Reference Holcombe and Lacombe1998). However, interstate special interests pushed to amend the Constitution such that both houses of Congress were directly answerable to popular election (Schleicher, Reference Schleicher2014; Zywicki, Reference Zywicki1994). The Seventeenth Amendment served those interstate special interests because individual voters were more amenable to them than state legislators. The latter were more likely to be focused on the shared interests of those within their states. Alternatively, voters were more apt to be swayed by interstate special interests that appealed to them individually (e.g. a truck driver in California may identify more with interstate trucking than the intrastate interests of Californians).

In the case of the Seventeenth Amendment, political entrepreneurship actual led to a change in the text. However, now consider the more recent example of political entrepreneurship's role in affecting the constitutional status of abortion rights in the US. That status has had two watershed moments in Supreme Court judicial review (Roe v. Wade 1973 and Dobbs v. Jackson Women's Health Organization 2022) and important Court decisions in between them (e.g. Planned Parenthood v. Casey 1992; Gonzalez v. Carhart 2007).Footnote 24 Through all of the above, the text of the US Constitution did not relevantly change.Footnote 25 Yet special interests have been active – both during and before the 1973–2022 period – to influence the courts' interpretations of that text in relation to abortion rights (Soper, Reference Soper1994; Staggenborg, Reference Staggenborg1991).Footnote 26

The activities on both the pro-choice and pro-life sides have been varied, ranging from grassroots movements, to co-opting both broader and narrower interest groups, and to procuring the services of lobbying groups, lawyers, and legal scholars.Footnote 27 Their efforts have been both direct (e.g. having lawyers file test cases within the court system) and indirect (e.g. lobbying for state legislatures to pass abortion laws that are the bases for the test cases). Importantly, counted amongst the indirect efforts are those aimed at electing a US president who will appoint judges favourable to certain views (and also Senate members who will have a say in whether a president's nominees are confirmed).

The direct and indirect efforts alluded to above all have – and will continue – to play a role in the constitutional status of abortion rights in the US. They are driven by political entrepreneurs of various stripes (grassroot organizers; leaders of organized political interest groups; constitutional lawyers; etc.). All of these efforts ultimately have relied on the interpretability of a constant Constitutional text via judicial review and the agents of ordinary politics who make such review come into play.Footnote 28

Entrenchment of non-generality

I have emphasized the endogeneity of constitutional government role above. This is obviously relevant for any Constitutional text which is added towards an ideal of generality. Such text may be interpreted in ways that, perversely, favour special interests. On the other hand, Constitutional text can also be reinterpreted over time to promote generality in ways that it had not done so before. The former is obviously more relevant for those pursing a Buchanan-esque non-discriminatory politics amendment. But both scenarios are plausible and I will start with a case of the later.

Wu (Reference Wu2018: 548) sates that ‘The First Amendment was a dead letter for much of American history.’ While surprising to many, early US history evidences little Constitutional challenge and Supreme Court silence in response to government abridgements of political expression. The Alien and Sedition Acts of 1798 are a case in point.Footnote 29 It was only in response to new Espionage and Sedition Acts during WWI that First Amendment judicial challenges began to occur. A famous example is Debs v. US (1919), associated with the indictment of Eugene Debs for giving a speech in violation of the 1917 Espionage Act.Footnote 30 Interestingly, this case was plausibly motivated by special interest (in particular, Deb's special interest in not being imprisoned) but stood to further generality (by making political speech Constitutionally protected for all). In the event, Deb's conviction was upheld by the Supreme Court. Indeed, interpretations of the First Amendment as providing broad protection of political speech first appeared in dissenting opinions. It was not until the 1950s and 1960s that Supreme Court majorities established the core protections that are today taken for granted.Footnote 31

Now I turn to the possibility of changing interpretation leading away from generality. This possibility is more concerning for those who favour Buchanan's advocacy of Constitutionalizing non-discriminatory politics. The US Commerce Clause example provided above is pointedly relevant. While all must admit that the original text was open to interpretation to begin with, the Marshall Court (1801–1835) clearly established an interpretation that limited the federal government's powers to (1) its enumerated powers and (2) striking down state-based actions that conflicted with those powers (the so-called ‘Dormant Commerce Clause’). The Marshall Court's interpretation tended towards supporting a generality norm and also the benefits of a market-preserving federalism (Weingast, Reference Weingast1995). However, this interpretation was turned on its head by the Hughes and Stone Courts; subsequently, the US Congress' carte blanche for expansive and discriminatory powers has been entrenched.

Legal scholars respond to Buchanan

Turning back more decidedly to Buchanan's (Reference Buchanan2005) proposal of a non-discriminatory politics amendment, the responses of two prominent legal scholars (Amar, Reference Amar2005a; Kozinski, Reference Kozinski2005) are informative of the concerns outlined above.

Akhil Reed Amar is one of the foremost scholars of the US Constitution and the history of its interpretation and application (e.g. Amar Reference Amar2005b, Reference Amar2012). He seems puzzled by Buchanan's proposal, asking: ‘What, exactly, is this trying to add above and beyond existing Equal Protection Clause doctrine?’ The Equal Protection Clause is generally associated with the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment and the due process guarantee of the Fifth Amendment.Footnote 32 On the one hand, Amar is suggesting that ‘Equal protection’ under law and ‘non-discriminatory politics’ are prima facie the same thing. On the other hand, his subsequent discussion proceeds along the lines of (paraphrasing): Ok, let's call it ‘nondiscriminatory politics.’ Why do you think that will, in practice, be interpreted any differently?

For example, Amar (Reference Amar2005a) points to Buchanan's (Reference Buchanan2005) discussion of ‘uniform’ taxation. Buchanan claims that a non-discriminatory politics amendment would not imply a repeal of the Sixteenth Amendment (allowing for a federal income tax) but, rather: ‘offer the basis for the replacement of the complex tax structure by a uniform rate of tax that is imposed on all income, without exemptions, deductions, credits, or other special treatments.’ Amar (Reference Amar2005a) notes that the original (pre-Sixteenth Amendment) text:

[D]irect taxes shall be apportioned among the several States […] according to their respective Numbers […] (Article I, Section 2); No capitation, or other direct, Tax shall be laid, unless in Proportion to the Census or Enumeration herein before directed to be taken (Article I, section 9)

was actually interpreted, in a ‘sensible decision’, to uphold ‘progressive’/‘discriminatory’ taxes by the Supreme Court of the 1790s.Footnote 33 It was only a century later that the Supreme Court provided a repudiation of that precedent. That repudiation was an important contributor to the push for the Sixteenth Amendment. Given that amendment is now entrenched, Amar ponders: would Buchanan's non-discriminatory politics amendment be one that ‘prohibits even a standard [income tax] deduction (say, for income below the poverty line) – [which] marks a truly radical break with American constitutional history’. (Moving away from taxation, Amar muses that ‘aid to impoverished orphans might [also] run afoul of nondiscrimination as Buchanan understands it’.)

I infer from his text that Amar is in favour of discriminatory taxation and other policies in certain instances. Buchanan would disagree, but that is not the point. Amar is pointing out that, from the point of view of a constitutional law scholar, (1) what Buchanan calls ‘non-discriminatory politics’ was arguably already included in the Constitutional text; (2) to the extent it was, that text was interpreted in decidedly different ways by different Supreme Courts; and (3) why would we expect otherwise, if a Buchanan-esque change to the text were adopted, moving forward?

Alex Kozinski (2005), a constitutional scholar and a long-time judge on the US Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, raises related concerns in a different way. He states plainly: ‘[A] constitutional constraint [of the type that Buchanan proposes] would pretty much hand over the running of the federal government to the judiciary.’ He continues, poignantly: ‘All government action is inherently discriminatory: The penal codes discriminates against those who commit certain acts [… and] Taxing and spending are inherently discriminatory acts[:] No matter how uniformly a tax is laid, it will fall more heavily on some than on others[.]’Footnote 34

Given that scholars of constitutional law are taken aback by Buchanan's straightforward proposal of writing non-discriminatory politics into the US Constitution, we need to understand why. I argue that they are bemused because they understand that Constitutional text is not the be-all and end-all: (1) that text is always open to interpretation and (2) political entrepreneurs will always be present, seeking opportunities to move interpretations towards the special interests that they embody or represent.

Substance versus procedure

Is the lesson of this paper that Buchanan was wrong to promote de jure Constitutional change towards non-discriminatory politics? I do not believe that is necessarily true. However, this paper points towards an emphasis on procedural versus substantive Constitutional provisions (Wagner and Gwartney, Reference Wagner, Gwartney, Gwartney and Wagner1989). Substantive provisions are those that, for example, state specific rights that the government will either not infringe upon or positively act against infringements upon. Procedural provisions, alternatively, are those that layout the structure of the government, providing the checks and balances between different branches of that government.

Vanberg (Reference Vanberg2011) argues that procedural provisions have advantages over substantive ones. His arguments are based on the idea that procedural provisions, relative to substantive ones, ‘tap into focal understandings that that emerge out of a shared political history [and therefore] may offer better prospects of successful constitutional governance’ (p. 317). This is consistent with the above-cited studies of Hardin (Reference Hardin, Grofman and Wittman1989), Ordeshook (Reference Ordeshook1992), Weingast (Reference Weingast1997), and Hadfield and Weingast (Reference Hadfield, Weingast, Galliani and Sened2014). Vanberg's argument is essentially that procedural provisions are more effective focal points than substantive ones.

We can think about this in terms of the sources of constitutional drift (Salter, Reference Salter2017; Salter and Furton, Reference Salter and Furton2018) discussed in section ‘The limits of generality in constitutional design’ above. First consider the Ambiguity of Rules and, relatedly, the Time-Invariance Rules. These concerns can be relevant to both substantive and procedural provisions. However, they are relatively more important for the former. For example, something like ‘the right of the people to keep and bear Arms’ (US Constitution; Second Amendment) is open to wide interpretation from the get-go of adoption; even more so as the technology of ‘Arms’ evolves. Alternatively, a procedural provision such as the ‘Senate […] shall be composed of two Senators from each State, elected by the people thereof, for six years’ (US Constitution; Seventeenth Amendment) is more clear-cut and, over time, it is difficult to see how technological, socioeconomic, or demographic changes would change the provision's interpretation. As such, the substantive provision may be a less effective focal point than the procedural one.

A similar point can be made in terms of Political Entrepreneurship. Again, as Salter and Wagner (Reference Salter and Young2018: 218) note, there will always be ‘margins of contestation where political entrepreneurship is active in seeking support for alternative constitutional interpretations’. Consistent with the points immediately above, those margins of contestation will be less exploitable in relation to procedural versus substantive provisions. Because the former have less wiggle room in terms of interpretation – both immediately and over time – political entrepreneurs will tend to channel their efforts on the latter.

The Seventeenth Amendment may illustrate this point. Prior to that amendment, Article I, Section 3 dictated that each state's senators be elected by its legislature. Despite the clear-cut nature of that provision, there were informal end-runs that interstate special interests could exploit. For example, prior to 1913 a number of US states approximated direct election via state legislator pledges, public canvases (i.e. when senators publicized the state legislators that would vote for their selection), and direct primaries (Riker, Reference Riker1955; Zywicki, Reference Zywicki1994). But these practices did take hold uniformly. For example, while they were common in western states, they were avoided by southern states (where one-party control allowed legislatures to consistently return senior senators to Washington [Zywicki, Reference Zywicki1994]). At the end of the day, the Article I procedural provision was difficult for interstate special interests to effectively exploit. The margins of contestation were too meagre. This made the movement for the formal Seventeenth Amendment critical despite the informal end-runs.Footnote 35

For the reasons above, the Entrenchment of Non-Generality is less of a risk when it comes to procedural versus substantive Constitutional provisions. If there is less wiggle room for a provision to be perversely (from its authors' point of view) interpreted as favouring special rather than general interests, then there is less of a risk that such a perverse interpretation will be entrenched by court decisions and/or subsequent development of convention based on it.

Additionally, consider Alexander Hamilton's response to objections to the original draft of the US Constitution that it ‘contains no bill of rights’. He argued in the Federalist 84 that any substantive right of value would be provided by procedural checks and balances; and in the absence of such, any codified substantive right provides a mere ‘parchment barrier’ (borrowing James Maddison's terminology) that would not be enforceable.Footnote 36 In other words, substantive rights are implicit in the definition of veto players within the governance structures (Tsebelis, Reference Tsebelis2002). Those veto players – who are particular governance providers – will self-interestedly defend the balance of their powers versus those of other players.Footnote 37 Since the checks and balances are implicit in the balance of powers between veto players, the implied substantive rights are not dependent on wishful parchment.

If procedural checks and balances imply substantive rights, then a corollary is that the removal of the former tends to weaken the latter. The Seventeenth Amendment to the US Constitution – briefly discussed in section ‘Political entrepreneurship’ above – is a case in point. While this amendment obviously did not change any substantive enumerated rights, it does appear to have weakened checks and balances by making Senate and House of Representative makeup and behaviour more similar. For example, Crook and Hibbing (Reference Crook and Hibbing1997) report that, post-amendment, senators were more likely to have had previous experience in government and, more generally, Senate and House elections tended to mirror one another more. (Engstrom and Kernell [Reference Engstrom, Kernell, Brady and McCubbins2007] more recently echo the latter point.) Likewise, Meinke (Reference Meinke2008) reports that senators exhibited ‘behavioral shifts toward mass audience’ (p. 445), including increased sponsorship of bills and roll-call participation, and Gailmard and Jenkins (Reference Gailmard and Jenkins2009) report that senators both became more responsive to the mass electorate and gained leeway to cater to special interests.

What about adding procedural checks and balances? The US case is a difficult one to evaluate: the Bill of Rights was approved by Congress the very year the Constitution went into effect, and then ratified two years later.Footnote 38 However, recent work by Voigt and Gutmann (Reference Voigt and Gutmann2013) is consistent with the importance of procedure versus the codification of substantive rights.Footnote 39 They find that the inclusion of substantive property rights into a Constitution is not strongly associated with their provision; alternatively, they find that the effect becomes more meaningful when conditioned on strong independence of the judicial branch.Footnote 40 Granted, the independence of the judiciary is, itself, not entirely a de jure matter.Footnote 41 Still, Voigt and Gutmann's work is suggestive.

Recent work also points to constitutional checks and balances in medieval Europe as foundational to the development of substantive rights, both political and economic. Obviously, medieval polities did not have Constitutions, but they did have meaningful checks and balances that implied certain substantive rights (e.g. Salter, Reference Salter2015; Salter and Young, Reference Salter and A.T.2018, Reference Salter and Young2019). Furthermore, given the documented gaps between de jure Constitutional provisions and de facto practice on the ground (e.g. Chilton and Versteeg, Reference Chilton and Versteeg2016; Gutmann et al., Reference Gutmann, Metelska-Szaniawska and Voigt2022; Law and Versteeg, Reference Law and Versteeg2013; Voigt, Reference Voigt2021), Vanberg's arguments and Voigt and Gutmann's evidence clearly call for further work to empirically assess the importance of substantive codification versus procedural realities.

Conclusion

James Buchanan was a fervent advocate of a non-discriminatory politics; in other words, he saw value in a generality norm for governance. The author of this paper tends to agree with him.

That being said, Buchanan attempted to translate his views on constitutional political economy into (de jure) Constitutional design in an insufficiently thoughtful way. Writing non-discriminatory politics into a Constitution is unlikely to have the desired effect. All Constitutional language is open to interpretation; and political entrepreneurs representing special interests will be ready to push interpretation in their favoured directions. The history of US Constitutional law bears this out.

Does this mean that Buchanan's quest for constitutionalized non-discriminatory politics must be abandoned? Not necessarily. It does mean that it must be tempered by realistic concerns regarding constitutional design. It also means that focusing on procedural, rather than substantive, Constitutional provisions may be more fruitful.

Acknowledgement

I thank session participants at the 2022 Association for Private Enterprise Education meetings for helpful discussion and comments on this research.

Footnotes

1 While Buchanan's view is a normative one, it is informed by his positive analyses of constitutional political economy. Likewise, while this paper takes issue with Buchanan's reliance on writing generality into de jure constitutions, it does so based on a positive analysis and presentation of evidence.

2 Buchanan and Tullock (Reference Buchanan and Tullock1962) provide the seminal theoretical analysis. The little-c/big-C stylistic distinction is utilized in economics, political science, and constitutional law (e.g. Brennan and Pardo, Reference Brennan and Pardo1991; Elkins and Ginsburg, Reference Elkins and Ginsburg2021; Harris, Reference Harris1993; Michelman, Reference Michelman and Alexander1998).

3 See the interview at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=DP8Ymod_ses. Regarding the ‘by implication’, when you read the text of Buchanan (Reference Buchanan2005) around the Hayek quotations it is clear that Buchanan is in agreement.

4 Even Elkins et al. (Reference Elkins, Ginsburg, Melton, Ginsburg and Huq2016: 233) – scholars who have devoted careers to taking Constitutions seriously – admit that the ‘surprising fact is not that constitutions are often ignored; it is that they guide the behavior of power-hungry leaders at all’. Still, 85% of countries formed post-1789 had a Constitution within two years of their existence (Elkins et al., Reference Elkins, Ginsburg and Melton2009: 41–43). Today, nearly every country has a Constitution. It would, then, be surprising that they devote substantial resources into negotiating and drafting them – as well as amending them ex post – if Constitutions did not matter at all.

5 Also, the flipside of the above-cited empirical studies is that Constitutions do matter in many other countries (i.e. those with small de jurede facto gaps).

6 Intuitively, assume that individuals in a society face a coordination game, i.e. they can all be better off if they behave similarly. (Contrast this to a prisoner's dilemma game where each player can individually benefit by defecting.) Considering constitutional orders, there may be many rule sets that are potential coordination equilibria. A Constitution provides everyone with a specific set of rules. That specific set of rules may not be first-best for the society, but each individual is better off acquiescing to those rules than not. The Constitution makes focusing on that particular coordination equilibrium the lowest-cost option. (See the discussions in Ginsburg [Reference Ginsburg, Sajo and Uitz2010b: 73–75] and Young [Reference Young2022: 11–14].)

7 Conversely, ‘[C]onstitutional content not aligned with its environment is unlikely to be complied with’ (Voigt, Reference Voigt2021: 1780).

8 Notwithstanding, a de jure constitution is still ‘only one element, albeit a very central element, of the larger constitutional order’ (Elkins and Ginsburg, Reference Elkins and Ginsburg2021: 327).

9 Emphasis in the source.

10 In the US, most of us are taught that interpretation of the Constitution is the exclusive realm of the judiciary and, in particular, the Supreme Court. However, the executive and legislative branches play important roles in Constitutional interpretation; often contrary to one another and Supreme Court rulings. For examples, Thomas Jefferson instructed US Attorneys to not prosecute violations of the 1798 Sedition Act because it was unconstitutional; Abraham Lincoln stated clearly in his first inaugural address that he would propose and then enforce legislation inconsistent with the Dred Scott ruling based on his own interpretation of the Constitution; Franklin Roosevelt asked and obliging Congress to pass laws that were decidedly contrary to the Lochner ruling. See Easterbrook (Reference Easterbrook1989); also Amar (Reference Amar2005) on executive review specifically.

11 While certainly to a lesser degree, it would be absurd to think that Supreme Court Justices are not influenced by public pressure (directly from the citizens or indirectly through their elected representatives).

12 Waismann refers to the open texture of ‘empirical concepts’ but a reasonable reading of his paper makes clear that constitutional conventions are specifics that fit comfortably under that penumbra.

13 Barnett (Reference Barnett2001: 108) makes the related point that, even for an originalist, ‘[d]ue to either ambiguity or vagueness, the original meaning of the text may not always determine a unique rule of law[. …] original meaning can be “underdeterminate”. […] When this happens, interpretation must be supplemented by construction – within the bounds established by original meaning’.

14 See Pozen and Schmidt (Reference Pozen and Schmidt2021) for a discussion of the open texture of the US Constitution's Article V and its implications for how successful amendment of the document has and has not occurred, and may or may not be moving forward.

15 Amar (Reference Amar2005a, Reference Amar2005b: 322–326) points to the above, along with the more favourable view of the national army that was associated with the Civil War following Union victory: Reconstruction ‘necessarily valorized the central army and called into question the anti-army ideology driving the Founders’ Second Amendment’ (p. 326).

16 The societal and economic changes referred to need not be exogenous; they may include purposive efforts to change the meaning. See section ‘Political entrepreneurship’ below.

17 Gibbons v. Ogden, 22 U.S. 1, 197 (1824). Marshall sated: ‘Commerce, undoubtedly, is traffic, but it is something more: it is intercourse. It describes the commercial intercourse between nations, and parts of nations, in all its branches, and is regulated by prescribing rules for carrying on that intercourse.’

18 In United States v. Lopez (1995), the first Supreme Court decision in six decades to strike down a statute based on Congress having exceeded its authority under the Commerce Clause, Justice Clarence Thomas' concurring opinion stated: ‘At the time the original Constitution was ratified, “commerce” consisted of selling, buying, and bartering, as well as transporting for these purposes. […] [“Commerce”] was used in contradistinction to productive activities such as manufacturing and agriculture.’

19 https://www.commerce.gov/about (last accessed 8 January 2022).

20 The so-called ‘Dormant Commerce Clause’ (i.e. the exclusivity of the US Congress to regulate interstate trade) is read from Article I, Section 8, Clause 3 combined with Article VI, Clause 2: it was in largest part rooted in Gibbons. Whether the Marshall court was warranted in establishing this precedent is not entirely uncontroversial (e.g. see Berker-Cooper [Reference Berker-Cooper1990] and Redish and Nugent [Reference Redish and Nugent1987]). However, the Marshall Court provided the initial, entrenched interpretation of the Commerce Clause. The important point here is that, more than a century later, a new interpretation of the same verbatim Commerce Clause ended up providing a near carte blanche to the national-level government for what its legislation and regulation could touch.

21 Nebbia v. New York, 291 U.S. 502 (1934); Wickard v. Filburn, 317 U.S. 111 (1942).

22 There would be some rollback during the latter years of the Rehnquist Court (see section ‘Entrenchment of non-generality’ below) but it was marginal and, ultimately, the ratchet effect from the New Deal has left the expansive Commerce Clause powers intact.

23 Salter (Reference Salter2017) and Salter and Furton (Reference Salter and Furton2018) refer to constitutional drift, which is defined in terms of ‘informal constitutions – that is, the state's actual decision procedure, with drift the unintended results of political bargains among political elites’ (Salter, Reference Salter2017: 569). Defined as such, constitutional drift differs from constitutional capture in that the latter represents intended results on the part of political entrepreneurs. Still, broadly conceived of, constitutional drift and capture are both the result of bargains between political elites (using Holcombe's [Reference Holcombe2018] characterization of them as individuals with low political transaction costs).

24 Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1937); Dobbs v. Jackson Women's Health Organization, 597 U.S. ____ (2022); Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992); Gonzales v. Carhart, 550, U.S. 124 (2007). The latter two decisions, respectively, changed the standard for impinging on the abortion right from strict scrutiny to undue burden, and upheld the ability of a state to regulate/outlaw so-called ‘partial-birth abortions’.

25 The only formal amendment from 1973 through 2022 was the Twenty Seventh (ratified 1992), and it clearly had no relevance (event tangential) to abortion rights issues.

26 Of note, sociologists like Staggenborg do not define ‘special interests’ or ‘interest groups’ as broadly as political economists do.

27 While efficiency concerns are not likely at the forefront of many participants in the abortion debate, one can still note that both pro-choice and pro-life groups are competing in a zero-sum game; there are ultimately many redundant resources expended (Tullock, Reference Tullock1967).

28 The relevant texts have fundamentally included those of the Ninth, Thirteenth, and Fourteenth Amendments; peripherally those of the First, Third, Fourth, and Fifth.

29 These acts were controversial and all but one repealed following the Federalists losing power to Thomas Jefferson and the Democratic-Republicans. However, the repeals were a matter of ordinary (rather than constitutional) politics, and Thomas Jefferson was ‘quite willing to limit speech and punish sedition’ (Downy, Reference Downy1998: 694; 694–699 generally).

30 Debs v. US, 249 US 211 (1919).

31 See Bork (Reference Bork1971: 22) and Wu (Reference Wu2018: 551–52).

32 The Equal Protection Clause doctrine primarily developed from the Fourteenth Amendment, which in large part extends constraints on the federal government to state governments. However, subsequent interpretation read from the Fourteenth Amendment back to the due process clause of the Fifth, therefore extending the Equal Protection Clause doctrine to federal government actions.

33 Though not explicitly cited in his response, Amar (Reference Amar2005a) is referencing the ‘luxury’ excise taxes on carriages and certain other goods that was pushed for by Alexander Hamilton (enacted 1794). It turned out to be the first legislative act that was put forth to the Supreme Court for review (Hylton v. United States, 3 U.S. 171 [1796]).

34 Kozinski (2005) continues: ‘[E]vent if the tax is per capita and absolutely uniform, some will see the tax burden of, say, $10,000 as trivial, whereas others will see it as crushing.’ This specifically speaks to the fact that, for an income tax, the burden is different across individuals given each's wealth. Even in the case of a flat income tax rate, then, it is discriminatory across individuals in some sense. (Conversely, if we assume that income is positively correlated with wealth, then one might argue that a progressive income tax ends up, on net, less discriminatory! I am not supporting that view; nut I am noting that that view might be plausibly put forth in interpreting the Constitutional text.)

35 Among the western states, Oregon, Nebraska, and Nevada actually amended their own Constitutions such that the legislatures had to elect senators favoured in popular votes. At the state level, of course, these were formal constitutional changes. However, they changed how (some) US senators were elected without changing the relevant text of the US Constitution.

36 While I employ Maddison's ‘parchment barrier’ here in the spirit of Federalist 84, it is not a specific phrase requoted by Hamilton.

37 Aranson (Reference Aranson1987) makes a complementary argument: the judiciary has its independence by the grace of the legislature and, therefore, refrains from striking down substantive legislation; alternatively, it is more willing to act based on ‘grounds orthogonal to legislative concerns’ (p. 370) (e.g. procedural elements of the Constitution).

38 Since then, the individual substantive rights that have been added to the Constitution have been the Reconstruction Amendments (Thirteenth, Fourteenth, and Fifteenth; obviously entirely different creatures), the right to sell alcohol (Eighteenth; then reversed by the Twenty First), right to vote at 18 years of age (Twenty Sixth).

39 Voigt's (Reference Voigt2011, Reference Voigt2020) works together provide a very effective view of the empirical constitutional political economy literature.

40 Relatedly, Bjønskov (Reference Bjønskov2015) reports that, for transition countries, codification of property rights has no positive (and indeed a negative) effect on subsequent development. Motivated by the positive relationship between economic freedom and growth (Hall and Lawson, Reference Hall and Lawson2014; Young and Sheehan, Reference Young and Sheehan2014), an early paper by de Vanssay and Spindler (Reference de Vanssay and Spindler1994) found that entrenchment of economic freedom-promoting rights in a Constitution had no significant effect on economic growth. Also indirectly speaking to the issues here, Plümper and Martin (Reference Plümper and Martin2003) report that bicameralism is significantly associated with lower government spending.

41 Recall that constitutional judicial review in the US became a convention under the Marshall Court (1801–1835) while not explicitly provided for in the Constitutional text.

References

Amar, A.R. (2005a) Reply to Buchanan. Cato Unbound (December 6). Available at https://www.cato-unbound.org/2005/12/14/james-m-buchanan/response-comments/.Google Scholar
Amar, A.R. (2005b) America's Constitution: A Biography. New York, NY: Random House.Google Scholar
Amar, A.R. (2012) America's Unwritten Constitution: The Precedents and Principles We Live By. New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Aranson, P.H. (1987) Procedural and substantive constitutional protection of economic liberties. Cato Journal 7(2), 345375.Google Scholar
Barnett, R.E. (2001) The original meaning of the Commerce Clause. University of Chicago Law Review 68, 101147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnett, R.E. (2004) Restoring the Lost Constitution: The Presumption of Liberty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Berker-Cooper, S. (1990) The commerce clause: The case for judicial non-intervention. Oregon Law Review 69, 895.Google Scholar
Bjønskov, C. (2015) Constitutional property rights protection and economic growth: Evidence from the post-communist transition. Constitutional Political Economy 26(3), 247280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bork, R.H. (1971) Neutral principles and some first amendment problems. Indiana Law Journal 47(1), 135.Google Scholar
Boudreaux, D.J. and Pritchard, A.C. (1993) Rewriting the constitution: An economic analysis of the constitutional amendment process. Fordham Law Review 62(1), 111162.Google Scholar
Brennan, G. and Pardo, J.C. (1991) A reading of the Spanish Constitution (1978). Constitutional Political Economy 2(1), 5379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brennan, G. and Buchanan, J.M. (1980) The Power to Tax: Analytical Foundations of a Fiscal Constitution. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. (1959) Positive economics, welfare economics, and political economy. Journal of Law and Economics 2(October), 124138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. (1975) The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. (2000 [1975]) The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. (2005) Three amendments: Responsibility, generality, and natural liberty. Cato Unbound (December 4). Available at https://www.cato-unbound.org/2005/12/04/james-m-buchanan/three-amendments-responsibility-generality-natural-liberty/.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. and Tullock, G. (1962) The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Lansing, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J.M. and Congleton, R.D. (2003 [1998]) Politics by Principle, not Interest: Towards Nondiscriminatory Democracy. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Chilton, A.S. and Versteeg, M. (2016) Do constitutional rights make a difference? American Journal of Political Science 60(3), 575589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Congleton, R.D. (2004) Generality and the efficiency of government decision making. In Rowley, CK and Schneider, F (eds.), The Encyclopedia of Public Choice. Boston, MA: Springer.Google Scholar
Congleton, R.D. (2014) The contractarian constitutional political economy of James Buchanan. Constitutional Political Economy 25(1), 3967.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crook, S.B. and Hibbing, J. (1997) A not so distant mirror: The Senate and Congressional change. American Political Science Review 91(4), 845853.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Vanssay, X. and Spindler, Z.A. (1994) Freedom and growth: Do constitutions matter? Public Choice 78(3–4), 359372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, K.L. and Edward, J. (eds.) (2011) The Calculus of Consent and Constitutional Design. New York, NY: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dove, J.A. and Young, A.T. (2019) US state constitutional entrenchment and default in the 19th century. Journal of Institutional Economics 15(6), 963982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downy, M.P. (1998) The Jeffersonian myth in Supreme Court sedition jurisprudence. Washington University Law Quarterly 76(2), 683720.Google Scholar
Easterbrook, F.H. (1989) Presidential review. Case Western Reserve Law Review 40(4), 905929.Google Scholar
Elkins, Z. and Ginsburg, T. (2021) What can we learn from written constitutions? Annual Review of Political Science 24(1), 321343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elkins, Z., Ginsburg, T. and Melton, J. (2009) The Endurance of National Constitutions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elkins, Z., Ginsburg, T. and Melton, J. (2016) Time and constitutional efficiency. In Ginsburg, T and Huq, A (eds.), Assessing Constitutional Performance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Engstrom, E. and Kernell, S. (2007) The effects of presidential elections on party control of the Senate under direct and indirect elections. In Brady, DW and McCubbins, MD (eds.), Party, Process, and Political Change in Congress, Volume 2: Further New Perspectives on the History of Congress. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Epstein, R.A. (1987) The proper scope of the commerce power. Virginia Law Review 73(8), 13871455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, R.A. (2006) How Progressives Rewrote the Constitution. Washington, CD: Cato Institute.Google Scholar
Epstein, R.A. (2014) Constitutional faith and the commerce clause. Notre Dame Law Review 71(2), 167192.Google Scholar
Gailmard, S. and Jenkins, J.A. (2009) Agency problems, the 17th Amendment, and representation in the Senate. American Journal of Political Science 53(2), 324342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garrett, T.A., Kozak, A.F. and Rhine, R.M. (2010) Institutions and government growth: A comparison of the 1890s and 1930s. Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review 92(2), 109119.Google Scholar
Ginsburg, T. (2010a) Public choice and constitutional design. In Farber, D and O'Connell, AJ (eds.), Handbook of Public Choice. UK: Edward Elgar Publishing.Google Scholar
Ginsburg, T. (2010b) Constitutional specificity, unwritten understandings and constitutional agreement. In Sajo, A and Uitz, R (eds.), Constitutional Topography: Values and Constitutions. The Netherlands: Eleven International Publishing.Google Scholar
Gutmann, J., Metelska-Szaniawska, K. and Voigt, S. (2022) The comparative constitutional compliance database. University of Hamburg, Institute of Law and Economics Working Paper 2022 No. 57. Available at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4035701.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hadfield, G.K. and Weingast, B.R. (2014) Constitutions as coordinating devices. In Galliani, S and Sened, I (eds.), Institutions, Property Rights, and Economic Growth. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hall, J.C. and Lawson, R.A. (2014) Economic freedom of the world: An accounting of the literature. Contemporary Economic Policy 32(1), 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, R. (1989) Why a constitution? In Grofman, B and Wittman, D (eds.), The Federalist Papers and the New Institutionalism. New York: Agathon Press.Google Scholar
Harris, W.F. II. (1993) The Interpretable Constitution. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Univ. Press.Google Scholar
Holcombe, R.G. (2018) Political Capitalism: How Economic and Political Power is Made and Maintained. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holcombe, R.G. and Lacombe, D.J. (1998) Interests versus ideology in the ratification of the 16th and 17th Amendments. Economics and Politics 10(2), 143159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kozinski, A. (2005) Reply to Buchanan. Cato Unbound (December 9), https://www.cato-unbound.org/2005/12/09/alex-kozinski/reply-buchanan/.Google Scholar
Landes, W.M. and Posner, R.A. (1975) The independent judiciary in an interest group perspective. Journal of Law & Economics 18(3), 875901.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Law, D.S. and Versteeg, M. (2013) Sham constitutions. California Law Review 101, 863952.Google Scholar
Lehto, O. and Meadowcroft, J. (2021) Welfare without rent seeking? Buchanan's demogrant proposal and the possibility of a constitutional welfare state. Constitutional Political Economy 32(2), 145164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meadowcroft, J. (2020) Buchanan at the American founding: The constitutional political economy of a republic of equals and unequals. Public Choice 183(3), 389403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meinke, S.R. (2008) Institutional change and the electoral connection in the Senate: Revisiting the effects of direct election. Political Research Quarterly 61(3), 445457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michelman, F. (1998) Constitutional authorship. In Alexander, L (ed.), Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations. New York, NY: Cambridge Univ. Press.Google Scholar
Niskanen, W.A. (2005) Odds and Ends. Cato Unbound (December 15), https://www.cato-unbound.org/2005/12/15/william-niskanen/odds-ends/.Google Scholar
Ordeshook, P.C. (1992) Constitutional stability. Constitutional Political Economy 3(2), 137175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plümper, T. and Martin, C.W. (2003) Democracy, government spending, and economic growth: A political-economic explanation of the Barro-effect. Public Choice 117(1–2), 2750.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pozen, D.E. and Schmidt, T.P. (2021) The puzzles and possibilities of Article V. Columbia Law Review 121(8), 23172395.Google Scholar
Redish, M.H. and Nugent, S.V. (1987) The Dormant Commerce Clause and the constitutional balance of federalism. Duke Law Journal 36(4), 569617.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reid, T. (1852) Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, 3rd edn. Cambridge, UK: John Bartlett.Google Scholar
Riker, W.H. (1955) The Senate and American federalism. American Political Science Review 49(2), 452469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runst, P. and Wagner, R.E. (2011) Choice, emergence, and constitutional process: A framework for positive analysis. Journal of Institutional Economics 7(1), 131145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salter, A.W. (2015) Sovereignty as exchange of political property rights. Public Choice 165(1), 7996.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salter, A.W. (2017) Constitutional drift and political: Underappreciated maladies of the political commons. Independent Review 21(4), 569585.Google Scholar
Salter, A.W. and A.T., Young (2018) The Medieval Constitution of Liberty: Political Foundations of Liberalism in the West. Lansing, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Salter, A.W. and Young, A.T. (2019) Polycentric sovereignty: The medieval constitution, governance quality, and the wealth of nations. Social Science Quarterly 100(4), 12411253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salter, A.W. and Furton, G. (2018) Emergent politics and constitutional drift: The fragility of procedural liberalism. Journal of Entrepreneurship and Public Policy 7(1), 3450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salter, A.W. and Wagner, R.E. (2018) Political entrepreneurship, emergent dynamics, and constitutional politics. Review of Social Economy 76(3), 281301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schleicher, D. (2014) The Seventeenth Amendment and federalism in an age of national political parties. Hastings Law Journal 65(C), 10431098.Google Scholar
Soper, J.C. (1994) Political structures and interest group activism: A comparison of the British and American pro-life movements. Social Science Journal 31(3), 319334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Staggenborg, S. (1991) The Pro-Choice Movement: Organization and Activism in the Abortion Conflict. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stigler, G. (1971) The theory of economic regulation. Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science 2(1), 321.Google Scholar
Tsebelis, G. (2002) Veto Players: How Political Institutions Work. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tullock, G. (1967) The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Economic Journal 5, 224–223.Google Scholar
Vanberg, G. (2011) Substance vs. procedure: Constitutional enforcement and constitutional choice. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 80(2), 309318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voigt, S. (2011) Positive constitutional economics II – a survey of recent developments. Public Choice 146(1), 205256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voigt, S. (2020) Constitutional Economics: A Primer. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voigt, S. (2021) Mind the gap – analyzing the divergence between constitutional text and constitutional reality. International Journal of Constitutional Law 19(5), 17781809.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Voigt, S. and Gutmann, J. (2013) Turning cheap talk into economic growth: On the relationship between property rights and judicial independence. Journal of Comparative Economics 41(1), 6673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, R. and Gwartney, J. (1989) Public choice and constitutional order. In Gwartney, J and Wagner, R (eds.), Public Choice and Constitutional Economics. JAI Press.Google Scholar
Waismann, F. (1945) Verifiability: II. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 19(C), 101164.Google Scholar
Weingast, B.R. (1995) The economic role of political institutions: Market-preserving federalism and economic development. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 11(1), 131.Google Scholar
Weingast, B.R. (1997) The political foundations of democracy and the rule of law. American Political Science Review 91(2), 245263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weingast, B.R. (2005) The constitutional dilemma of economic liberty. Journal of Economic Perspectives 19(3), 98108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wenzel, N. (2010) From contract to mental model: Constitutional culture as a fact of the social sciences. Review of Austrian Economics 23(1), 5578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, M. (2017) Encoding interesting times: Managing unpredictability with vague constitutional language. Presented at the Political Studies Association 2017 conference, Glasgow. Available at https://www.psa.ac.uk/sites/default/files/conference/papers/2017/Encoding%20interesting%20times_Williams.pdf.Google Scholar
Wu, T. (2018) Is the First Amendment obsolete? Michigan Law Review 117(3), 547581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, A.T. (2019) How Austrians can contribute to constitutional political economy (and why they should). Review of Austrian Economics 32(4), 281293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, A.T. (2021) The political economy of feudalism in medieval Europe. Constitutional Political Economy 32(1), 127143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, A.T. (2022) Consent or coordination: Assemblies in early medieval Europe. International Review of Law and Economics 72(C).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, A.T. and Sheehan, K.M. (2014) Foreign aid, institutional quality, and growth. European Journal of Political Economy 36(C), 195208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zywicki, T.J. (1994) Senators and special interests: A public choice analysis of the seventeenth amendment. Oregon Law Review 73(C), 10071055.Google Scholar