Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T04:46:58.314Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Relativity, categories and principles in the diuisio aristotelea 67M/32DL

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 March 2023

Roberto Granieri*
Affiliation:
KU Leuven
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The Diuisio Aristotelea 67M/32DL draws a distinction between two categories of beings, per se and relatives. I defend three main theses. First, that the relation of dependence characterizing the members of the latter category is modal and symmetrical in nature and, accordingly, the per se-relatives contrast cannot be equivalent to the substance-accidents contrast. Second, that the type of relativity relevant to this diuisio is both ontological and semantic in nature (but with different emphases depending on the version of the diuisio considered). Third, I argue, against a widespread opinion, that the last line of the DL version of the diuisio does not concern metaphysical principles. Here I also compare the diuisio to other Early Academic bicategorial schemes and show that they differ from one another significantly, especially as far as the alleged connection between categories and metaphysical principles is concerned.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

I. Introduction

The Diuisiones quae dicuntur Aristoteleae (hereafter DA) is a text containing a corpus of ‘divisions’ (διαιρέσϵις), that is, brief and schematic classifications of philosophical concepts. The topics of these classifications are various (for example, soul, virtue, vice, justice, beings), but not in a way that makes the work completely heterogeneous, as all the divisions can be clearly grouped under five rubrics: logical/dialectical, ethical, physical, political and rhetorical.Footnote 1 It has convincingly been suggested that the chief aim of this work was to provide a checklist of certain relevant philosophical concepts that would prove useful for dialectical discussions, scientific accounts or rhetorical discourses.Footnote 2 Thus, the DA likely constituted a scholastic handbook compiled for students.

The DA is a ‘multiple-tradition text’: a text transmitted in different redactions,Footnote 3 even in different languages, for which a unique original model is supposed, albeit impossible to reconstruct. More precisely, the DA has been transmitted in Greek through Diogenes Laertius’ Lives of Eminent Philosophers (Recensio Laertiana)Footnote 4 and six Byzantine manuscripts, which transmit it as an independent text and, as Tiziano Dorandi has recently shown, in three different recensions (labelled by him the Recensio Marciana, Recensio Florentina and Recensio Leidensis, according to the place where the chief codex of each is preserved). These three recensions differ not only from Diogenes’ but also from one another. Thus, we have a total of four different redactions.Footnote 5 Finally, outside of the Greek tradition, the DA is also transmitted by one Syriac and two Arabic translations. All of these translations are supposedly based on a lost Greek exemplar presenting a redaction very similar to the Laertiana, although with significant differences likely due to multiple phases of rewriting, revision and manipulation.Footnote 6

Both the authorship and the historical origins of this text have been subject to intense debate for almost two centuries, that is, at least since the publication of Immanuel Bekker’s edition of Aristotle’s works, from which the DA was excluded, and Valentin Rose’s Aristoteles Pseudepigraphus, where it was first published. The hypotheses have been various: some have argued for an Aristotelian authorship; others have denied it; still others have proposed that the work comes from a text produced by a young Aristotle incorporating doctrines developed by Plato, Aristotle himself and other members of the Academy.Footnote 7 I will not engage with this controversy. Whatever the answer to the question may be, there is one main point that is shared by a substantial majority of scholars and is of genuine interest for the present study: whoever the author(s) of the DA may be, this text quite certainly contains material from the Early Academy. This opinion has been persuasively defended by Eduard Zeller, Wilhelm von Christ, Ernst Hambruch and several others,Footnote 8 and the remainder of this paper is founded on acceptance of the truth of their view.

My goal here is to provide a detailed examination and an overall interpretation of DA 67M/32DL. In all the versions in which it has come down to us, this diuisio draws an exhaustive and exclusive distinction between two categories of beings, dubbed by scholars per se (or absolutes) and relatives. I shall defend three main theses. First, that the relation of dependence characterizing the members of the category of relatives is modal and symmetrical in nature and, accordingly, the per se-relatives contrast cannot be equivalent to the substance-accidents contrast. Second, that the type of relativity relevant to this diuisio is both ontological and semantic in nature (but with different emphases depending on the version of the diuisio considered). Third, I argue, contrary to a common view, that the last line of the DL version of the diuisio does not concern metaphysical principles. In doing so, I also compare the diuisio to other Early Academic bicategorial schemes and show that they differ from one another significantly, especially as far as the alleged connection between categories and metaphysical principles is concerned.

II. Symmetry and modality

We need a modicum of context first. The diuisio under consideration is found only in the Marciana and Laertiana recensions (so neither in the Florentina nor in the Leidensis).Footnote 9 As regards the internal structure of the DA corpus, this diuisio appears to belong to two subgroups. On the one hand, it is one of the divisions concerned with beings (τὰ ὄντα). Besides DA 67M/32DL, this subgroup includes DA 25M, 26M/31DL and 55M/24DL. DA 25M, only attested in the codex Marcianus, presents a threefold classification of beings, by distinguishing those by essence (κατ’ οὐσίαν), by accident (κατὰ συμβϵβηκός) and by affection (κατὰ πάθος). DA 26M/31DL divides beings into indivisible (ἀμϵρῆ) and divisible (μϵριστά), and subdivides the latter into homeomers (ὁμοιομϵρῆ) and anhomeomers (ἀνομοιομϵρῆ). DA 55M/24DL distinguishes beings good (ἀγαθόν), bad (κακόν) and those that are neither (οὐδέτϵρον). On the other hand, only in the Recensio Marciana, DA 67 is also part of another subgroup including DA 64–69 M. These six diuisiones (concerning genus/species, prior/posterior, the whole, beings, opposites and affirmation/negation) constitute a unified cluster, as they explicitly recall one another.Footnote 10

I shall examine DA 67M/32DL by considering first the version of Recensio Laertiana and then that of the Marciana. Here is text of the Recensio Laertiana:

T1: τῶν ὄντων τὰ μέν ἐστι καθ’ ἑαυτά, τὰ δὲ πρός τι λέγϵται. τὰ μὲν οὖν καθ’ ἑαυτὰ λϵγόμϵνά ἐστιν ὅσα ἐν τῇ ἑρμηνϵίᾳ μηδϵνὸς προσδϵῖται· ταῦτα δ’ ἂν ϵἴη οἷον ἄνθρωπος, ἵππος καὶ τἆλλα ζῷα. τούτων γὰρ οὐδὲν δι’ ἑρμηνϵίας χωρϵῖ. τῶν δὲ πρός τι λϵγομένων ὅσα προσδϵῖταί τινος ἑρμηνϵίας, οἷον τὸ μϵῖζόν τινος καὶ τὸ θᾶττόν τινος καὶ τὸ κάλλιον καὶ τὰ τοιαῦτα· τό τϵ γὰρ μϵῖζον ἐλάττονός ἐστι μϵῖζον καὶ τὸ θᾶττον <θᾶττόν> τινός ἐστι. τῶν ὄντων ἄρα τὰ μὲν αὐτὰ καθ’ αὑτὰ λέγϵται, τὰ δὲ πρός τι.

ὧδϵ καὶ τὰ πρῶτα διῄρϵι κατὰ τὸν Ἀριστοτέλη.Footnote 11

Among beings, some are spoken of per se, others relatively to something. The things which are spoken of per se need nothing in the expression. These might be, for example, a human being, a horse and other animals. For none of these proceeds in virtue of an expression. The things which are spoken of relatively to something are such that they need a certain expression, for example, what is larger than something or faster than something or more beautiful and alike.Footnote 12 For the larger is larger than the smaller, and the faster is faster than something. Among beings, then, some are spoken of per se, others relatively to something.

In this way, according to Aristotle, <Plato> also divided the primary things.

T1 draws a dichotomous distinction between two classes of beings or categories.Footnote 13 Arguably, the author(s) took the distinction to be exhaustive, as the use of the τὰ μέν … τὰ δέ construction throughout the DA seems consistently to suggest.Footnote 14 So, the whole domain of beings is here divided into two jointly exhaustive classes: on the one hand, that of beings spoken of by themselves, or simply per se (τὰ μέν καθ’ ἑαυτά); on the other, that of beings spoken of relatively to another (τὰ δὲ πρός τι).

One attractive way of understanding the philosophical import of this bicategorial distinction focuses on the examples of per se beings mentioned by Diogenes. These examples are ἄνθρωπος, ἵππος and τἆλλα ζῷα, that is, items one would tend to recognize as Aristotelian substances. In Aristotle’s doctrine of the categories, substances are contrasted with the other nine categories, in that the former are prior to all of the latter λόγῳ καὶ γνώσϵι καὶ χρόνῳ (Metaph. Z 1.10128a31–1028b7), such priority being the main grounds for the so-called doctrine of πρὸς ἕν homonymy defended in Metaph. Γ 2. Thus, the relation of dependence of non-substances to substances is asymmetrical. For it cannot be the case that if, say, a quality is dependent upon a substance, then a substance is also dependent upon a quality. One might suggest that a similar type of relation is operative in T1 and that the examples of per se beings mentioned in the diuisio suggest that T1 draws a distinction between a class of metaphysically fundamental beings and one of metaphysically dependent beings (i.e. dependent on the fundamental ones). Hence, on this reading, the τι to which a πρός τι being is relative is a per se being; and a πρός τι being exists because there is a per se being that exists and is metaphysically explanatory of the existence of a πρός τι being. A reading along these lines is proposed for example by Gail Fine,Footnote 15 who argues that our diuisio ‘distinguishes between substances and non-substances, for we have independent evidence that the distinction was of central concern in the Academy’.Footnote 16

Attractive as this interpretation may be, I believe it does not have the cogency claimed for it. The text posits that the two classes of beings are distinguished on the basis of two different predicative behaviours of the terms that signify them: per se beings are such that the terms that signify them do not need any ἑρμηνϵία, whereas those signifying relative beings do.Footnote 17 A proper understanding of the notion of ἑρμηνϵία is therefore important for a correct interpretation. The meaning of this word in the ancient Greek philosophical vocabulary, notably with regard to the title and σκοπός of Aristotle’s De interpretatione, is notoriously controversial.Footnote 18 However, I do not think this proves particularly puzzling as far as the translation and interpretation of T1 is concerned. LSJ and standard Greek etymological dictionaries list as the main meanings of ἑρμηνϵία ‘interpretation’, ‘explanation’ and ‘expression’, especially of thoughts by words.Footnote 19 The term ἑρμηνϵία and its cognates are found with these meanings, which I do not regard as technical, in several places of the Platonic, Aristotelian and Xenophontean corpora.Footnote 20 My sense is that ‘expression’ is the preferable translation of ἑρμηνϵία in T1.Footnote 21 I take ἑρμηνϵία here to designate a semantic or syntactic supplement (as LSJ puts it: ‘an expression of thoughts by words’), of the form of a complement of specification, here indicated by the indefinite pronoun τινός at l. 109.1196. Without such a syntactic supplement (explicitly stated or implicitly presupposed in an elliptical sentence) a given predicate cannot be meaningful (i.e. cannot form a well-formed sentence when predicated of a given subject). This is the case of a predicate that stands for a relative being. By contrast, a per se being is signified by a predicate which does not ‘proceed in virtue of an expression’ (οὐδὲν δι’ ἑρμηνϵίας χωρϵῖ), that is, one that does not need such a syntactic supplement.Footnote 22

The text lends support to this reading. As previously mentioned, the diuisio posits that the two classes of beings are distinguished on the basis of two different predicative behaviours of the terms that signify them: per se beings do not need any ἑρμηνϵία, whereas relative beings do. It follows that the two categories, in addition to being jointly exhaustive, are mutually exclusive (it is not the case that a single predicate can have both predicative behaviors). When it comes to explaining what it means to need an ἑρμηνϵία, the text offers no explicit clarification of this notion, but provides some examples (οἷον). These examples are all comparatives (τὸ μϵῖζόν καὶ τὸ θᾶττόν καὶ τὸ κάλλιον καὶ τὰ τοιαῦτα) whose counterparts (i.e. the τι to which a πρός τι entity is relative) are first each referred to with an indefinite pronoun (τινος), but then one of them, that of τό μϵῖζον, is unequivocally identified as a correlative (ἐλάττονος). Comparatives are relatives in that they need the expression or syntactic supplement of a complement of specification in order, when predicated of a subject x, to make a well-formed sentence. Thus, if I predicate ‘larger’ (μϵῖζον) of a subject x, I must add a complement like ‘than y’ (explicitly stated or implicitly presupposed in an elliptical sentence), otherwise the sentence ‘x is larger’ is not well-formed and does not constitute a meaningful grammatical unit.Footnote 23 The y variable here stands for a correlative (or an item qua correlative),Footnote 24 which must be ‘smaller’ (ἐλάττονός) than x.

If this reading is correct, two further remarks are in order. First, Diogenes’ text draws a distinction between categories of beings, as signified by complete and incomplete predicates .Footnote 25 This is a classification of items in the attribute mode (i.e. qua attributes of subjects).Footnote 26 A per se being is signified by a semantically or syntactically complete predicate. A relative being is signified by a semantically or syntactically incomplete predicate. A syntactically incomplete predicate is a predicate that needs to be supplied with an additional linguistic expression, namely a complement, in order to constitute a well-formed sentence, when it is predicated of a certain subject (for example, ‘Four is the double of…’). A syntactically complete predicate, by contrast, does not need such a supplement (for example, ‘Paul is a human being’). A semantically incomplete predicate is one that may not be syntactically incomplete, but whose semantics suggests an implicit reference to another item (for example, ‘Mathematics is a science’, which is a syntactically complete expression, but suggests that mathematics is the science of something, namely numbers, as being a science is always said in relation to something, i.e. to the object of that science). Semantically complete predicates do not suggest so (for example, ‘Humans are bipedal’).

Second, the relation of dependence this diuisio draws upon, unlike that between Aristotelian substances and non-substances, is symmetrical. For the relation between correlatives must be symmetrical: what is faster is always said of something slower, and what is slower is always said of something faster. Further, as well as being symmetrical, this relation of dependence is also modally qualified in the text,Footnote 27 by two occurrences of the compound verb προσδϵῖται (ll. 1193, 1195). This verb is a composite of the preposition πρός plus the verb δέομαι, which obviously has a modal semantic colour, notably in the third person singular and in impersonal constructions. In other words, the verb προσδϵῖταί establishes that an expression must be provided (i.e. is a necessary condition) for a πρός τι predicate to constitute a meaningful grammatical unit. Thus, in T1 the relation of dependence between a πρός τι predicate and its ‘expression’ (ἑρμηνϵία) is symmetrical and modal in nature.

One might object that the fact remains that the examples of per se beings are items that we would recognize as Aristotelian substances. Undoubtedly. But this is outweighed by two pieces of evidence. First, the examples of relative beings include only relatives, not members of any of the other nine non-substantial categories. Second, the specification of the criterion of distinction between the two classes of beings in terms of ἑρμηνϵία cannot fit the substance-accidents contrast. In other words, the need of an ἑρμηνϵία cannot be identical or comparable to the πρὸς ἕν relation explored in Metaph. Γ 2 or the ‘being-in-a-subject’ relation described in Cat. 2.Footnote 28 Hence, the rest of the division suggests that the αὐτὰ καθ’ ἑαυτά class should include all the items denoted by syntactically or semantically complete predicates: thus even predicates which in the Aristotelian categorial scheme stand for qualities, quantities and so on (i.e. all nine non-relative categories). Interestingly enough, this seems to be how Clement of Alexandria (Strom. VIII 24.1 Stählin–Früchtel–Treu), as well as Simplicius (in Cat. 174.16–20 Kalbfleisch) and Galen (Dig. Puls. II 2.839,13–16 Kuhn) conceived of the καθ᾽αὑτά-πρός τι contrast.Footnote 29

Now, the version of the Recensio Marciana:

T2: τῶν ὄντων τὰ μὲν αὐτὰ καθ’ ἑαυτά ἐστι, τὰ δὲ πρός τι. αὐτὰ μὲν οὖν καθ’ ἑαυτά ταῦτά ἐστιν, οἶον ἄνθρωπος οἰκία ἱμάτιον χρυσίον καὶ πάντα ὅσα ἁπλῶς, μὴ τῷ ἕτϵρόν τι ϵἶναι ἐi ἀνάγκης ἐστι, τὰ δὲ πρός τι τοιαῦτα ἐστὶν οἶον τὸ διπλάσιον καὶ ἡ ἐπιστήμη. τό τϵ γὰρ διπλάσιον πρὸς τὸ ἥμισυ λέγϵται καὶ ἡ ἐπιστήμη πρὸς ἄλλο τι.

Among beings, some are per se, others are relative to something. Per se are those, for example, a human being, a house, a dress, a coin and all such things which are in an absolute way, and do not necessarily exist accompanied by the existence of something else. Those which are relative to something, instead, are of such kind, for example, double and science; for double is said relatively to half and science relatively to something else.

Just as in T1, this text too proposes a dichotomous division into two jointly exhaustive classes: on the one hand, that of beings in themselves by themselves, or simply per se (τὰ μὲν αὐτὰ καθ’ ἑαυτά); on the other, that of relative beings (τὰ δὲ πρός τι). Yet, unlike T1, T2 does not make any reference to the notion of ἑρμηνϵία to explain the difference between these two classes. Rather, it posits that per se beings exist in an absolute way (ἁπλῶς). This adverbial qualification would not in itself be very illuminating if it were not in turn clarified by a further explanatory remark: things that are ἁπλῶς are such that they do not necessarily need, for their own existence, something different to exist as well. By contrast, this is the distinctive status of relative beings. Such a characterization suggests that a relation of dependence is at play here.

Two relevant details clarify how the notion of dependence is conceived of in this context. First, the phrase ἐi ἀνάγκης, which, I submit, stands for a modal operator (analogous to προσδϵῖταί in T1) and thus suggests once again a modal analysis of the relation of dependence. The second detail is the crucial phrase τῷ ἕτϵρόν τι ϵἶναι. One attractive interpretation of this phrase is that the article in the dative case stands for a phrase such as ‘in virtue of’ or ‘because’ and thus imposes a modification of the modal relation of dependence that makes it asymmetrical. This would mark a major difference from the relation of dependence characterizing the πρός τι class in T1, as it was accounted for earlier in this section. For the diuisio would be drawing a distinction between a class of metaphysically fundamental beings and another of metaphysically dependent beings (i.e. dependent on the fundamental ones: a πρός τι being exists because there exists a per se being that is metaphysically explanatory of the existence of that πρός τι being). Once again, the resulting relation of dependence displayed here would be very close to that between Aristotelian substances and non-substances. One might even go so far as to say that, if this reading is correct, it would also constitute indirect evidence against the proposed interpretation of T1.

Yet, just as for T1, this interpretation is unpersuasive. First, the examples used by the author(s) of the diuisio seem to restrict membership to the πρός τι class only to items denoted by syntactically or semantically incomplete predicates, such as ‘double’ or ‘science’. However, this would mean that the τι to which a πρός τι entity is relative (i.e. the τι whose existence is required for the existence of a πρός τι entity) is not a per se being, but a correlative. The explanation of the examples provided in the last line of the diuisio supports this reading: what a double is, is always said in relation to a half (i.e. its correlative); and what a science is, is always said in relation to its object (again, its correlative).Footnote 30 Accordingly, the article in the dative case cannot stand for an expression such as ‘in virtue of’ or ‘because’, which would make the modal relation of dependence asymmetrical, too. The relation between correlatives, once again, must be symmetrical.Footnote 31 For this reason, I translated the dative articular infinitive as ‘accompanied by the existence of something else’. Hence, for both T1 and T2, the relation of dependence characterizing the members of the πρός τι category is modal and symmetrical in nature and, thus, the per se-relatives contrast cannot be equivalent to the substance-accidents contrast.

III. Types of relativity

Commenting on the eighth sceptical mode, Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes make the following remark:

the notion of relativity is itself a complex one. The Greeks speak frequently of ta pros ti, ‘things relative to something’; but behind that uniform nomenclature there stand several different accounts or theories of relativity. Different philosophical schools offered different analyses of ta pros ti.Footnote 32

This is certainly true and we should therefore ask which notion of relativity is operative in DA 67M/32DL. In their analysis of the eighth mode Annas and Barnes single out three types of relativity: epistemic, ontological and semantic. For x to be epistemically relative to y, x is not recognizable or knowable without y. For x to be ontologically relative to y, x cannot exist without y. For F to be semantically relative to y, sentences of the form ‘x is F’ need a syntactic or semantic supplement such that they can make sense only if they are elliptical for sentences of the form ‘x is F in relation to y’.Footnote 33

It is perhaps natural to suggest that the notion of relativity operative in T1 is semantic in nature. The most telling textual signposts in this regard are, on the one hand, the several occurrences of forms of the verb λέγϵιν (λέγϵται (ll. 1191, 1199), λϵγόμϵνα (l. 1192) and λϵγομένων (l. 1195)) and, on the other, the very notion of ἑρμηνϵία, which, as I argued, here means ‘expression’. Thus, the linguistic and semantic dimensions are certainly prominent in the Recensio Laertiana. And yet, I suggest that the text is not concerned solely with semantics. For the subject of the diuisio is τὰ ὄντα: DA 32DL is and is intended to be a bicategorial distinction of beings. Beings, and not words or concepts, are here divided. The modality of their division appeals to semantics, however. And one might well suppose that, far from excluding every notion of ontological relativity, the author(s) of this scholastic handbook of divisions simply found it explanatorily or didactically more perspicuous to present the per se-relatives contrast in terms of syntax and semantics. In other words, a double cannot exist without a half, both in the sense that a sentence of the form ‘four is double’ needs the supplement ‘of two’ (which is the half of four) and in the sense that the property of being double and that of being a half necessarily do or do not exist together. Accordingly, the dominant notion of relativity operative in T1 is certainly the semantic one, but the opening genitive τῶν ὄντων suggests an ontological nuance.Footnote 34

It is likewise natural to suggest that the notion of relativity operative in T2 is ontological in nature. The most telling textual signposts in this regard are the multiple occurrences of forms of the verb ϵἶναι: ἐστι(ν) (ll. 11, 12, 13), ϵἶναι (l. 12). So, the ontological aspect is certainly prominent in the Recensio Marciana. Yet again, I submit that the text is not concerned solely with ontology. For at l. 14 the verb λέγϵται suggests that the per se-relatives contrast concerns both beings and their linguistic correlates (i.e. predicates). The ‘double-half’ example also fits this remark perfectly well.Footnote 35

I shall conclude this brief section by suggesting that, rather than striving to single out one particular notion of relativity operative in each of the two recensions, it seems more advisable to talk about different, but not exclusive, emphases. T1 insists more on the linguistic aspect of the division, whereas T2 stresses the ontological aspect. In other words, I take both divisions to be concerned with beings as they are signified by the appropriate predicates,Footnote 36 with T1 focusing more on the semantic features of those predicates, and T2 focusing more on the ontological features of the beings those predicates signify.Footnote 37

IV. Principles?

I shall devote the last section of my paper to the final sentence of T1: ὧδϵ καὶ τὰ πρῶτα διῄρϵι κατὰ τὸν Ἀριστοτέλη. A question arises from the outset: what exactly are τὰ πρῶτα? Several commentators have taken this phrase to indicate the first ‘principles’ of Plato’s unwritten metaphysics, shared and developed by some members of the Academy, notably Xenocrates. These principles are traditionally called the One and the Indefinite Dyad. According to this reading, the diuisio would be establishing a relationship between two distinctions, one concerning categories and the other concerning metaphysical principles. These commentators take this relationship to be explanatory in nature (the explanation in question being metaphysical, i.e. dependence). I will call this interpretation the “Categories-Principles Interpretation”.Footnote 38

To understand better the grounds of this reading, it should first be recalled that DA 67M/32DL is only one of several examples of bicategorial distinction in the Early Academy.Footnote 39 There are at least three other relevant texts: Simpl. in Cat. 63.21–24 Kalbfleisch = Xenocrates F 15 IP2; Alexander Aphrodisiensis. in Metaph. 56.13–21 Hayduck = Arist. De bono fr. 2 Ross; Simpl. in Phys. 247.30–248.15 Diels = Hermodorus F 5 IP2.Footnote 40 Supporters of the Categories-Principles Interpretation think that these texts report, with some variations, an identical basic doctrine, in that they divide beings into two categories, and then trace them back to the two first principles.

More precisely, it has been suggested that the bicategorial scheme constituted the basis for a ‘categorial reduction argument’, which was meant to support the very postulation of those metaphysical principles. The argument goes roughly as follows: once the whole domain of beings is divided up into two categories, one will be in a position to see the general distinctive ontological features of each category (i.e. to be per se and to be relative to something else) and, finally, to recognize the pair of supreme metaphysical principles upon which those categories depend and which ultimately explain those ontological features.

Further, so the exegetical hypothesis continues, some of these texts, namely our T1, Arist. De bono fr. 2 Ross, and Hermodorus F 5 IP2, are consistent in attributing this doctrine to Plato himself; but since there is no clear trace of such a tenet in the dialogues, this must have been part of Plato’s unwritten teachings.Footnote 41 Thus, according to the Categories-Principles Interpretation, there is a common and persistent doctrinal scheme shared by all these Early Academic texts, according to which there is a relation of dependence between the two categories and the two metaphysical principles. In what follows, I will try to show that the Categories-Principles Interpretation is misleading, both as an exegesis of the last line of T1 and, more generally, as a reconstruction of an alleged ‘Academic doctrine of the categories’.

We should bear in mind that the last line of T1 constitutes the end of the entire corpus of divisions reported by Diogenes. This corpus begins as follows: διῄρϵι δέ, φησὶν Ἀριστοτέλης, καὶ τὰ πράγματα τοῦτον τὸν τρόπον (Diog. Laert. 3 80.864–65). Clearly, this initial statement symmetrically corresponds with the last line of T1 (ὧδϵ καὶ τὰ πρῶτα διῄρϵι κατὰ τὸν Ἀριστοτέλη). Apart from the occurrence of the same verb (διῄρϵι) and a parallel structuring of the formula, the explicit reference to Aristotle’s name, which does not appear in any diuisio in between, makes the correspondence unequivocal. It follows that, just as the opening sentence does not belong to any diuisio, it has no relevant doctrinal content and is nothing but an introductory clause to the corpus, so too the last line, I submit, does not belong to any diuisio, has no relevant doctrinal content and is nothing but a concluding clause to the corpus. In other words, the last line of T1 is not part of DA 32DL.Footnote 42 It does not matter for my present purposes whether Diogenes himself inserted these clauses in the text or whether he found them in the source he copied, and I would rather suspend my judgement on this question, although I am inclined to believe that the latter was the case. What does matter, instead, is that no philosophical point is made in the final line of T1.Footnote 43

I foresee two possible objections. First, the fact remains that the last line of T1 invokes τὰ πρῶτα. What else could they designate other than metaphysical principles? I answer that the pendant between the introductory and the concluding clauses rather suggests that τὰ πρῶτα is more naturally read in relation to the initial τὰ πράγματα.Footnote 44 After all, there is only one other occurrence of the adjective πρῶτος, η, ον, in Diogenes Laertes’ DA (l. 1106) and it has nothing to do with metaphysical principles. But if this is the case, one might reply, it is unclear in what sense the divisions listed by Diogenes might be ‘first’. One speculative hypothesis is that the reference is to those of the other recensions that have been transmitted to us and are missing from the Laertiana. But this hypothesis will not do, as Diogenes does not appear to be aware of any other group of divisions, nor is there any mention of an integration of the provided list. More reasonably, τὰ πρῶτα means ‘the chief things’ or ‘the primary things’, and we can speculate that since the DA was a scholastic handbook, Diogenes or (more likely) his source compiled a selection of (the main) divisions for didactic purposes.

The second objection concerns the phrase ὧδϵ καὶ. Does this not clearly indicate a connection with DA 32 (‘in this way too’) and suggest that Diogenes is proposing an analogy between a distinction concerning categories and another concerning metaphysical principles? It does not. For one thing, there is a καὶ in the introductory clause as well (καὶ τὰ πράγματα κτλ.), which of course has no connection whatsoever with what precedes it. For another, nothing compels us to think that the demonstrative ὧδϵ refers precisely to the bicategorial distinction just drawn and not to the divisional procedure implemented throughout the corpus. Again, the introductory clause is most helpful for a sober exegesis: ὧδϵ is more naturally interpreted as the concluding counterpart of the initial τοῦτον τὸν τρόπον (ll. 864–65). In other words, ὧδϵ καὶ is an expository formula with no doctrinal bearing.

Accordingly, the Categories-Principles Interpretation is untenable as a reading of T1. But I would also like to show that it is not a consistent interpretative proposal in itself. The contents of the other testimonies reporting Early Academic bicategorial schemes, I submit, differ significantly from one another and can hardly be reduced to a single coherent doctrine, especially as far as the putative connection between categories and principles is concerned.

The text of Xenocrates’ F 15 IP2 is the following:

T4: ἄλλοι δὲ κατ’ ἄλλον τρόπον αἰτιῶνται τὴν πϵριττότητα. οἰ γὰρ πϵρὶ Ξϵνοκράτη καὶ Ἀνδρόνικον πάντα τῷ καθ᾽ αὑτὸ καὶ τῷ πρός τι πϵριλαμβάνϵιν δοκοῦσιν, ὥστϵ πϵριττὸν ϵἶναι κατ’ αὐτοὺς τὸ τοσοῦτον τῶν γϵνῶν πλῆθος.

Others raise the accusation of superfluity in another way. Xenocrates and Andronicus and their followers seem to include all things in [the opposition] per se and relative, so that, according to them, so large a multitude of genera is superfluous.Footnote 45

The text reports that Xenocrates defended a bicategorial doctrine (against Aristotle’s tenfold scheme), but it makes no reference whatsoever to first principles.Footnote 46 So, one would naturally conclude that it should be regarded as uninformative about the categories-principles relation. Still, it has been speculated, for example by Margherita Isnardi Parente,Footnote 47 that since Xenocrates had a doctrine of principles, he too might have posited a connection between categories and principles. In other words, the speculative argument would be that since (1) in other sources, such as T1, Arist. De bono fr. 2 Ross and Hermodorus F 5 IP2, the bicategorial distinction is somehow connected to the metaphysics of principles, and since (2) Xenocrates defended both a bicategorial distinction and a metaphysics of principles, it follows that (3) for Xenocrates, too, the two theories were connected. But there are two serious problems with this reconstruction. For one thing, this speculation simply has no support in the texts. There is no trace in the extant Xenocratean fragments of an alleged connection between the bicategorial distinction and the metaphysics of principles.

It is also impossible to illuminate how exactly the two theories might have been connected for Xenocrates. The only putative (indirect) evidence to illuminate this point is found in the very Early Academic texts I am presently examining, as is clear from premise (1) in the previous argument. But not only do these texts differ from one another significantly, as we will see shortly, it would also be arbitrary to ascribe their doctrines to Xenocrates. Further, since one would need to supply claims and arguments from other Early Academic sources to interpret Xenocrates’ alleged view about the categories-principles connection, it would be methodologically circular to use Xenocrates’ fragment in turn to interpret any of them, including T1. Hence, Xenocrates’ F 15 IP2 is also of no use to illuminate the categories-principles relation in T1.

In Arist. De bono fr. 2 Ross, it is said that, according to Plato, ‘the equal and the unequal are the principles of all things, both of those per se and of the opposites’ (τὸ ἴσον καὶ τὸ ἄνισον ἀρχὰς ἁπἁντων τῶν τϵ καθ’ αὑτὰ ὄντων καὶ τῶν ἀντικϵιμένων). Leaving aside the significant fact that the second category is named differently from all the other texts, it should be observed that the grammar of this sentence demands that each category must depend upon both principles.Footnote 48 Aristotle does not say that per se beings are traced back to the One and ἀντικϵίμϵνα to the Dyad. Instead, each category derives from the ‘cooperation’ of both principles.

Finally, I shall briefly consider Hermodorus’ F 5 IP2. This fragment is certainly too complex to be explored here in any detail.Footnote 49 But for the present purposes it is crucial to stress that Hermodorus recognized only one supreme principle. What other members of the Academy recognized as a second principle Hermodorus describes as essentially privative, passive and deprived of causal efficacy. Accordingly, it is for Hermodorus not a substance and not a principle. Here is the relevant passage of F 5 IP2 which corroborates this point:

T5: ὥστϵ ἄστατον καὶ ἄμορφον καὶ ἄπϵιρον καὶ οὐκ ὂν τὸ τοιοῦτον λέγϵσθαι κατὰ ἀπόφασιν τοῦ ὄντος. τῷ τοιούτῳ δὲ οὐ προσήκϵιν οὔτϵ ἀρχῆς οὔτϵ οὐσίας, ἀλλ’ ϵ̓ν ἀκρισίᾳ τινὶ φέρϵσθαι. δηλοῖ γὰρ ὡς ὃν τρόπον τὸ αἴτιον κυρίως καὶ διαφέροντι τρόπῳ τὸ ποιοῦν ϵ̓στιν, οὕτως καὶ ἀρχή, ἡ δὲ ὕλη οὐκ ἀρχή. διὸ καὶ τοῖς πϵρὶ Πλἁτωνα ϵ̓λέγϵτο μία, ὅτι ἡ ἀρχή.

Consequently, such a thing, being unstable and formless and unlimited and a not-being, is described by negation of being, and to such a thing neither principle nor substance is appropriate, but it is driven into confusion. For [Plato] makes clear that just as in one way what acts is the cause in the strict sense and distinctively, so too it is a principle. But matter is not a principle, and therefore also it was said by those around Plato that there is one principle.Footnote 50

Hermodorus is therefore a monist about metaphysical principles. He does not accept the correspondence between categories and principles, as it is proposed by the Categories-Principles Interpretation for the very simple reason that there is place for only one principle in his metaphysics.

The three texts I have just discussed invite us to resist the Categories-Principles Interpretation. They show that neither the relata of the connection between categories and principles nor the nature of the connection itself are identical across all these testimonies. The only thing that these texts seem to share is the basic scheme of a twofold division of beings. Accordingly, they can hardly be reduced to a single, persistent, doctrinal body. In other words, there seems to have been nothing like an ‘Academic doctrine of the categories’ or a ‘categorial reduction argument’. The evidence attests little more than a series of modest attempts to divide beings into two categories (sometimes with different names) that are occasionally connected, in different ways, to the doctrine of principles.

V. Conclusions

The study of the meagre remnants attesting bicategorial distinctions in the Early Academy may make (and has made) it tempting to downplay the originality of Aristotle’s contrast between substances and accidents by tracing it back to the doctrines of other members of Plato’s schools or to a purported ‘Academic doctrine of the categories’ shared by several of Plato’s disciples. In this paper, my aim has been to show that, as far as Diuisio Aristotelea 67M/32DL is concerned, such a reconstruction is unconvincing. I have shown that the relation of dependence characterizing the members of the πρός τι category is modal and symmetrical in nature and, thus, the per se-relatives contrast cannot be equivalent to the substance-accidents contrast.

In addition, I have defended two further theses. The first is that the type of relativity relevant to this diuisio is both ontological and semantic in nature (but with different emphases depending on the version of the diuisio considered). Second, I have argued that the last line of the DL version of the diuisio does not concern metaphysical principles. In so doing, I also compared the diuisio to other Early Academic bicategorial schemes and showed that they differ significantly, especially as far as the alleged connection between categories and metaphysical principles is concerned. Accordingly, not only is the Aristotelian contrast between substances and accidents different from that between per se and relatives that we find in some Early Academic categorial accounts, but these very accounts in turn differ significantly. Thus, I think it is inaccurate to speak of an ‘Academic doctrine of the categories’, as if it were a uniform view shared by the members of the Early Academy.

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this paper have been presented in Durham and Toronto. I am grateful to those audiences for valuable discussions and to Luc Brisson, Tiziano Dorandi, Mark Gatten, Lloyd Gerson, Jaap Mansfeld, Matt Watton and the two anonymous referees for helpful comments on earlier drafts.

Funding Statement

This paper is part of a project that has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (Grant agreement no. 885273).

Footnotes

1 Cf. Berti (Reference Berti and Rossitto2005) 10–11 and Dorandi (Reference Dorandi2016a) 2. I am much indebted to the latter paper for information about the text and the transmission of the DA. As Berti notes, this grouping might seem artificial as it is based on a typically Aristotelian order. However, it is also echoed in DA 42 M, so its application is legitimate. Unless otherwise noted, translations are my own. Greek texts are quoted according to the following editions: Dorandi (Reference Dorandi2013) for Diogenes Laertius; Dorandi (Reference Dorandi2016a) for the Recensio Marciana of DA; other texts are quoted according to standard editions.

3 These differences in redaction probably result from the transmission of the text and have nothing to do with the intention of the author(s).

4 Diogenes transmits a set of 32 divisions in the last section of the third book of the Lives, devoted to Plato’s biography. The corpus has no title but is introduced and concluded by mentioning Aristotle’s name: for Diogenes affirms that these divisions were made by Plato and reported by Aristotle (more later). Further details on these manuscripts can be found in Dorandi (Reference Dorandi, Algra, van der Horst and Runia1997) and (Reference Dorandi2016a). The name Recensio Laertiana is also due to Dorandi.

5 This conclusion of Dorandi marks a substantive point of departure from the last available editions of the text, i.e. Mutschmann (Reference Mutschmann1906) and Gigon (Reference Gigon1987), who both prioritized the Laertiana and Marciana only, since they did not know about the other recensions.

6 This branch of the tradition of the DA has also been studied by Dorandi, in a 2017 paper co-authored with Issam Marjiani, but the three translations had already been edited by Brock (Reference Brock, Coda and Martini Bonadeo2014) (Syriac) and Kellerman-Rost (Reference Kellermann-Rost1965) (Arabic). On this note, it is worth mentioning that the DA had a vast and long-lasting diffusion. Not only does Diogenes’ Lives attest that this text was still circulating in the third century CE, but Pasquali (Reference Pasquali1910), followed by Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld and Battegazzore1992a) 370–71 with n.83, has shown that there are still traces of it in Late Antiquity, as proved by an unambiguous reference in a scholium (200.4–5) to Basil of Caesarea’s in Hexaemeron. Further, Dorandi (Reference Dorandi, Casanova, Messeri and Pintaudi2016b) has spotted traces of the DA diairetic method in a medical text datable to the first century CE, transmitted from the Papyrus inv. 137 of the British Library (P. Lit. Lond. 165), also known as the Anonymus Londiniensis, recently edited by Manetti (Reference Manetti2011) and Ricciardetto (Reference Ricciardetto2016).

7 See the status quaestionis in Rossitto (Reference Rossitto2005) 29–35.

8 References in Hambruch (Reference Hambruch1904) 4.

9 I shall make clear in due course that the versions included in the Marciana and the Laertiana also present some differences, although they share the main point.

10 For example, the closing lines of DA 64M announce a treatment of the concept of ‘prior’, and ‘prior and posterior’ are the subjects of DA 65 M. Likewise, DA 66 M begins by recalling DA 65. DA 67 M confirms this internal network as it is announced at the end of DA 66 M.

11 In Dorandi’s edition, this sentence does not begin a new paragraph. I explain in section III why I think it should; see especially n.42 below.

12 I translate the genitive of comparison with the more idiomatic ‘than …’ construction. A more literal, but less idiomatic, rendering would be ‘greater of something’, ‘faster of something’.

13 In this paper, I use the word ‘category’ in its ontological sense, i.e. as class or genus of being. Since the texts I shall examine distinguish between groups of ὄντα, I take this use of ‘category’ to be legitimate, even though the word κατηγορία is absent from both recensions and, as is well known, ‘class or genus of being’ was not the original philosophical meaning of the word κατηγορία.

14 Cf. Duncombe (Reference Duncombe2012) 78.

15 Cf. Fine (Reference Fine1993) 180. See also Berti (Reference Berti2004) 264–65, who, however, is more prudent than Fine, as he does not say that καθ’ ἑαυτά beings are Aristotelian substances and that πρός τι beings are non-substances. Rather, following Gercke (Reference Gercke1891) and von Fritz (Reference von Fritz1931), he claims that ‘dalla classe dei καθ’ αὑτά deriva la categoria [aristotelica] della sostanza (οὐσία) […] dalla classe dei πρός τι derivano, invece, tutte le altre categorie, cioè i cosiddetti “accidenti”’ (my emphasis). But see also the more general (and less prudent) remark at p. 376: ‘se infatti è vero che già in Accademia si distinguevano gli enti in καθ᾽ ἀὑτά e πρός τι, è anche vero che il senso di tale distinzione era analogo a quello della distinzione aristotelica fra la sostanza (ciò che è in sé) e gli accidenti (ciò che è in altro)’ (my emphasis). Nota bene: Fine and Berti focus on the Laertiana version of the division, but I take their interpretation to be disputable both for the Laertiana and the Marciana versions, as I shall argue later in this section.

16 It is beyond the scope of this paper to provide a detailed investigation of this alleged independent evidence from other Early Academic texts, but I am doubtful that any of them supports this Aristotelian-oriented interpretation. I shall discuss the texts Fine alludes to in section III, but only as far as the (putative) connection between the bicategorial distinction and the metaphysics of principles is concerned.

17 The phrase ἐν τῇ ἑρμηνϵίᾳ μηδϵνὸς at l. 1192 is the negative counterpart of the genitive τινος ϵ̔ρμηνϵίας at l. 1196. Thus, I take it that in T1 ἐν τῇ ἑρμηνϵίᾳ τινος is equivalent to τινος ϵ̔ρμηνϵίας and the phrase ‘to need something in the expression’ is equivalent to ‘to need some expression’.

18 Cf. for example, Montanari (Reference Montanari1984) and Zadro (Reference Zadro1999) 164–76.

19 Cf. LSJ, s.v.; Frisk (Reference Frisk1960) 563; Beekes (Reference Beekes2010) 462.

20 Cf. the references in LSJ s.v.

21 Matt Watton has suggested to me in private correspondence that at Tht. 209a5 Plato might be using ϵ̔ρμηνϵία in a technical fashion, when he writes that λόγος δέ γϵ ἧν ἡ τῆς σῆς διαφορότητος ϵ̔ρμηνϵία, a sentence which seems to provide a formal definition of λόγος in terms of ϵ̔ρμηνϵία of the differentiae. However, I still tend to resist the point. In that passage Socrates explores the last meaning of λόγος (the crucial component of the third definition of ἐπιστήμη), as what enables one to identify a given object and to distinguish it from all other things. The result is that a λόγος is ultimately an exposition or expression of those differences. But, crucially, he introduces his point at 208c7 by saying that this is ‘what the majority of people would say’ (ὅπϵρ ἂν οἱ πολλοὶ ϵἴποιϵν). So this can hardly be the introduction of a technical use of ϵ̔ρμηνϵία.

22 I prefer ‘expression’ to ‘explanation’ and ‘interpretation’, because the latter two suggest an asymmetrical relation (between the explanans and the explanandum), which I want to exclude.

23 Except when the comparative is used when the English (or other modern languages) requires the positive, cf. Smyth (Reference Smyth1920) 282 (§1083). Instead, the Greek use of the comparative to soften an expression (‘rather’, ‘somewhat’) is not an exception: as Smyth (Reference Smyth1920) 282 (§1082d) says, ‘here the quality is compared with its absence or its opposite’, which means that, albeit implicitly, a term of comparison is still present.

24 By this parenthetical remark I mean that if I say, ‘Paul is taller than John’, I of course do not mean that ‘John’ is the correlative of the comparative ‘taller’; ‘than John’ is the correct syntactic supplement of ‘taller’ as John is ‘shorter’ (correlative of ‘taller’) than Paul.

25 This reading was originally proposed, though not thoroughly argued, by Owen (Reference Owen and Nussbaum1957). An anonymous referee asks: where does a predicate such as ‘large’ fit into this scheme? It is semantically incomplete, I answer. But what exactly does this mean? It means that a thing is said to be ‘large’ only within the framework of a given context. Note that at Phd. 100e5 ‘large’ (τὰ μϵγάλα) is regarded as equivalent to ‘larger than’ (τὰ μϵίζω). The point is then that the expression καθ᾿ αὑτό here conveys the idea of ‘taking something in itself’, without any qualification or relation to something else (cf. Ademollo (Reference Ademollo, Chiaradonna and Galluzzo2013) 47–51 and El Murr (Reference El Murr, Doucet and Koch2014) on this); the expression πρὸς ἄλλα indicates the necessity of such a qualification. If I predicate ‘large’ of x, there is always a given context or reference system in which x is large, a view which of course is only reasonable. Sure, I can use ‘large’ without a complement, but given the semantic incompleteness of this predicate, an implicit qualification or reference to another item is, I submit, always in order. So, if I say, ‘Socrates is large’, the sentence is correct, but I am still presupposing some term of comparison.

26 I take this point from the fine analysis of Soph. 255c13–14 proposed by Leigh (Reference Leigh2012) 11–21.

27 In the Recensio Marciana this modal characterization is even clearer.

28 At least according to the standard interpretation of ‘being-said-of-a-subject’ and ‘being-in-a-subject’, which, however, has been recently questioned by Crivelli (Reference Crivelli2017).

29 Cf. Havrda (Reference Havrda2017) 254–55.

30 In DA 67 M the object of science is not explicitly specified, and it is only said that ἐπιστήμη is πρὸς ἄλλο τι. However, I think it fair to read behind ἄλλο τι the word ἐπιστητόν.

31 David Sedley makes the following objection: as Arist. Cat. 7 makes clear, there are cases in which a relative does not have a correlative, and that of ἐπιστήμη and ἐπιστητόν is one of them. I assume that, in raising this objection, Sedley refers to Cat. 7, 7b23–8a12. But I am doubtful that this is Aristotle’s point in that passage. Rather, he emphasizes there that ἐπιστήμη and ἐπιστητόν, and similar pairs of relatives (for example, αἴσθησις and αἰσθητόν), are not simultaneous, so ἐπιστητόν is only temporally prior to ἐπιστήμη not logically or ontologically.

32 Cf. Annas and Barnes (Reference Annas and Barnes1985) 130.

33 I shall not defend the exhaustivity of Annas and Barnes’ list, though it arguably captures the main ancient notions of relativity. For my present purposes, it suffices that it provide an effective explanatory framework for understanding the type(s) of relativity at work in T1 and T2.

34 A similar point is made about Sext. Emp. Math. 8.161–62 by Barnes (Reference Barnes1988–1990) 21–22.

35 I thank Matt Watton for pushing me to clarify my views on this point.

36 Cf. the perhaps overly bold, but essentially correct remarks in Annas (Reference Annas1974) 266–67: ‘the difference between καθ᾽ αὑτά and πρός τι items […] becomes developed into something like an “Academy theory of categories”. As with Aristotle’s categories, the distinction in question is one to which linguistic differences are relevant, but it is in no way about words or coextensive with any linguistic distinction. It is a distinction that can only be made by means of general facts about words, but what are distinguished are items that words signify’.

37 I only mention, as a complement to my analysis of T2, that the translatio Araba of Ibn al-̣ayyib, one of only three translations constituting the Eastern tradition of the DA, basically conveys the same philosophical content as T1, but with some interesting variations, which, as noted by Dorandi and Marjiani (Reference Dorandi and Marjiani2017), are likely due to different phases of rewriting, revision and manipulation. The text, T3, is the following:

Further, beings can also be divided in another way, as follows: there are those subsisting per se and those said by analogy. Per se beings are those which to understand the intellect needs nothing else, for example human being, bull, and the rest of the animals. Those said by analogy are those understood in relation to another thing different from them, for example ‘big’, ‘small’ and similar. For ‘big’ is said by analogy to ‘small’ and ‘small’ by analogy to ‘big’. So beings are divided according to these two classes. End.

I will confine myself to pausing on some differences from and similarities with T1 and T2. First, if T1 insists more on the strictly linguistic aspect of the division, and T2 stresses more the ontological one, T3 addresses the logical side, by focusing on the notion of ‘intellect’, but always with reference to ‘beings’. Second, T3 uses the concept of ‘analogy’, and not of ἑρμηνϵία, to describe the status of relative beings. I suggest interpreting this word too in a non-technical fashion, and understand it to be very similar in meaning to ‘relation’ or the French rapport and the Italian rapporto. It seems to me that the notion of ‘analogy’ is the logical counterpart of the linguistic notion of ἑρμηνϵία. Third, just like T1 and T2, so too T3 proposes that the relation between a predicate by analogy and that of which this predicate is said by analogy to, is a symmetrical one. My thanks to Celia Byrne for assistance with translating this passage.

38 Krämer (Reference Krämer1959) 292–93 and Berti (Reference Berti2012) 141 are two proponents of this interpretation.

39 First general overviews of the categorial schemes in the Early Academy are provided by Krämer (Reference Krämer1971) 75–107, Isnardi Parente (Reference Isnardi Parente1979) 73–81, 123–32, Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld1992b) 59–61 and Fine (Reference Fine1993) 171–82. Bastianini and Sedley (Reference Bastianini and Sedley1995) 552 claim that the bicategorial scheme was the dominant categorial doctrine from Xenocrates to the first century AD.

40 To this list one can add also Sext. Emp. Math. X 263–73, assuming that the ‘Pythagoreans’ in this passage refer to the members of the Early Academy, as suggested by Burkert (Reference Burkert1972) 54–56. But Sextus’ Pythagoreans propose a division into three (and not two) categories. So, this passage would require a separate discussion, cf. Isnardi Parente (Reference Isnardi Parente1992) for an initial exploration.

41 And this is also why these texts have been included in Gaiser’s, Krämer’s and Isnardi Parente’s collections of Testimonia platonica; cf. Gaiser (Reference Gaiser1963), Krämer (Reference Krämer1982) and Isnardi Parente (Reference Isnardi Parente1998).

42 For this very reason, I believe that both the introductory and the concluding clauses of Diogenes’ corpus of divisions should constitute independent paragraphs and not be printed in continuity with the first and the last diuisio respectively; cf. above n.11.

43 Apart from being more faithful to the text, this exegesis has at least one other advantage. Since there is no mention whatsoever, not even implicit or indirect, of metaphysical principles in T2, a deflationary reading would preserve a stronger doctrinal continuity between the (only) two versions of the same division that have come down to us. Certainly this is not decisive, but I do think it contributes to a cumulative case.

44 An interpretation akin to mine seems implicitly suggested by Luc Brisson, in his French translation of the passage (cf. Goulet-Cazé (Reference Goulet-Cazé1999) ad loc.), in which he clearly takes τὰ πρῶτα to refer not to metaphysical principles but to the whole corpus of divisions presented by Diogenes: ‘Voilà donc les premières divisions qu’effectuait Platon, si l’on en croit Aristote’. Despite the similarity between our understanding of the passage, I find the translation ‘les premières divisions’ problematic. For τὰ πρῶτα is a neuter plural, whereas ‘divisions’ can only render an implicit (feminine) διαιρήσϵις. It might be replied that ‘les premières divisions qu’effectuait’ is a rather free translation somehow importing into τὰ πρῶτα the meaning of the verb διῄρϵι. But it remains true that a translation of this sort is potentially misleading, as shown by the fact that if one were to produce a reverse translation from French to ancient Greek, one would not get to Diogenes’ text.

45 Tr. Chase (Reference Chase2003), slightly modified.

46 Cf. Isnardi Parente (Reference Isnardi Parente and Dorandi2012) 254–56 and Granieri (Reference Granieri2021) for a more detailed analysis of this fragment.

47 Cf. Isnardi Parente (Reference Isnardi Parente1979) 75–81. See also Berti (Reference Berti2004) 246.

48 Cf. Berti (Reference Berti1962) 279.

49 Cf. Isnardi Parente (Reference Isnardi Parente1982) 439–44 and Granieri (Reference Granieriforthcoming).

50 Tr. Mueller in Baltussen et al. (Reference Baltussen, Atkinson, Share and Mueller2012) 132.

References

Ademollo, F. (2013) ‘Plato’s conception of the forms: some remarks’, in Chiaradonna, R. and Galluzzo, G. (eds), Universals in Ancient Philosophy (Pisa) 4186 Google Scholar
Annas, J. (1974) ‘Forms and first principles’, Phronesis 3, 257–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. and Barnes, J. (1985) The Modes of Scepticism: Ancient Texts and Modern Interpretations (Cambridge)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltussen, H., Atkinson, M., Share, M. and Mueller, I. (2012) Simplicius: On Aristotle Physics 1.5–9 (London)Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1988–1990) ‘Scepticism and relativity’, Philosophical Studies 32, 131 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bastianini, G. and Sedley, D. (1995) ‘Commentarium in Platonis “Theaetetum”’, in Corpus dei papiri filosofici greci e latini, Parte III: Commentari (Florence) 227562 Google Scholar
Beekes, R. (2010) Etymological Dictionary of Greek. 1. (Leiden and Boston)Google Scholar
Berti, E. (1962) La filosofia del primo Aristotele (Padua)Google Scholar
Berti, E. (2004) Aristotele. Dalla dialettica alla filosofia prima (Milan) 1st edition Padua 1977Google Scholar
Berti, E. (2005) ‘Presentazione’, in Rossitto, C., Aristotele ed altri: Divisioni (Milan) 526 Google Scholar
Berti, E. (2012) Sumphilosophein. La vita nell’Accademia di Platone (Rome and Bari)Google Scholar
Brock, S.P. (2014) ‘An abbreviated Syriac version of Ps.-Aristotle, De virtutibus et vitiis and Divisiones ’, in Coda, E. and Martini Bonadeo, C. (eds), De l’Antiquité tardive au Moyen Âge: études de logique aristotélicienne et de philosophie grecque, syriaque, arabe et latine offertes à Henri Hugonnard-Roche (Paris) 94101 Google Scholar
Burkert, W. (1972) Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (Oxford)Google Scholar
Chase, M. (2003) Simplicius: On Aristotle’s Categories 1–4 (Ithaca)Google Scholar
Crivelli, P. (2017) ‘Being-said-of in Aristotle’s Categories ’, RFN 3, 531–56Google Scholar
Dorandi, T. (1997) ‘Ricerche sulla trasmissione delle Divisioni aristoteliche’, in Algra, K.A., van der Horst, P.W. and Runia, D.T. (eds), Polyhistor: Studies in the History of Historiography of Ancient Philosophy (Leiden) 145–65Google Scholar
Dorandi, T. (2013) Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers (Cambridge)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorandi, T. (2016a) ‘Le Divisiones quae vulgo dicuntur Aristoteleae. Storia del testo e edizione delle Recensiones Marciana, Florentina e Leidensis ’, Studia Graeco-Arabica 6, 158 Google Scholar
Dorandi, T. (2016b) ‘Elementi “diairetici” nella sezione iniziale dell’Anonymus Londiniensis (PBrLibr inv. 137 I-IV 17)’, in Casanova, A., Messeri, G. and Pintaudi, R. (eds), E sì d’amici pieno: Omaggio di studiosi italiani a G. Bastianini per il suo settantesimo compleanno (Florence) 199205 Google Scholar
Dorandi, T. and Marjiani, I. (2017) ‘La tradizione siriaca e araba delle cosiddette Divisiones Aristoteleae. Analisi e commento della versione siriaca (ed. Brock) e delle due traduzioni arabe (ed. Kellermann-Rost)’, Studia Graeco-Arabica 7, 155 Google Scholar
Duncombe, M. (2012) ‘Plato’s absolute and relative categories at Sophist 255c14’, AncPhil 32, 7386 Google Scholar
El Murr, D. (2014) ‘Aὐτὸ καθ’ αὑτό: la genèse et le sens d’un philosophème platonicien’, in Doucet, D. and Koch, I. (eds), Autos, idipsum: aspects de l’identité d’Homère à Augustin (Aix-en-Provence) 3956 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, G. (1993) On Ideas (Oxford)Google Scholar
Frisk, H. (1960) Griechisches Etymologisches Wörterbuch 1 (Heidelberg)Google Scholar
Gaiser, K. (1963) Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre (Stuttgart)Google Scholar
Gercke, A. (1891) ‘Ursprung der aristotelischen Kategorien’, AGPh 4, 224–41Google Scholar
Gigon, O. (1987) Aristotelis Opera III (Berlin and New York)Google Scholar
Goulet-Cazé, M.O. (1999) Diogène Laërce. Vies et doctrines des philosophes illustres (Paris)Google Scholar
Granieri, R. (2021) ‘Xenocrates and the two-category scheme’, Apeiron 54, 261–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Granieri, R. (forthcoming) ‘Hermodorus of Syracuse and Sextus Empiricus’ “Pythagoreans” on Categories and Principles’, CQ Google Scholar
Hambruch, E. (1904) Logische Regeln der Platonischen Schule in der Aristotelischen Topik (Berlin)Google Scholar
Havrda, M. (2017) The So-Called Eighth Stromateus by Clement of Alexandria: Early Christian Reception of Greek Scientific Methodology (Leiden and Boston)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. (1979) Studi sull’Accademia platonica antica (Florence)Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. (1982) Senocrate-Ermodoro: Frammenti (Naples)Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. (1992) ‘Sesto, Platone, l’Accademia antica e i Pitagorici’, Elenchos 13, 119–67Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. (1998) ‘ Testimonia Platonica: per una raccolta delle principali testimonianze sui λϵγόμϵνα ἄγραφα δόγματα di Platone: Testimonianze di età ellenistica e di età imperiale’, RAL Supplement 9.10, fasc. 1, 395, 1120 Google Scholar
Isnardi Parente, M. (2012) Senocrate e Ermodoro: Testimonianze e frammenti (ed. by Dorandi, T.) (Pisa)Google Scholar
Kellermann-Rost, M. (1965) Ein pseudoaristotelischer Traktat über die Tugend: Edition und Übersetzung der arabischen Fassungen des Abū Qurra und des Ibn aṬ-Ṭayyib (Ph.D. Diss. Erlangen)Google Scholar
Krämer, H. (1959) Arete bei Platon und Aristoteles (Heidelberg)Google Scholar
Krämer, H. (1971) Platonismus und Hellenistische Philosophie (Berlin and New York)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krämer, H. (1982) Platone e i fondamenti della metafisica (Milan)Google Scholar
Leigh, F. (2012) ‘Modes of being at Sophist 255c–e’, Phronesis 57, 128 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manetti, D. (2011) Anonymus Londiniensis: De medicina (Leipzig)Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1992a) ‘ Physikai doxai e Problemata physica da Aristotele ad Aezio (ed oltre)’, in Battegazzore, A.M. (ed.), Dimostrazione, argomentazione dialettica e argomentazione retorica nel pensiero antico (Genova) 311–82 (repr. with additions in J. Mansfeld and D.T. Runia (2010) Aëtiana: The Method and Intellectual Context of a Doxographer 3 (Leiden and Boston) 33–98)Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1992b) Heresiography in Context: Hippolytus’ Elenchos as a Source for Greek Philosophy (Leiden)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montanari, E. (1984) La sezione linguistica del Peri hermeneias di Aristotele (Florence)Google Scholar
Mutschmann, H. (1906) Divisiones quae vulgo dicuntur Aristoteleae (Leipzig)Google Scholar
Owen, G.E.L. (1957) ‘A proof in the Peri Ideôn ’, JHS 77, 103–11 (repr. in G.E.L. Owen (1986) Logic, Science and Metaphysics (ed. by Nussbaum, M.) (Ithaca) 165–78)Google Scholar
Pasquali, G. (1910) ‘Doxographica aus Basiliusscholien’, Nachrichten der Akademie der Wissenschaften in Göttingen, phil.-hist. Kl., 194228 (repr. in G. Pasquali (1986) Scritti filologici. I. Letteratura greca (ed. by F. Bornmann, G. Pascucci and S. Timpanaro) (Florence) 539–74)Google Scholar
Ricciardetto, A. (2016) L’Anonyme de Londres (P. Lit. Lond. 165, Brit. Libr. Inv. 137). Édition et traduction d’un papyrus grec médical du Ier siècle après J.-C. (Paris)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rossitto, C. (2005) Aristotele ed altri: Divisioni (Milan) (1st edition Padua 1984)Google Scholar
Smyth, H.W. (1920) Greek Grammar for Colleges (New York)Google Scholar
von Fritz, K. (1931) ‘Der Ursprung der aristotelischen Kategorienlehre’, AGPh 40, 449–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zadro, A. (1999) Aristotele: De interpretatione (Naples)Google Scholar