Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T16:19:41.006Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Sense and sensibility or: remarks on the ‘bounds of (non)sense’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 December 2020

Hannes Peltonen*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Management and Business, Tampere University, Tampere, Finland
*
Corresponding author. E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Kratochwil's diagnostic approach identifies specific failures in particular, historical contexts in order to prescribe practically realisable remedies under non-ideal conditions. The diagnostic approach compares actual alternatives against each other rather than against some ideal. Yet, the basis for such an identification is unclear. By reinterpreting Kratochwil's approach with the help of Buddha's Four Noble Truths, one can understand Kratochwil's existential worldview and his aims, but the medium Kratochwil uses hinders the attainment of those goals. He tries to communicate in writing something (phronesis) that belongs in the world of experience.

Type
Symposium: In the Midst of Theory and Practice: Edited by Hannes Peltonen and Knut Traisbach
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

There are numerous ways of being wrong, Kratochwil tells us in his Status of Law in World Society or Meditations.Footnote 1 In its last meditation, in a ‘reflective judgement’, Kratochwil interrogates traditional strategies for knowledge generation, finds them wanting, and outlines his own alternative: diagnostics.

Kratochwil criticises the usual division of labour between a theorist and a practitioner, where the former is tasked with the clarification of foundational principles and the latter with the application of those principles to ‘real world problems’. Such a division results, he argues, in ‘two pathologies for the price of one’.Footnote 2 The theorist may elaborate ideal principles, which are allegedly at best loosely derived from the actual problems they are supposed to solve, but such ideal principles are poor guides to action.Footnote 3 The practitioner's knowledge of what ‘works’ may be based on certain techniques and practices, but ‘ready-made “solutions” are again in search of problems’. In both cases, Kratochwil argues, ‘the “answer” drives out any concern of what the question was’.Footnote 4 This leads him to argue that practitioners are quite similar to ideal theorists in their mindsets.Footnote 5 Kratochwil calls for a different mindset.Footnote 6

Dr Kratochwil or: how I learned to stop worrying and love diagnostics

Instead of ideal theory or an unreflective focus on practices, Kratochwil espouses diagnostics that supposedly avoids the pathologies of ideal theorists and ‘a-theoretical’ practitioners. Diagnostics begins with the premise that reason cannot provide a theory of judgement with which to apply universal principles, derived from ideal theory, but it does not deny the usefulness of ideals or values.Footnote 7 Rather than deriving ideal goals from values, which are used to assess some actual order, a diagnostic approach identifies specific failures in a historical real-world context. This identification should lead to a prescription of a particular remedy, which need not aspire to universal applicability, but which needs to be realisable under actual, non-ideal conditions.Footnote 8 Put differently, we can be satisfied with the second best, because the ideal is unreachable; ideal solutions may work on paper but usually not in practice. Or, in any case, ideals always need interpretation and application in a specific context anyway, and to pretend otherwise pushes the bounds of sense, argues Kratochwil. For him, an unreachable ideal is worse than a reasonable, possible, partial solution for the time being. The latter are not ideal, and they do not solve all of our problems, but they are good enough if they work and attract at least the indifference of others, if not their acceptance.

Kratochwil's focus on the ‘good enough’ solutions begs the question ‘as compared to what?’Footnote 9 Here, the comparison might be to the ideal or to other good enough solutions. As to the former, Kratochwil argues that the ideal is unrealisable in practice and a poor guide to action. Even if some ideal could be identified, it could be realised in multiple, equally valid ways. Therefore, there are multiple ‘best’ solutions, and a fundamental problem remains: no logical proof can be conclusive.

If comparing to other good enough solutions, there are, also, many of those. While some may be better than others, some of them may be equally good, although there are probably different trade-offs between equally good solutions. Analysing these trade-offs helps one to decide on a course of action, and by understanding that one's initial position is imperfect prepares one for the (inevitable) need to make future adjustments in light of the identified trade-offs.

In turn, this serves as an important ‘reality check’: the efforts of many ideal theories to solve an issue by isolating it from others is far removed from our experience in living in a social world where fully isolating one issue from others is difficult. We do not live in some ideal, imagined, timeless world but in interconnected and temporal worlds, in which we are reminded of our (and others') limitations on a regular basis. But we nevertheless must act in various ways despite those limitations.

Because we are embedded in social relations and our solutions and their trade-offs impact others, or entail acting together in some form or another, politics as the art of the possible takes centre stage. The possible is limited for instance by the need to have political agreement among multiple interested or affected parties, by our (and their) other limitations and other projects, and by the fallibility of our (and their) knowledge at any given time. Instead of focusing on the ‘Truth’ or the ideally best, Kratochwil calls attention to the need to nevertheless act within a historical and a practical social context and to focus thereby also on such issues as responsibility as an element of action.Footnote 10

In sum, Kratochwilian diagnostics leaves behind ideals and the pursuit of a perfect design. It focuses on identified or perceived problems and disappointments in the social world. We should be more like good casuists: identify and diagnose an actual problem, and why it is a problem, within particular, historical circumstances; don't start by imagining some ideal world and work backwards from there.Footnote 11 Kratochwil wants us to start in the midst of things and other people, with the possible and the realisable, in order to see what is ‘the best we can do’ given our limitations and the need to accommodate or work with others, who also have their own ideas, values, limitations, and projects.Footnote 12 Politics as the art of the possible is needed in order to settle on one solution over the others. Partially, this political process aims to achieve at least a temporarily binding decision in the absence of some algorithm to whose conclusions all ‘must’ agree.

Kratochwil's sutta

Kratochwil's punchline is: focus on acting (well) in the worlds (plural) you live in rather than on trying to discover the World (singular) from some Archimedean point. There are plenty of actual problems in need of solutions, and we have limited capabilities, resources, and time in addition to having other individual and collective projects. Do the best you can, Kratochwil seems to say. This alleviates perhaps some anxiety.

Yet, other anxieties emerge. This meditation requires one to unlearn much of what has been drilled into our western way of thinking for the past centuries. Here, some of Siddhārtha Gautama's teachings seem more relevant than those following from the western Enlightenment.

Kratochwil is no Buddhist, but there are similarities between this meditation and the Four Noble Truths.Footnote 13 Kratochwil would disagree with claims that he has an innocent view of the social world in the sense that it is allegedly void of conflict.Footnote 14 Instead, he would agree with the First Noble Truth: life is suffering (or pain), and this is an ineradicable condition of being part of the social world. Moreover, given the overall message of his meditation, Kratochwil should also agree with the Second Noble Truth: we perpetuate some of that suffering with our perceived need for some ideal theory that could solve our problems once and for all. Therefore, he should also agree with the Third Noble Truth: the suffering may cease (at least partially), when we let go of the perceived importance of having some ideal theory. Finally, the way to let go is to follow a different path: one of moderation regarding the importance and usefulness of theory, of ultimate values, and of experience. While the last three Noble Truths are important, none transcends the First Noble Truth. And so, with regards to peace and justice, like any other aspect of the social world, they must be cared for by diagnosing first the suffering and by then acting moderately, ‘not by fantasies of perfect health or omnipotence that changes the human condition by the stroke of a pen or the thump of a gavel’.Footnote 15

Hello, stranger!

Kratochwil counters objections to his diagnostics swiftly. The first objection concerns the criticism that his approach understands the existing as the reasonable, and that thereby diagnostics is uninterested in emancipation or change and only interested in feasibility. Second, diagnostics does not provide a roadmap, because it does not specify a goal to strive for. Third, a focus on local conditions misunderstands morality and its purpose in providing universally valid standards. All three objections appear valid from the perspective of ideal theory, but they are less convincing without the presumption that we must have some ideal theory, or values which all can share, or otherwise we cannot act. Moreover, these three criticisms have their own weaknesses: the perceived need to have some supreme values leads to paradoxes and undecidable debates (or even to open conflict); ideal theories do not provide roadmaps either; and morality does not require that assessments are made on the basis of alleged universal values and among all possibly imaginable claims – even if it does require an impartial assessment of affected interests.Footnote 16

Yet, in his ‘internal dialogue’, Kratochwil avoids certain important questions that might imply a return of ideals and thereby that we meet ideal theory again, some sunny day.Footnote 17

First, the diagnostic approach identifies specific failures, but it is unclear how to identify a ‘failure’. Do we not need a prior idea of what would count as a ‘success’ in order to be able to judge something as a ‘failure’, or at least as ‘not success’?Footnote 18 Second, failures are to be analysed in their actual contexts, but there are no ‘contexts’ ready to be analysed. Kratochwil has spent much of his academic career in explaining this! Contexts are constructed and constituted through our assessments, assertions, and judgements. Third, one is to compare the trade-offs of various realisable alternatives to a given, actual problem. Here, some criteria are needed, but whence they originate, or how to decide over competing, alternative, equally valid sets of criteria remains unclear. Thus, if diagnostics begins by identifying a failure in its actual context, it is unclear how to first identify the failure as a failure, how to identify what the actual context is, and how to select among alternative ways of addressing it.

Kratochwil's answer to this critique might relate to his general approach to (social) science and particularly to his ontological stance.Footnote 19 He might say that we need to interpret the context and understand that whatever criteria we use, they are historical, not a-historical, local, not universal, probably contingent. The criteria themselves are contextual. Fine, but the second criticism still holds. Alternatively, one might move to the meta-level, but that would only move the criticism by one level without answering it. Thus, because some criteria are needed, and such criteria must come from somewhere even if they are contingent and contextual, a reader is left with the impression that some form of ideals and thereby ideal theory are needed also in diagnostics. Settling on ‘what works’ or ‘is possible’ might not help, because even such an assessment requires some criteria. Somehow, on the basis of something, we need to make our assessments, judgements, and assertions, but these issues remain unclear in Kratochwil's diagnostics.

Kratochwil might point towards his overall argument about the centrality of politics. There is a need for a political process exactly because there are multiple, possibly acceptable sets of criteria or possibilities, and in a given case, we need to settle on one set at least in that case and at this time. Neither perfect theories nor laws, or thumps of a gavel, can settle this problem once and for all and ensure that one need not return to it in the future.Footnote 20 Exactly because we need some criteria, but they cannot be determined beforehand for all possible cases and futures, politics is needed. Politics is needed in constituting particular circumstances as this kind of a context within which further politics takes place in constituting a failure to be diagnosed. Politics is then needed to settle on some set of criteria and on a process to determine what to do about it. Afterwards, politics is needed to actually do it.

Does this not sound like saying that to understand politics one needs to understand politics? If so, why take ideal theory so seriously, allegedly being about finding the universal solution? Why not see it as just another part of the political process? Moreover, is this not what diagnostics is too? Is the diagnostic approach not also a ‘best’ way, albeit that it does not claim universal, ahistorical solutions beyond the diagnostic approach per se?

Put differently, Kratochwil says that ‘“non-ideal” … reflection on problems of praxis does not deny the importance of “ideals” or values, but proposes a different way of realising them’.Footnote 21 But a sympathetic co-meditator is puzzled. If one is told that we should focus on the ‘second best’, not the ‘ideally best’, because the second best is the best we can hope for in practice, then is the second best not practically the ideal? To quote Kratochwil's own saying: just because you can imagine a Pegasus does not mean that you are likely to encounter one in nature. Similarly, just because people are able to imagine some ideal world, do we not always act within the bounds of what is practically possible? Why take ideal theory so seriously, at its own word?

These questions arise from Kratochwil's desire to communicate through a written text something that belongs in the world of action, experience, and phenomenology. Diagnose, not (ideal) theorise and test, he says, but an academic book, no matter what its style, is not the greatest medium for conveying phronesis.Footnote 22 For that – ‘ideally’, hah! – we should have actual practice, deeds, and experiences (and failures and learning that we have ‘failed’) in various practical situations, just like medical students learn through clinical clerkship, rounds, and rotation. One can learn from the experiences of others, and certainly those experiences might have been written down; it is a good practice. Yet, even though someone else may have written down their experiences, reading them is my personal experience, and what I learn and how and when to apply it is not determined by the text. Like in learning to practice medicine, it is vital to learn from texts, but it is important to treat actual patients and to follow through the effects of different treatments in order to learn how and when to apply what. And that one learns through one's own experiences. One can write a book about how to ride a bicycle, but one learns how to ride it only through actual experience and trial and error.

Kratochwil wants to teach phronesis by having us read his book, but here lies his biggest challenge. Through an internal monologue with (imagined) interlocutors, by going ‘back and forth’ between facts and norms, by using analogies, metaphors, and counterfactuals, Kratochwil tries to ‘woo’ us.Footnote 23 But this wooing and its medium follow a form taken from the object of his critique. His audience (and he himself) has been trained to think and understand through that same form. What can he do but also himself use the same, currently prevailing, historical, contingent, contextually valid criteria and mindset? Thus, he himself attracts criticisms in that same form, and our mindsets elude change, despite his best efforts. But perhaps remembering Kratochwil's sutta is good enough – for now.

Acknowledgements

The author thanks Nicholas Onuf, Knut Traisbach, the journal editors, and three anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.

Footnotes

1 Kratochwil Reference Kratochwil2014, 283.

2 Footnote Ibid., 265.

4 Footnote Ibid., 289.

6 Elaborated more fully in Kratochwil Reference Kratochwil2018, Reference Kratochwil2021.

7 Kratochwil Reference Kratochwil2014, 285.

9 Footnote Ibid., 286.

10 Footnote Ibid. On responsibility in this context, see e.g. Peltonen Reference Peltonen2013 and Sikkink Reference Sikkink2021.

11 See especially Kratochwil's treatment of Rawls throughout this meditation; Jonsen and Toulmin Reference Jonsen and Toulmin1989; see also Kurowska Reference Kurowska2021.

12 Although not present in this meditation, an analogy to the medical practice would have been suitable. I thank Nicholas Onuf for ensuring that I mention this somewhere.

13 Buddha 1993.

14 E.g. Sinclair Reference Sinclair2010.

15 Kratochwil Reference Kratochwil2014, 291.

16 Footnote Ibid., 286–87.

17 See also Onuf Reference Onuf2021; Peltonen and Traisbach Reference Peltonen and Traisbach2021.

18 Note the importance of hope (of success, or at least ‘not failure’) in this context. See Vilaça Reference Vilaça2021.

20 But they can create, manage, evaluate, and adjudicate expectations of the ongoing and ensuing political processes. Kratochwil Reference Kratochwil2014, 284.

21 Footnote Ibid., 285 (original emphasis).

22 Aristotle 1984; see also Bueger Reference Bueger2021.

23 Kant's term; Kratochwil Reference Kratochwil2014, xv; see also Onuf Reference Onuf2021; Peltonen and Traisbach Reference Peltonen and Traisbach2021.

References

Aristotle. 1984. Nicomachean Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Buddha 1993. Dhammacakkappavattana Sutta: Setting in Motion the Wheel of Truth. SN 56.11, PTS: S v 420, CDB ii 1843.Google Scholar
Bueger, Christian. 2021. “Meditating Deformalization: Remarks on ‘Of Experts, Helpers, and Enthusiasts’.” International Theory 13 (3): 546–51.Google Scholar
Jonsen, Albert R., and Toulmin, Stephen. 1989. The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning. London: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2007a. “Of False Promises and Good Bets: A Plea for a Pragmatic Approach to Theory Building (the Tartu Lecture).” Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (1): 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2007b. “Of Communities, Gangs, Historicity and the Problem of Santa Claus: Replies to My Critics.” Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (1): 5778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2014. The Status of Law in World Society: Meditations on the Role and Rule of Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2018. Praxis: On Acting and Knowing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2021. “On Engagement and Distance in Social Analysis: A Reply to My Critics.” International Theory 13 (3): 588602.Google Scholar
Kurowska, Xymena. 2021. “Politics as Realitätsprinzip in the Debate on Constitutions and Fragmented Orders: Remarks ‘On Constitutions and Fragmented Orders’.” International Theory 13 (3): 538–45.Google Scholar
Onuf, Nicholas. 2021. “Bewitching the World: Remarks on ‘Inter-disciplinarity, the Epistemological Ideal of Incontrovertible Foundations, and the Problem of Praxis’.” International Theory 13 (3): 522–9.Google Scholar
Peltonen, Hannes. 2013. International Responsibility and Grave Humanitarian Crises: Collective Provision for Human Security. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peltonen, Hannes, and Traisbach, Knut. 2021. “In the Midst of Theory and Practice: A Foreword.” International Theory 13 (3): 508–12.Google Scholar
Sikkink, Kathryn. 2021. “Meditating on Rights and Responsibility: Remarks on ‘The Limits and Burdens of Rights’.” International Theory 13 (3): 574–80.Google Scholar
Sinclair, Adriana. 2010. International Relations Theory and International Law: A Critical Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vilaça, Guilherme Vasconcelos. 2021. “Hope behind the Critique of Grand Narratives of Collective Salvation: Remarks on ‘The Power of Metaphors and Narratives’.” International Theory 13 (3): 552–9.Google Scholar
Welsh, Jennifer M. 2021. “Unsettling Times for Human Rights: Remarks on ‘The Politics of Rights’.” International Theory 13 (3): 567–73.Google Scholar
Westerwinter, Oliver. 2021. “From Meditation to Action – A Research Agenda for Studying Informal Global Rule-Making: Remarks on ‘Cosmopolitanism, Publicity, and the Emergence of a ‘Global Administrative Law’ ’.” International Theory 13 (3): 560–6.Google Scholar