Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-lvwk9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-01T17:13:52.534Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

(E.D.) KARAKANTZA Who Am I? (Mis)identity and the Polis in Oedipus Tyrannus. Washington DC: Centre for Hellenic Studies and Harvard University Press, 2020. Pp. xii + 178. £17.95. 9780674237940.

Review products

(E.D.) KARAKANTZA Who Am I? (Mis)identity and the Polis in Oedipus Tyrannus. Washington DC: Centre for Hellenic Studies and Harvard University Press, 2020. Pp. xii + 178. £17.95. 9780674237940.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 April 2023

Richard Seaford*
Affiliation:
University of Exeter
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews of Books: Literature
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

How is it possible to say something new and substantial about Sophocles’ Oedipus Tyrannus? Efimia Karakantza makes her bold choice explicit: ‘No matter how important all the other issues are, it is the omnipresent question of identity that dominates the entire Sophoclean tragedy’ (43). She brings out the complexity of Oedipus’ self-discovery by skilfully combining elements from a range of thinkers that includes Cornelius Castoriadis (on the polis), Claude Lévi-Strauss (on lameness), Michel Foucault (on power-knowledge), Charles Taylor (on the self) and Jean-Pierre Vernant (on the will).

From Lévi-Strauss Karakantza takes the lameness implicit in the names of the successive kings Labdacus, Laius and Oedipus. Oedipus’ deformity, caused by Laius yoking together the baby’s feet, both integrates him into the family tree and marks him as an outcast. Reminded of it, Oedipus calls it an ‘ancient’ (ἀρχαῖος, 1033) evil, to which Karakantza compares Deianeira’s reference to the centaur Nessus as ἀρχαῖος (Trachiniai 555): in both instances the word marks the re-emergence of primitive violence into a life from its remote past. Imention this to exemplify the sensitivity of Karakantza’s comments on the text, which often supplement P.J. Finglass’ commentary (Cambridge 2018). She also connects the episode to her fundamental theme, the relationship of individual identity to the polis, by interpreting Laius’ mutilation of his baby son as a perversion of the ceremony of naming: Oedipus is never admitted into his father’s oikos, ‘crippling any later capacity for acting properly as a citizen’ (50).

For Castoriadis, in creating democracy the Athenian polis reimagined itself as autonomous in the sense of being subject only to the laws that it had itself passed. Accordingly, explains Karakantza, ‘the perception of oneself as an Athenian involved the imaginary signification of a citizen attached to his polis’ (20) and subject to its laws, rather than as, for example, a client attached to his individual lord. The identity of Oedipus (and of some other Sophoclean individuals), be it ὑψίπολις or ἄπολις (Antigone 370), can be understood only in this historical context of accountability to the polis. The self is historically constructed, and the ancient Greek self is ‘essentially public’ (26). This requires Karakantza to demolish Bernard Knox’s influential exaggeration of the self-sufficiency of the Sophoclean ‘hero’ (‘to the hero himself the opinion of others is irrelevant’: The Heroic Temper: Studies in Sophoclean Tragedy (Berkeley 1964), 31). In this she succeeds, not least by pointing out how relevant the opinion of others is even to the suicidal Ajax.

Another influential reading of Athenian tragedy to which Karakantza opposes her Castoriadean perspective is Vernant’s essay ‘Intimations of the will in Greek tragedy’ (in J.-P. Vernant and P. Vidal-Naquet (eds), Myth and Tragedy in Ancient Greece (New York 1988), 49–84). Who is the source of Oedipus’ actions, the gods or Oedipus himself? If it is the gods, then how can Oedipus be guilty? To these obvious and famous questions there are various kinds of answers. One is to remove the incompatibility between divine control and human autonomy by integrating them into a whole, by, for instance, adopting David Kovacs’ analogy of a chess game between an ordinary player (Oedipus) and a grandmaster (Apollo): Oedipus acts autonomously (and reasonably) but must lose (‘The Role of Apollo in Oedipus Tyrannus’, in J.C.R. Cousland and J. Hume (eds), The Play of Texts and Fragments: Essays in Honour of Martin Cropp (Leiden 2009), 357–68, analogy at 359–60). Another is to retain the incompatibility but explain it historically (Vernant): tragedy inherits the traditional idea of the gods imposing madness, transgression and pollution on successive generations of a family and combines it with the new idea of the accountability of the free individual agent to the laws of the polis. But this new commitment of the individual to his actions is, says Vernant, ‘still limited, indecisive, and vaguely defined’ (82): tragedy expresses the ‘internal inadequacy of the agent’ (83) by retaining overall control by the gods.

Karakantza’s own answer is also historical, but she rejects the idea of transition: ‘when we come to classical Athens and the tragic genre, we can understand the co-existence of the divine and the human, not as an incomplete transition, but as a new “creation” in the sense that Castoriades defines it’ (142–43). From this perspective, she claims to see in the Oedipus ‘no fatalistic or divinely bound action’, but rather ‘the transcendent ability of mortals to rise in stature above all external constraints’ (145); in other words, she sees the opposite of the ‘weakness inherent in action’ (83) ascribed to tragedy by Vernant.

The appeal of this view, one-sided though it may seem, is that the drama does indeed provide a unified, compelling vision, not a juxtaposition of historically successive outlooks. But in what does the unity consist? Here Idiffer from Karakantza (and from Kovacs and Vernant), but that is because her book has helped me to expand my thinking on this issue. Ishare her view of Ajax 394, σκότος, ἐμὸν φάος (‘darkness, my light’), as ‘one of the most beautiful lines of poetry ever written’ (6). For Sophocles the unity of opposites is, as for Heraclitus, a pervasive conception, through which he perceives and shapes what others call a historical transition: the action of Oedipus is simply both autonomous and pre-determined by the gods.