Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T14:13:03.328Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Doing No Wrong: Law, Liberty, and the Constraint of Kings

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 January 2014

Extract

The challenge Charles I prepared to fling at his accusers on 22 January 1649 has conditioned the thinking of generations of historians. “No earthly power can justly call me, who am your king, in question as a delinquent,” he proclaimed. He reminded those who presumed to judge him that they had been “born his subjects and born subjects to those laws, which determined, ‘that the king can do no wrong,’” a maxim that “guards every English monarch, even the least deserving.” Indeed, there was no established legal process that could hold Charles personally accountable for his actions, even if, as charged, he meant to overthrow the rights and liberties of his people. The tenet the king can do no wrong shifted responsibility onto those who carried out royal orders. Proponents of royal supremacy had seen in that maxim proof that kings were not only legally unaccountable but actually above the law.

However, an equally venerable English maxim explained that although “the king was under no man, he was under God and the law; for the law maketh the king.” To modern historians the two maxims seem contradictory. And the dramatic failure of the law in Charles's case has induced scholars to doubt the efficacy of this second maxim, to accept Charles's interpretation of its counterpart—that the king could do no wrong—and to shrug off as fine-sounding but unrealistic the strategies early modern Englishmen relied on to control kings. Both maxims, the one Charles sheltered under and the one he rejected, were designed to control his behavior.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © North American Conference of British Studies 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Kenyon, John, The Stuart Constitution, 2d ed. (Cambridge, 1986), p. 292Google Scholar; Hume, David, The History of England: From the Invasion of Julius Caesar to the Abdication of James the Second, 1688, rev. ed., 6 vols. (New York, 1880), 5:373Google Scholar.

2 SirCoke, Edward, The Reports of Sir Edward Coke (hereafter cited as Reports), 6 vols. (London, 1826), 6:6365Google Scholar. According to Clayton Roberts the maxim the king can do no wrong, rarely, if ever, heard in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, appeared in modern guise in the fifteenth century. See Roberts, Clayton, Growth of Responsible Government (Cambridge, 1966), p. 4Google Scholar. The statement that the king was under God and the law was usually cited from Bracton. For a history of the growing respect for and reliance on Bracton, see Yale, David E. C., “Of No Mean Authority: Some Later Uses of Bracton,” in On the Laws and Customs of England: Essays in Honor of Samuel E. Thome, ed. Arnold, Morris S., Green, Thomas A., et al. (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1981), pp. 383–96Google Scholar.

3 One exception is David Ogg, who provides a thoughtful, if brief, assessment of the place of the maxim in early modern English constitutional history. See Ogg, David, England in the Reign of Charles II, 2d ed. (Oxford, 1967), pp. 452–54Google Scholar.

4 Roberts, , Growth of Responsible Government, p. 4Google Scholar.

5 Greenberg, Janelle, “Our Grand Maxim of State, ‘The King Can Do No Wrong,’History of Political Thought 2, no. 12 (1991): 216Google Scholar.

6 Ibid., p. 217.

7 Ibid., pp. 227–28.

8 Burnet, Gilbert, An Enquiry into the Present State of Affairs (London, 1689), p. 11Google Scholar. A somewhat different slant on the meaning was given in 1642 by the parliamentarian, Charles Herle, who saw the king intrinsically bound with Parliament and unable to do no wrong because together they made law. [Herle, Charles], A Fuller Answer to a Treatise Written by Doctor Feme, Entitled the Resolving of Conscience upon This Question, 2d ed. (London, 1642), p. 16Google Scholar.

9 SirL'Estrange, Roger, A Plea for a Limited Monarchy, as It Was Established in This Nation before the Late War; in a Humble Address to … General Monk (London, 1660), p. 8Google Scholar.

10 [Holles, Denzil], Some Considerations upon the Question Whether the Parliament Is Dissolved by Its Prorogation for 15 Months? (London, 1676), p. 5Google Scholar.

11 L'Estrange, , Plea for Limited Monarchy, p. 7Google Scholar.

12 SirHale, Matthew, “Reflections by the Lord Chiefe Justice Hale on Mr. Hobbes His Dialogue of the Laws,” reprinted in SirHoldsworth, William, A History of English Law, 2d ed., 12 vols. (London, 1938), 5:508Google Scholar.

13 A Complete Collection of State-Trials, and Proceedings upon High-Treason, and Other Crimes and Misdemeanours, 5 vols. (London, 1730), 5:154, 159Google Scholar.

14 Ibid., p. 152.

15 Johnson, Robert C. and Cole, Maija Jansson, eds., Commons Debates: 1628, vol. 2 (New Haven, Conn., 1977), p. 336Google Scholar. Also see 25 Edw. III, 4 stat. 5, “None shall be outed of his Franchises or Free-hold, but by the way of Law: and if anything be done against the same, it shall be redressed, and holden for none”; 42 Edw. III, cap. 3, “None shall be put to answer an accusation to the King without presentment, or some matter of Record; and what is done otherwise shall be void, and holden for errour.” Wingate, Edmund, An Exact Abridgment of All Statutes in Force and Use, from the Beginning of Magna Charta, until 1641 (London, 1684), pp. 3, 4Google Scholar.

16 For this and the following comment, see Johnson, and Cole, , eds., Commons Debates, 2:358Google Scholar.

17 Cited by Sommerville, J. P., Politics and Ideology in England, 1603–1640 (London, 1986), p. 101Google Scholar.

18 SirFinch, Henry, trans., Law, or, a Discourse Thereof, in Foure Books (London, 1627), bk. 2, p. 85Google Scholar.

19 Cited by Judson, Margaret, The Crisis of the Constitution: An Essay in Constitutional and Political Thought in England, 1603–1645 (New Brunswick, N.J., 1949), p. 37Google Scholar.

20 Cited by McIlwain, Charles H., Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern, rev. ed. (Ithaca, N.Y., 1958), p. 125Google Scholar.

21 See Judson, , Crisis of the Constitution, p. 38Google Scholar.

22 See Gardiner, S. R., ed., The Constitutional Documents of the Puritan Revolution, 1625–1660, 3d ed. rev. (Oxford, 1906), p. 122Google Scholar.

23 Anthony Brown, J. in Willion v. Berkeley (1563)Google Scholar; Elton, Geoffrey, ed., The Tudor Constitution: Documents and Commentary, 2d ed. (Cambridge, 1982), p. 17Google Scholar.

24 Hooker, Richard, Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity, in The Works of That Learned and Judicious Divine, Mr. Richard Hooker: With an Account of His Life and Death by Isaac Walton, ed. Rev. Keble, John, 3d ed., 3 vols. (Oxford, 1845), vol. 3, Hooker's bk. 8, cap. 2, p. 13Google Scholar; Elton, , ed., Tudor Constitution, p. 17Google Scholar.

25 Kern, Fritz, Kingship and Law in the Middle Ages, trans. Chrimes, S.B. (1956; reprint, New York, 1970), p. 87Google Scholar.

26 Ibid., pp. 91–92.

27 Weston, Corinne C., “England: Ancient Constitution and Common Law,” in The Cambridge History of Political Thought: 1450–1700, ed. Burns, J. H. and Goldie, Mark (Cambridge, 1991), p. 386Google Scholar.

28 See the discussion below on the coronation oath devised for William and Mary in 1689.

29 Magna Carta was considered a confirmation of ancient rights and customs, particularly those known as the laws of Edward the Confessor. See Greenberg, Janelle, “The Confessor's Laws and the Radical Face of the Ancient Constitution,” English Historical Review 104 (July, 1989):614Google Scholar.

30 Magna Carta, 1215, in Holt, James C., Magna Carta and the Idea of Liberty (New York, 1972), p. 183Google Scholar.

31 Tomlins, T. E.et al., eds., Statutes of the Realm [to 1713], 11 vols. (London, 18101828), 1:6Google Scholar. The quotation is from Pollock, Frederick and Maitland, Frederic William, The History of English Law before the Time of Edward I, 2d ed., 2 vols. (1898; reprint, Cambridge, 1968), 1:179Google Scholar.

32 Holdsworth, , History of English Law, 2d ed., 9:8Google Scholar. Holdsworth also points out that while ordinary writs did not lie against the king in his court, he was “morally bound to do the same justice to his subjects as they could be compelled to do to one another” (9:10).

33 25 Edw. I, cap. 2.

34 18 Edw. III, cap. 7. And see [Jenkins, David], The Kings Prerogative and the Subjects Priviledges Asserted according to Law and Reason (London, 1645; reprint, 1680), p. 8Google Scholar. Medieval judges were still very much the king's servants, according to Turner, Ralph V., Judges, Administrators and the Common Law in Angevin England (Rio Grande, Ohio, 1994), p. 113Google Scholar.

35 Touching the Fundamental Laws (London, 1643), p. 11Google Scholar.

36 SirVane, Henry, The Tryal of Sir Henry Vane, Kt (London, 1662), p. 10Google Scholar.

37 Holdsworth, William, History of English Law, 4th ed., 11 vols. (London, 1936), 2:196Google Scholar.

38 Anson, William, The Law and Custom of the Constitution, 2 vols. (Oxford, 1892), 1:15Google Scholar.

39 Jolliffe, J. E. A., The Constitutional History of Medieval England: From the English Settlement to 1485, 4th ed. (London, 1961), p. 393Google Scholar.

40 Anson, , Law and Custom, 2:41Google Scholar. The Thirty Articles of 1410 required the king to govern by advice of a permanent council.

41 Schwoerer, Lois, “The Attempted Impeachment of Sir William Scroggs, Lord Chief Justice of the Court of King's Bench, November 1680–March 1681,” Historical Journal 39, no. 4 (1995): 848–49Google Scholar. Ogg makes a similar point. Ogg, , Charles II, p. 453Google Scholar.

42 See Davis, R. H. C., A History of Medieval Europe: From Constantine to Saint Louis (London, 1957), p. 244Google Scholar; Skinner, , Foundations of Modern Political Thought, 2:144–45Google Scholar.

43 Kern, , Kingship and Law, p. 89Google Scholar. This concept can be traced back to the New Testament, 2 Cor. 13:10.

44 See Davis, , A History of Medieval Europe, p. 244Google Scholar, and Skinner, , Foundations of Modern Political Thought, pp. 144–45Google Scholar.

45 Nenner, Howard, “The Later Stuart Age,” in The Varieties of British Political Thought, 1500–1800, ed. Pocock, J. G. A., Schochet, Gordon J., and Schwoerer, Lois G. (Cambridge, 1993), p. 205Google Scholar.

46 Ibid. Nenner concludes, “As the divinely appointed guarantor of the faith, the church was effectively denying that God's truth was alterable by the king alone or even by the king-in-parliament.” And see Goldie, Mark, “The Political Thought of the Anglican Revolution,” in The Revolutions of 1688: The Andrew Browning Lectures, 1988, ed. Beddard, Robert (Oxford, 1991), p. 107Google Scholar.

47 A Homily on Obedience,” from Certain Sermons or Homilies … (London, 1547), in Elton, , ed., Tudor Constitution, p. 15Google Scholar.

48 See Nenner, , “The Later Stuart Age,” p. 205Google Scholar; Goldie, , “Political Thought,” pp. 114, 116Google Scholar.

49 Touching the Fundamental Laws, pp. 6–7.

50 [Masters, Samuel], The Case of Allegiance in Our Present Circumstances Considered: In a Letter from a Minister in the City, to a Minister in the Country (London, 1689), p. 12Google Scholar.

51 Ibid., p. 14.

52 Hunton, Philip, A Treatise of Monarchy (London, 1643)Google Scholar, reprinted in Divine Right and Democracy, ed. Wootton, David (London, 1986), p. 195Google Scholar.

53 Ogg, , Charles II, p. 453Google Scholar.

54 Ibid.

55 Darcy v. Allein, Trin. 44 Eliz., in Coke, Reports, pt. 11, 87e. And see Sacks, David Harris, “The Paradox of Taxation: Fiscal Crises, Parliament and Liberty in England, 1450–1640,” in Fiscal Crises, Liberty, and Representative Government, 1450–1789, ed. Hoffman, Philip T. and Norberg, Kathryn (Stanford, Calif., 1994), pp. 6163Google Scholar.

56 Davenant and Hurdis, Trin. 41 Eliz. rot. 92, in Coke, , Reports, pt. 11, 86bGoogle Scholar.

57 For differing opinions on this point, see Johann P. Sommerville, “James I and the Divine Right of Kings: English Politics and Continental Theory,” who argues that there was no place in James's “political outlook for the idea of an ancient constitution underlying the rights of both sovereign and subject,” while Paul Christianson, “Royal and Parliamentary Voices on the Ancient Constitution, c. 1604–1621,” believes James meant to create “a model of ‘constitutional monarchy created by Kings’ in which monarchs limited their own powers by creating laws and the institutions of governance.” Both articles are found in Peck, Linda Levy, ed., The Mental World of the Jacobean Court (Cambridge, 1991), pp. 65, 72Google Scholar.

58 Cited by Lockyer, , The Early Stuarts, p. 52Google Scholar.

59 Ibid., p. 57. Coke, though on his knees, continued to insist that what the king asked was against his judicial oath.

60 Johnson, and Cole, , eds., Commons Debates, 19 April 1628, 5:287Google Scholar.

61 Ibid., 19 April 1628, p. 280. For proponents of the theory that subjects must obey even illegal orders, see, e.g., Cust, Richard, The Forced Loan, 1626–1628 (Oxford, 1987), pp. 6267Google Scholar.

62 Johnson, and Cole, , eds., Commons Debates, 11 June 1628, 4:276Google Scholar.

63 Johnson, Robert C. and Cole, Maija Jansson, eds., Lords Debates, 19 April 1628, 5:291Google Scholar.

64 Johnson, Robert C. and Cole, Maija Jansson, eds., Proceedings in Parliament, 17 June 1628, 6:55Google Scholar.

65 Johnson, and Cole, , eds., Commons Debates, 20 June 1628, 4:393Google Scholar.

66 Ibid.

67 Ibid.

68 Ibid., 21 June 1628, p. 406.

69 Gardiner, , ed., Constitutional Documents, pp. 7073Google Scholar.

70 Nenner, , “The Later Stuart Age,” p. 196Google Scholar.

71 12 Car. 2, cap. 30.

72 Cobbett, William and Howell, T. B., eds., A Complete Collection of State Trials and Proceedings for High Treason and Other Crimes and Misdemeanors from the Earliest Period to the Year 1783, 21 vols. (London, 1816), 5:1184Google Scholar.

73 Journals of the House of Commons, 1547–1714, 17 vols. (London, 1742), 9:252Google Scholar.

74 Hutton, Ronald, Charles II: King of England, Scotland, and Ireland (Oxford, 1989), pp. 297–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 Cust, , Forced Loan, p. 154Google Scholar. See Cust on opposition to the benevolences of 1614 and 1622 and the forced loan.

76 Ibid., p. 156.

77 Ibid., pp. 161–62.

78 Ibid., p. 162.

79 Sommerville, , Politics and Ideology, p. 42Google Scholar.

80 Sharpe, Kevin, The Personal Rule of Charles I (New Haven, Conn., 1992), pp. 1920Google Scholar. And see Cust, , Forced Loan, pp. 165–70Google Scholar. Coryton's comment is cited by Sharpe, , Personal Rule, p. 20Google Scholar.

81 Protestation of 2 March 1628/9 in Gardiner, , ed., Constitutional Documents, pp. 8283Google Scholar.

82 Rather than refuse, a group of Northamptonshire freeholders petitioned quarter sessions to dissuade the privy council from proceeding with the levy. Sharpe, , Personal Rule, p. 718Google Scholar.

83 Edward, Earl of Clarendon, The History of the Rebellion and Civil Wars in England, ed. Macray, W. Dunn, 6 vols. (Oxford, 1888), 1:150Google Scholar.

84 Burgess, Glenn, The Politics of the Ancient Constitution: An Introduction to English Political Thought, 1603–1642 (London, 1992), pp. 210–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Also see pp. 205, 209.

85 Ibid., p. 205.

86 Sommerville, , Politics and Ideology, pp. 101–2Google Scholar.

87 Henry Ball to Williamson, 18 July 1673, quoted in Ogg, , Charles II, p. 505Google Scholar. Ogg includes the text of the oath.

88 Ibid.

89 Jones, J. R., The Revolution of 1688 in England (London, 1972), pp. 6773Google Scholar.

90 Goldie, Mark, “Political Thought,” p. 120Google Scholar.

91 Costin, W. C. and Watson, J. Steven, The Law and Working of the Constitution, 2 vols. (London, 1952), 1:258–71Google Scholar.

92 Ibid., p. 265.

93 Ibid., p. 268.

94 The resolution was passed 1 February 1688/89. See The Tryal of Dr. Henry Sacheverell, before the House of Peers, for High Crimes and Misdemeanors; Upon an Impeachment (London, 1710), p. 28Google Scholar.

95 As doubts increased about the legality of Charles I's policies, many of his subjects pondered what their response should be to illegal royal orders. The Temple family of Stowe left the following analysis: “As the law has set the King's person and private actions above the censure and reach of any but God Almighty so has it excellently provided that none of his public acts in his public capacity are valid but what are legal and the execution thereof (is) committed to those who are sworn neither to counsel nor act but according to law and are answerable for the same if they do otherwise.” Cited in Sharpe, , Personal Rule, p. 716Google Scholar.

96 Kenyon, John P., Revolution Principles: The Politics of Party, 1689–1720 (Cambridge, 1977), p. 201CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

97 See Lockyer, , Early Stuarts, p. 49Google Scholar.

98 Grand Remonstrance, clause 38. Coke was dismissed in 1616.

99 Whether judges bent before that rod or not, Lois Schwoerer points out that the very nature of such judicial tenure opened the judges to charges of royal influence. Schwoerer, , “Attempted Impeachment,” pp. 848–49Google Scholar.

100 Carter, Jennifer, “Law, Courts and Constitution,” in The Restored Monarchy: 1660–1688, ed. Jones, J. R. (Totowa, N.J., 1979), p. 87Google Scholar.

101 Gardiner, S. R., A History of England, 1628–1637, 2 vols. (London, 1877), 1:153Google Scholar.

102 Jones, W. J., Politics and the Bench: The Judges and the Origins of the English Civil War (London, 1971), p. 89Google Scholar.

103 See “Quo Warranto: To the Charters of the City of London, 1681–1683,” “The Case of Benjamin Harris, Guildhall, London,” “Godden v. Hales, 1686,” all in Costin, and Watson, , Law and Working, 1:252–58Google Scholar.

104 Schwoerer, , “Attempted Impeachment,” p. 849Google Scholar.

105 Nenner, , “The Later Stuart Age,” p. 182Google Scholar.

106 Ibid., p. 208.

107 Slaughter, Thomas P., “‘Abdicate’ and ‘Contract’ in the Glorious Revolution,’ Historical Journal 24, no. 2 (1981): 323–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

108 Holdsworth, , History of English Law, 4th ed., 2:256Google Scholar.

109 “Act of Settlement,” 1701, 12 & 13 Will. III, cap. 2, in Costin, and Watson, , Law and Working, 1:95Google Scholar. And see Berman, Harold J. and Reid, Charles J., Jr., “The Transformation of English Legal Science: From Hale to Blackstone,” Emory Law Journal 45, no. 2 (Spring 1996): 506–7 and 506, n. 143Google Scholar.

110 Lamoine, Georges, ed., Charges to the Grand Jury: 1689–1803, Camden 4th ser., vol. 43 (London, 1992), pp. 68, 71Google Scholar.

111 See Kenyon, Revolution Principles, chap. 5.

112 Tryal of Sacheverell, p. 33.

113 Ibid., pp. 33–34.

114 Ibid., p. 39.

115 Among those cited were the act of 12 Car. II for the attainder of the regicides, the Militia Act, the Corporation Act, and the Act of Uniformity; see the Tryal of Sacheverell, p. 191.

116 See Plucknett, T. F. T., “Dr. Bonham's Case and Judicial Review,” Studies in English Legal History 14 (London, 1983): 34, 53Google Scholar.

117 Ibid., pp. 53–54.

118 Blackstone, William, Commentaries on the Laws of England, 4 vols. (1765–1769; reprint, Chicago, 1979), 1:91Google Scholar.

119 Plucknett, , “Judicial Review,” p. 60Google Scholar. My emphasis.

120 Blackstone, , Commentaries, 1:238–39Google Scholar.

121 Ibid., p. 239.

122 Nenner, Howard, “Liberty, Law, and Property: The Constitution in Retrospect from 1689,” in Liberty Secured? Britain before and after 1688, ed. Jones, J. R. (Stanford, Calif., 1992), p. 107Google Scholar.