Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T19:52:54.514Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Globalizing the international: Bull's metaphysics of order

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2023

Regan Burles*
Affiliation:
School of Politics and International Relations, Queen Mary University of London, London, UK
*
Author for correspondence: Regan Burles, E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

As the origin story of the present world political order the globalization of international society serves as a unifying frame for the discipline of international relations. This paper considers the consequences of the shift from the ‘expansion’ to the ‘globalization’ of international society in relation to two main texts: Hedley Bull's The Anarchical Society and Tim Dunne and Christian Reus-Smit's The Globalization of International Society. The analysis shows that Bull's conception of world order depends on a key distinction between aggregate and system which marks the difference between an aggregate of local political orders and a systematically unified world political order (a global international system). Because recent histories of the globalization of international society remain guided by Bull's distinction, they are unable to explain this transition in historical terms without transforming the global international order from the explanandum of the globalization of international society to its explanans. As a result, global histories of the globalization of international society grant a global international system a structural permanence the original expansion story was meant to contest. In doing so they change profoundly the kind of questions that can be asked regarding the origins, character, and future of political order on earth.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

From expansion to globalization

That the international order constitutes, in Hedley Bull's words, ‘a single political system that is genuinely global’, is an idea so elementary that it scarcely merits mention in most literature on international politics today.Footnote 1 In a discipline often characterized as fragmented, plural, and diverse, the story of the expansion of international society exercises an outsized influence as a unifying frame that explains what has been called the universalization of the nation-state or the globalization of the European system of states. As the origin story of the present world political order, what John Hobson calls the ‘big bang’ of international relations (IR),Footnote 2 the expansion narrative serves as ‘arguably the only effective and generally accepted grand narrative that prevails’ in the discipline.Footnote 3 Moreover, as Tim Dunne and Christian Reus-Smit write in the introduction to their edited volume The Globalization of International Society, many contemporary political debates ‘assume the global political order wrought by this transformation’ of the world into a ‘universal order of sovereign states’.Footnote 4 The expansion narrative and its critical revisions are thus a foundational element of debates about the character of contemporary world order.

Over the last several decades, the way this story is told in IR has undergone a transformation indicated by the conceptual shift from the expansion to the globalization of international society. This shift is characterized by greater emphasis on reciprocal interaction between Europe and the rest of the world; the agency of non-European peoples and states in the globalization process; the prior social, political, and economic interconnections that produced the globalization of the international order; and the centrality of hierarchy, violence, and empire to the globalization process. As a result of this shift, the idea of a global international system has transformed from the explanandum (what is to be explained) to the explanans (the explanation) of the globalization of international society.Footnote 5 In what follows I consider some of the consequences of this shift with reference to two main texts: Hedley Bull's The Anarchical Society and Tim Dunne and Christian Reus-Smit's The Globalization of International Society.

As both books acknowledge, one of the key elements of Bull and Watson's original text is its attention to the novelty of the global character of contemporary international order. As Dunne and Reus-Smit explain in the Globalization volume, ‘Bull and Watson recognized the uniqueness of the global order of sovereign states produced by post-1945 decolonization’.Footnote 6 The enduring relevance and significance of Bull and Watson's volume is that ‘while most of their contemporaries in IR took this [global] order as a given, as a fundamental and enduring structural condition of international relations, Bull and Watson understood its novelty in world history’.Footnote 7 This novelty consists in the universal or global (terms usually treated as synonyms in this literature) quality of the international system since the end of the 19th century. The universality of global international society is achieved, according to Bull, through the development of common interests, structures of generally agreed upon rules, and co-operation through international organization. Contemporary scholarship on global international society tends to follow Bull in examining the historical, political, and institutional specificities of these elements of world order.

The focus of this article, by contrast, is on the way Bull and subsequent scholars of the globalization of international society mark this novelty through a specific ontology of order. As Dunne and Reus-Smit acknowledge, The Expansion ‘consists of a series of interlinked empirical narratives, structured and informed by an a priori conception of international society, one drawn largely from Bull's earlier writings’.Footnote 8 Bull's conception of world order depends on a key distinction between an aggregate and a system which for Bull marks the difference between an aggregate world of local political orders and a systematically unified world political order in the form of a global international system. I examine the consequences of these distinctions – what I call Bull's metaphysics of order – for the theory of world politics presented in The Anarchical Society and subsequent scholarship on the globalization of international society. By metaphysics of order, I mean the irreducible relation between parts and whole (designated by the term ‘system’) that Bull argues is characteristic of anything that displays order, and that is common to Bull's conception of international system and society. Attention to this ontology demonstrates how Bull's metaphysics of order continues to structure the narrative of political globalization in ways that naturalize and universalize a highly particular account of world-scale political order.

To the extent that recent histories of the globalization of international society are guided by Bull's distinction, they are unable to explain such a transition in historical terms because they transform the global international order from the explanandum of the globalization of international society to its explanans. This transformation changes the original question that guided such research, that is, how a historically, geographically, and culturally specific political order, a system of states, became ‘global’ in scope – the first world political order. As a result, global histories of the globalization of international society resemble the structural theories of international politics that they disavow and naturalize a global international system as the structural form within which changes to world political order take place. The substantial historical revisions made to the expansion narrative over the last several decades seek to overcome the ways that the original expansion narrative reifies a particular conception of international society, reproduces a Eurocentric narrative, and affirms a universalizing philosophy of history linked to racial, national, and civilizational hierarchies.Footnote 9 Making a global international order an explanation of the globalization of international society, however, grants the global international system a kind of structural permanence that the original expansion story was meant to contest. Scholars of the globalization of international society posit globality as a permanent condition and thus universalize a historically specific form of and claim to world order. A particular form of universality is thereby cast as itself universal.

This universalization is linked to several key transformations that structure thinking on world politics such as a transition from an imperial to an international world order and from natural to positive international law. As Bull puts it regarding the latter distinction, while ‘natural law theorists from the sixteenth to the eighteenth centuries described an international society that was global in extent, even if they also recognized an inner circle of Christian or European states’, the recognition of the independence of non-European political communities ‘could not be said to have been endorsed by a universal system of positive international law and did not reflect a universal international society that actually existed’.Footnote 10 Bull and Watson thus contrast the ‘theoretical’ universalism of natural law theorists with the ‘actual’ universalism of an international society ‘worldwide in its dimensions’.Footnote 11 The way Bull marks the transition from a natural law to a positive law world order through a distinction between order and disorder introduces questions related to the relationship between constituted and constitutive power, norm and exception, and politics and the political that so far have been considered primarily in relation to claims to state sovereignty rather than world order and international law.Footnote 12

The globalization of international society is also said to mark the transition from an imperial to an international world order. On the model advanced by Bull and Watson, decolonization and the establishment of the United Nations marks an end to imperialism through the realization of a universal system of formally equal sovereign states. International and imperial, on this account, are cast as opposites, and imperialism is identified with the past in contrast to the international present. This ‘imperialist historiography’, as Julian Saurin calls it, incorporates the multiplicity of world histories in the service of international order such that ‘world-historical experience is reshaped to correspond with the already established imperial lexicon’ rather than ‘critical metaphors and analogues of IR being reshaped in the light of an imperial world ordering’.Footnote 13 Glossing over the difference between before and after the globalization of the international system obscures the particularity that makes such globalization comprehensible as the result of imperialist appropriation. The concepts used to understand and formulate this transformation of world order are thus key to analysing the relationship between the international and imperial in contemporary world politics.

The ontology of order through which the globalization of international society is theorized also has consequences for global international history. As Zarakol points out, what is taken to be the endpoint of a historical narrative influences which histories prior to that endpoint are told and how they are told. If we know the conclusion in advance, this conclusion is ‘read into’ events of the past, with the result that ‘the same “facts” take on a different meanings depending on the eventual outcome’.Footnote 14 This observation has significant implications for global history and histories of international systems given that the presumed endpoint that guides these narratives is the global international system. This dilemma points not only to the importance of understanding the history of the concept of the global and its relation to international order, but also of considering the conditions of possibility of global history. While the relationship between history and the legitimation of sovereign authority in relation to domestic order has been the subject of several studies,Footnote 15 these links are also present in relation to world political order. This is suggested by the way that global histories of the globalization of international society struggle to explain this globalization in historical terms. If the endpoint of global history is global international order, avoiding the incorporation of diverse national and other histories into a singular universalizing history requires reconsidering this endpoint, which is the starting point of theories of IR.

As I argue below, with the shift from expansion to globalization, the ontology of order that in part produces the teleological, universalizing features of the expansion story, one that marks the globalization of political order during a specific historical period, becomes the ground for theorizing all past ‘world orders’. By using this ontology, Bull implicitly describes the globalization of the European system of states as a transition from a disordered to an ordered – that is, systematically unified – world order. Projecting this universality back in history thus affirms rather than challenges a Eurocentric account of world order. This ontology continues to structure contemporary accounts of the globalization of international society with the result that critical historical accounts of political globalization remain tied to a structural account of globalization in which the creation of a global international order, which for Bull is a historical novelty, is projected backwards for centuries as the condition of possibility of such an order.

This transformation changes profoundly the kind of questions that can be asked regarding the origins, character, and future of political order on earth. This problem is especially salient in the context of a variety of challenges to the current configuration of world political order. Global patterns of violence and inequality, anthropogenic climate change, nuclear weapons, old and new great power rivalries, and novel transnational social and technological forces have all given rise to vigorous debates on the prognosis for political order on a world scale. If the difference between world order and a global international system is erased, questions about possibilities for world order are limited to transformations within an unchanging structural form. If maintained, that structure itself is considered one possibility among many, a possibility whose origins, potentialities, and conceptual foundations become subject to scholarly investigation and political contestation. The qualities, genealogies, and constitutive effects of this ontology must therefore figure in the critique and contestation of such features and the structuring hierarchies that they generate.

The significance of Bull's conception of order to The Anarchical Society and the literatures it inspires has not gone unnoticed. As John Williams notes, ‘the study of and reflection upon order…have constitutive effects…ideas like order play a highly significant role in shaping the interests that are the classic focus of enquiry into political actions’.Footnote 16 Edkins and Zehfuss point out that what is excluded from a concept as unimportant or irrelevant is constitutive of the concept itself. In the case of Bull, attention to the problem of order works as a perpetual deferral of questions concerning justice.Footnote 17 More recently, Pasha has argued that the value Bull places on order obscures the centrality of colonial violence to international order. ‘By defining “order” and “justice” in specific ways’, he writes, ‘ownership of certain unsavoury features of the Western past can be evaded’.Footnote 18 Order is not simply a result of particular political practices or a neutral methodological tool but represents ontological claims constitutive of the limits and possibilities of those practices.

Bull's careful attention to questions of order thus introduces questions about form, structure, and unity to which political theories of the international already give particular answers. This is especially evident when it comes to questions about the possibilities of world politics or world political order, given the connection between conceptions of world or cosmos and metaphysical questions about order, totality, and wholeness. Bull's answers to these questions are foundational elements of his theory of world political order and remain highly influential of scholarship on the globalization of international society today.

System and society: Bull's metaphysics of order

Bull and Watson's volume The Expansion of International Society investigates how the European system of states becomes an international political system coextensive with the surface of the globe. This process, according to the authors, takes place over five centuries, beginning in the late 15th century and ending with the universalization of sovereign equality expressed in the UN Charter in 1945.Footnote 19 In Bull's view, a systematically unified world political order first emerges from what Daniel Green has recently called ‘the frenzied phase of English imperial expansion and conquest that saw much of the world suddenly come under European control after 1870’.Footnote 20 While this initial world political order is characterized by European political domination, on Bull's account, struggles for equal sovereignty, racial equality, economic justice, anti-colonial revolution, and cultural liberation bring the expansion process to its completion.Footnote 21

As Bull and Adam Watson explain in the introduction to their volume, the culmination of the expansion of international society – the political unification of the world in the form of a global international system – first occurs when the disparate political communities of the world are united in a single international political system. Before the expansion of international society, according to Bull and Watson's introduction to The Expansion, ‘the world was not organized into any single international system or society, but comprised several regional international systems (or what we choose to call international systems, with some danger of anachronism)’.Footnote 22 This systemic interconnection that produces a world political order is not simply a matter of economic or technological interconnections, but a political unification that is not reducible to them. Crucially, for Bull, ‘it was the expansion of Europe that first brought about the economic and technological unification of the globe, just as it was the European dominated international society of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries that first expressed its political unification’.Footnote 23 This unification is described by Bull with reference to the distinction between an aggregate and a system.

The significance of these a priori conceptual distinctions lies in the way they mark the novelty of the globalization of international order. Bull describes the genesis of world political order by explaining that ‘throughout human history before the nineteenth century there was no single political system that spanned the surface of the world as a whole’, but that ‘since the late nineteenth and early twentieth century there has arisen for the first time a single political system that is genuinely global’.Footnote 24 What this means, in Bull's view, is that ‘before the latter half of the nineteenth century world order was simply the sum of the various political systems that brought order to particular parts of the world’, whereas the expansion of international society across the globe means that ‘order on a global scale has ceased to be simply the sum of the various political systems that produce order on a local scale, it is also the product of what may be called a world political system’.Footnote 25 Here Bull expresses the difference between before and after the globalization of international society through a distinction between two kinds of order: an aggregate or ‘sum’ of local orders and a unified global political order that exhibits a relationship between its parts and the whole, that is, a system.

Bull thus theorizes the universalization of political order through a metaphysics of order based on the distinction between aggregate and system. This distinction marks the difference between disorder and order and is at the foundation of the concepts of international system and international society. Bull theorizes the universalization of political order with reference to the distinction between disorder and order with which The Anarchical Society begins.Footnote 26 The crucial difference between a European, or regional international system and a global one when it comes to world order is the difference between an aggregate of political units and a positive, systematically unified political order.

The Anarchical Society is an effective exemplar for its influence on subsequent scholarship and for its explicit attention to an account of order per se by which various ordered arrangements can be identified, named, and studied. My analysis proceeds from a sense that The Anarchical Society is a text which, as Williams puts it, ‘continues to repay close reading’.Footnote 27 Bull begins his text with an explicit account of what constitutes order, one which informs his description of the international system and international society. This distinction has prompted a range of responses over the last four decades from defenses of its methodological usefulness,Footnote 28 to arguments that the terms should be understood as opposite poles of a continuum,Footnote 29 to Dunne and Reus-Smit's approach of erasing the distinction between the terms altogether. Because of the shared conception of order at their foundation, however, collapsing the distinction between system and society prompts greater attention to the theory of order at their foundation, rather than less.

System and society are usually distinguished by a prior distinction between order in general and social order in particular. As Andrew Hurrell points out, this is a feature of ‘almost all analyses of social order’, which begin by distinguishing between order understood ‘in the sense of stable and regular patterns of human behaviour…in contrast to chaos, instability, or lack of predictability’, and order conceived as ‘a particular kind of purposive pattern…that involves a particular set of goals, objectives, and values’.Footnote 30 These forms of order correspond to the way the distinction between an international system and an international society is elaborated by Bull and subsequent scholars of international society. On these accounts, system refers to the minimal form of order that enables the development of the common rules, values, and culture that are characteristic of international societies.

Although descriptions of Bull's conception of order are divided between mechanical and purposive accounts, the way Bull distinguishes between order and disorder shows that his account of order is not a mechanistic one, but rather purposive, that is, expressed by an organized relation between parts and whole. William Bain aligns mechanistic and purposive conceptions of order with what he calls imposed and immanent theories of order that have their roots in philosophical and theological conflicts over the origin of the world, the nature of God, and the conflict between religious and secular authority. While in an immanent theory of order, ‘the natures of things are the outcome of their interconnections and their interconnections are the outcome of their characters’,Footnote 31 on the theory of imposed order ‘singular things, having no intrinsic connections, enter into relations that are imposed from without, either by legislation or the force exerted by an impersonal mechanism’.Footnote 32 Most commentators ascribe a mechanical conception of order to Bull's theory of international society. Louiza Odysseos, for example, argues that the realist, rationalist, and revolutionist traditions combined in Bull's anarchical society are premised on an account of political coexistence premised on what Odysseos calls a ‘logic of composition’ in which coexistence takes place between pre-constituted units, whether individuals or states.Footnote 33 According to this logic of composition, the international names the sum total of this collection of autonomous, non-relational, independent units. Bain agrees, arguing that Bull employs a mechanical conception of system that exhibits the qualities of imposed order, in which separate states combine in ‘an aggregate of singular states’.Footnote 34 These descriptions, I contend, are at odds with the way Bull's understanding of systemic order is theorized in opposition to an aggregate.

Bull begins The Anarchical Society by distinguishing between order and disorder, a difference which is analogous to the relation between purposive and mechanical forms of order. Here Bull is concerned not with the limits of particular conceptions of order but the boundaries of order, that is, the conditions of possibility of any ordered whole, be it a set of books or an international system. ‘To say of a number of things that together they display order’, he writes, ‘is to say that they are related to one another according to some pattern, that their relationship…contains some discernible principle’.Footnote 35 Order results when a number of parts have been organized in relation to a common whole. To illustrate the distinction between what he calls a ‘haphazard relation’ and an ordered relation, Bull uses the example of a number of books. ‘A row of books on the shelf displays order’, he explains, ‘whereas a heap of books on the floor does not’.Footnote 36 The row of books aligned on the shelf is arranged according to a principle by which they are organized, whereas the books on the floor lack any such principle. To use language that Bull will use later in the text, the books on the floor do not display order because unlike the books on the shelf, they are not related to one another as parts to a whole.

Next, Bull distinguishes between order in general and social order in particular. Order as such is to be distinguished from what he calls ‘order in social life’, which is not any ordered pattern, but one designed to achieve the realization of purposes, goals, and values. Hurrell calls this distinction ‘beguilingly simple’ because of the way that ‘order as fact and order as value are often very hard to disentangle’.Footnote 37 Bull tries to do so by analogy with books, explaining that, ‘in this purposive or functional sense, a number of books display order when they are not merely placed in a row, but are arranged according to their author or subject so as to serve the purpose or fulfil the function of selection’.Footnote 38 The distinction between order in general and social order in particular is expressed in the difference between the books placed in a row, and books arranged according to some principle of selection. This is a curious definition, since Bull has just described books placed in a row as related to one another according to ‘some discernible principle’.Footnote 39 Arranging books by author or subject is precisely to arrange them according to a unifying principle, just as arranging books in a row on a shelf is to do the same. In short, on Bull's account, both order in general and social order in particular are determined by an organizing principle or purpose that combines parts into an organized whole. Only phenomena that exhibit such a relation between parts and whole can be said to display order.

Bull defines international order as ‘a pattern or disposition of international activity that sustains those goals of the society of states that are elementary, primary, or universal’.Footnote 40 These goals are sustained by the five primary institutions of international society that Bull identifies: the balance of power; international law; diplomacy; war; and great powers.Footnote 41 According to Bull, these institutions are forms of social order, and as such, they are directed towards the achievement of particular goals. In the case of international society, these goals are threefold: first, preservation of the system and society of states; second, preservation of the independence of sovereign states; and third, the maintenance of peace in the sense of the temporary absence of war.Footnote 42 The primary goal of international society, on this account, is to secure a particular kind of order that enables other goals or patterns of order to follow. This definition of international order relies on a prior conception of order expressed by the concept of a system of states. ‘A system of states (or international system)’, Bull writes, ‘is formed when two or more states have sufficient contact between them, and have sufficient impact on one another's decisions, to cause them to behave – at least in some measure – as parts of a whole’.Footnote 43 Both concepts depend on a prior distinction between order and disorder in such a way that make order (in general) and social order (particular orders) difficult to distinguish.

How then can social order be distinguished from order? Bull qualifies his definition by arguing that social order is not defined by purposive action in general, but by purposive action aimed at specific ends. For Bull, these ends are security from violence and death (life), guarantees of contract and agreement (truth), and some conception of private ownership (property).Footnote 44 Thus, while violent conflict exhibits a pattern, ‘this is a situation we should characterize as disorderly’.Footnote 45 It is here, as Vincent aptly puts it, that ‘the exponent of order in social life in general is in practice a defender of particular orders’.Footnote 46 The entanglement of order and social order in Bull's text is outlined in detail by John Williams, who shows how Bull vacillates between normative and ‘objective’ conceptions of order. At various points throughout The Anarchical Society, Bull presents order either as an arrangement that displays purpose or goal-directed behaviour in general, or as an arrangement that aims at those particular goals that Bull views as conditions of possibility for social life.Footnote 47 The result, Williams explains, is that ‘the idea of society is virtually subsumed into the notion of order; for where there is order there is society, as the distinguishing feature of society is that it generates order’.Footnote 48 In short, on Bull's account, social order is a particular form of order in general, but any attempt to identify such a general account of order inevitably lapses into particularity.

As Williams admits, Bull's articulation of the relation between order, social order, and international politics is, at times, ‘deeply confusing’.Footnote 49 Part of this confusion stems from the very different forms of order that are attributed to Bull's conception of an international system. The difference is in part attributable to the way that, as Jackson points out, ‘“system” is a term that invites a billiard-ball image of international relations as a mechanical “clash of forces”’.Footnote 50 Bull's emphasis on a particular form of order, however – a whole not reducible to its parts – leads others to conclude that for Bull, ‘order and purpose are in some fundamental way connected’.Footnote 51 Bull sometimes acknowledges explicitly that there is no impartial conception of order, and thus that social order is ‘necessarily a relative concept’; what counts as order and disorder depends on one's purpose.Footnote 52 Bull thus articulates a conception of order that depends on purpose, and a conception of purpose that depends on a particular form of order. The reciprocal relation between order and social order in Bull's text helps explain the difficulty of distinguishing between system and society in studies of international order. Just as the difference between a purposive order in general (books on a shelf) expresses the same form of order as one directed towards the achievement of particular purposes, so system and society express an analogical form of order, one in which order is achieved through parts related by some kind of ordering principle. Ultimately, all of Wight's ‘traditions’ rely on the form of order expressed by system: that of a relation between parts and whole.

It is in this sense that Bull's distinction between order and social order is not a difference in form. Rather, social order is considered as a particular expression of order in general. Bull thus has much to say about how the social order of the international is maintained in relation to particular ends through common interests, rules, and institutions such as the balance of power, diplomacy, great powers, and war.Footnote 53 These elements of international politics, however, concern the maintenance of an already present system. While social order, on Bull's account, is constituted by parts arranged in particular ways for particular purposes, order as such is understood as the arrangement of parts in relation to a whole. This reading of Bull's theory of order accords with the position that the system/society distinction can and should be collapsed, as both depend on a systemic, purposive conception of order. Underneath the claim that order is purposive and constructed is an ontological account of order based on the concept of system as opposed to an aggregate. This distinction is the basis of Bull's theorization of the globalization of international society.

Bull's account of the development of a world political order is thus consistent with the theory of order that Bull outlines at the start of The Anarchical Society. On this account, before the European states system expands to encompass the globe, the various political orders of the world resembled the heap of books in Bull's metaphor. Like the heap of books, and like the international, the world only becomes ordered with the emergence of a system, that is with the arrangement of the various ‘local’ political orders that populated the earth into an irreducible whole. It is precisely the lack of any relation between parts and whole by which Bull marks the difference between the world before the globalization of international society and world constituted by global international political order. It is only when these local orders are understood as elements of a single system, a whole that is not reducible to its component parts, that, according to Bull, world political order is achieved. It is precisely the lack of any relation between parts and whole by which Bull marks the difference between the world before the globalization of international society and world constituted by global international political order. While there is something that Bull can call world order before international society becomes global, the relations between these local political orders are not organized in relation to a single political order of which they are all a part; order is merely local order.

What is notable about Bull's analysis is the way that the link between the expansion of the European system of states and the development of world order is expressed in the abstract distinction between aggregate and system. This distinction has profound implications for studies of world politics, given that it marks the genesis of what for Bull is the first world political order: the global system of states. It is on the basis of the distinction between system and aggregate that Bull attributes an ordering function to the European system of states and positions that system as the subject of the creation of a world political order. This theory of order informs Bull's account of the globalization of international society. This has consequences for Dunne and Reus-Smit's synthesizing conceptual innovation – to conceive of the globalization of international society as the result of forces constitutive of a broader world political system.

Globalizing international society

A consensus has emerged in IR that The Expansion presents a narrow, one-sided account of the globalization of international society that portrays the European system of states as the subject of a progressive history of which post-1945 decolonization is the culmination. This account has been subject to a number of critiques over the last several decades which demonstrate that the expansion narrative provides a Eurocentric explanation of the spread of the European states system and tells a story of unidirectional European expansion that largely occludes both the experiences of those outside Europe and the co-constitution of Europe and its outsides.

Following Neumann's suggestion to turn towards a conceptualization of entry into international society as a ‘relational process’,Footnote 54 a host of studies examine the entry into international society of various countries that emphasize the diffuse, complex, relational processes by which the European states-system expanded. This work aims to correct what Shogo Suzuki identifies as the English School's ‘myopic and normatively driven conceptualization’Footnote 55 of the expansion of international society by attending to what Ejdus calls ‘the entrants’ side of agency’.Footnote 56 Slovakia's entry, for example, is ‘multi-stage’ and ‘chronologically layered’ process that required contact with ‘multiple power centres’ within Europe,Footnote 57 while Russia exemplifies a ‘mediated expansion’ that demonstrates the way the standard of civilization operates within the state system as well as between the states system and its outsides.Footnote 58 Others point to the way that China's diplomatic practices, from its entry into international society in the late 19th century to its role in the reconstruction of international order after the First World War, evince not ‘a passive “response” to the Western “impact”’ but rather that ‘China actively participated in the reconstruction of the post-war international order’.Footnote 59 Colàs, meanwhile, considers the role of pirates, privateers, and corsairs in the development of international society from the 16th to the 19th centuries, describing the process as ‘a dialectical relationship between barbarism and civilization’ that is characterized as ‘highly uneven, protracted and conflictual’.Footnote 60 This theme also appears in global history in Andrew Phillips' critique of vanguardism, which concludes from a study of the strategic use of local intermediaries by colonial powers that ‘world politics has been defined by hybridization – not homogenization – for the vast majority of the modern era’.Footnote 61

This literature corrects the way that standard accounts conceive of expansion as a primarily intra-European process, thus ignoring how European identity was constructed through relations with an outside ‘Other’.Footnote 62 As Neumann writes, ‘European international society was, from the very start, dependent on having internal and external Others in relation to which it could self-define’.Footnote 63 As a result, ‘a focus on the expansion of international society occludes the experience of being expanded upon – the focus directs attention only to one side of the social relation in question’.Footnote 64 This literature is critical of standard accounts of international society for missing the significance of colonialism and empire in determining the boundaries of international society and corrects this oversight by showing the tensions between the principles of equality and reciprocity that existed within the European states-system and the relations of hierarchy and inequality that existed between Europe and the rest of the world. While historical scholarship on the expansion in IR focuses on a variety of time periods, from the earliest European voyages to the Americas to the entry of states into the international order post-1989, these analyses articulate shared conceptual innovations.

These are synthesized by Dunne and Reus-Smit in The Globalization of International Society. Contributors to Dunne and Reus-Smit's volume respond to the limits of the expansion narrative by studying the development of international society in global terms. Only by understanding the world as an already-ordered political whole, the argument goes, can the globalization of the European state-system be studied without excluding or rendering subordinate other peoples, actors, and practices constitutive of that process. The key conceptual move that organizes the volume is the distinction between the original account of the expansion of international society and the contemporary critical study of the globalization of international society. The distinction between expansion and globalization is summed up by Dunne and Reus-Smit as follows:

The conventional narrative about the ‘expansion’ of international society is a story of ‘European’ international society expanding outwards to encompass the globe through processes of imperialism and decolonization…the story we tell in the following chapters is one in which international society was, from the outset, profoundly influenced by encounters, engagements and interactions between European and non-European peoples, producing a global international order that is culturally and politically far more complex.Footnote 65

Expansion presents a vision of the development of world order as a ‘scaled-up’ version of the European system of states that develops internally rather than through an interplay of internal and external identities, forces, and processes. Globalization is a catch-all term for the variety of critical accounts of the development of European international society in relation to the political communities and economic forces that traversed the wider world.

Dunne and Reus-Smit's volume synthesizes decades of historical scholarship on the globalization of international society through two key conceptual innovations made with reference to The Anarchical Society. The first relates to the distinction between system and society, the need for which the authors argue is eliminated by contemporary developments in conceptual and historical analysis related to international society. The second has to do with Bull's concept of a world political system, the world order whose study the authors suggest can explain the globalization of the European system of states. Together, however, these conceptual changes present a vision of the global international order characterized by the kind of structural permanence that was the target of the original expansion story. This results from the way globalization narratives continue to rely on many of the same basic conceptual distinctions found in Bull's work.

The rejection of the system/society distinction has been adopted wholesale by the contributors to the recent edited volume The Globalization of International Society. These scholars, the introduction claims, ‘draw no distinction between international society and system, theoretically or historically’.Footnote 66 This analytical move is one that has been gaining increasing currency in studies of international order and international society. For Dunne and Reus-Smit, its benefit is a more fulsome account of the way today's global international society developed in relation with a global political order. ‘International society’, they write, is ‘preceded by, and embedded within, wider networks of global social and political interaction’.Footnote 67 Understanding international society as analytically inextricable from the international system helps explain its globalization in relation to forces beyond its boundaries that are global in scope. Such an approach, however, reinforces the way conceptions of the international system and society rely on a single account of order to theorize the establishment of the international system as world political order. Bull's use of this conception of order casts doubt on Dunne and Reus-Smit's reading of the relationship between the international system and the world political system in The Anarchical Society. While they consider the globalization of international society to be an effect of a broader world political system, for Bull it is the globalization of international society that produces the first world political system in the form of a global system of states.

Dunne and Reus-Smit's global approach to the history of the European system of states builds on Bull's conception of the world political system. The authors point out that while Bull admits that ‘international society emerged and globalized within a broader world political system’ by which ‘[its] evolution is profoundly affected’,Footnote 68 he and other scholars of expansion fail to ‘consider the long-term constitutive effects of the world political system on the development of international society’.Footnote 69 By contrast, the globalization approach locates international society within a long history of interactions with outside political, economic, and social actors within a broader world order, interactions which are constitutive of international society itself. According to Dunne and Reus-Smit the novelty of the global international order is related to the division of the entire surface of the globe into separate states: ‘Never before had the entirety of the globe been divided up into such states’.Footnote 70 This global division, however, cannot be considered an aggregate in the manner that Bull views world order prior to globalization. Rather, it is predicated on a substantive political unity expressed by the concept of system. It is only after this unification that, according to Bull, a world political system can develop.

While Bull's most frequently cited definition of world order is ‘patterns or dispositions of human activity that sustain the elementary or primary goals of social life among mankind as a whole’,Footnote 71 world order in The Anarchical Society, as shown above, is also defined on the basis of the distinction between aggregate and system. In Bull's influential formulation, ‘the first global political system has taken the form of a global system of states. What is chiefly responsible for the emergence of a degree of interaction among political systems in all the continents of the world, sufficient to make it possible for us to speak of a world political system, has been the expansion of the European states system all over the globe, and its transformation into a states system of global dimension’.Footnote 72 The distinction between a world comprised of a multitude of political orders, be they empires, states, or proto-international systems, and a global international political order is marked by the distinction between an aggregate and a system by which Bull defines order in general. Thus, while Bull does distinguish between world order and international order, world politics for Bull has taken the form of international politics because the international constitutes a single global political system. The global character of this political order lies in the way it links various local political orders into a systematically unified whole. According to Bull, it is the world prior to the globalization of international society that is characterized by political division. What marks the genesis of world order is not only a novel form of division but a novel form of political unity: a global system of states.

This is because for Bull, the wider set of processes that constitute the world political system can only develop after the emergence of what Bull considers the first world political system, the global system of states. While Bull does argue that ‘the state-system has always been part of a wider system of interaction in which groups other than the state are related to each other’, he adds that ‘all that is in any sense new or recent in the world political system of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries is its global or worldwide character; and, of course, it is only in this recent period that the states system itself has been worldwide’.Footnote 73 To examine the historical development of the European system of states as an element of a positive (in the sense of positive law) world political order, would be, on Bull's definition of world political order, to project backwards into history a world political condition that is only characteristic of the planet since the late 19th century. While it is surely possible to imagine the world as a single order at any given point in history, such an order is substantively different from the positive, systematically unified political order Bull identifies as the result of the globalization of international society.

What Bull calls world order and world society, however, do involve much more than the global system of states. Bull distinguishes between international order and world order, writing that the subjects of the former are states while the subjects of the latter are individuals. Thus, world order is ‘more fundamental and primordial’ and ‘morally prior’ than international order. However, ‘if international order does have value, this can only be because it is instrumental to the goal of order in human society as a whole’.Footnote 74 Possibilities for world order and world society depend upon the prior ordering of the world as a global international system. While the international is constitutive of world political order, then, world order exceeds the explicitly political dimension of global order.

Exactly what additional elements are constitutive of world order is the subject of considerable debate. Some point to the development of a culture of universal human rights or a global civil society.Footnote 75 Others suggest that humanitarian intervention in the name of human security is suggestive of world society.Footnote 76 These elements align with Bull's conception of a ‘world political system’ which includes a greater range of social interaction within the whole of world political order. Bull insists that a global system of states is not synonymous with the world political system, whose beginnings Bull discerns in ‘the world-wide network of interaction that embraces not only states but also other political actors, both “above” and “below” the state’.Footnote 77 These, however, are additions to the existing world order established by the system of states. The globalization of the states-system provides the unity that makes a ‘world’ out of what Bull might call the ‘haphazard’ relations between local political orders.

At the same time, this degree of interaction is insufficient for a world society, since for Bull the latter involves not just ‘interaction linking all parts of the human community to one another, but a sense of common interests and values, on the basis of which common rules and institutions may be built’.Footnote 78 In this regard, Bull explains, ‘the concept of a world society…stands to the totality of global social interaction as our concept of an international society stands to the concept of an international system’.Footnote 79 The relation between the world political system and world society is analogous to that between the international system and international society. This means that the world political system follows from and is enabled by the globalization of international order. The world political system thus cannot explain the development of international society without transforming global international order from an explanandum to an explanans – from a question to an answer.

Global international order: from explanandum to explanans

The way a global international system is transformed from the explanandum of studies of the expansion of international society to its explanans is exemplified in chapters by Jennifer Welsh and Adam Phillips in the Globalization volume. Both Welsh and Phillips are explicit about their use and revision of conceptual claims made initially by Bull. Welsh's article aims to ‘adjust the frame of reference from the narrower notion of European expansion, which misrepresents the relations between West and non-West, to the global interplay between states, regions, and civilizations’.Footnote 80 Welsh writes that ‘the core question is…less “who became part of international society and when”, and more how various entities fit within a global order at different points in time – an order which contained elements of both system and society’.Footnote 81 In referring to system and society, Welsh evokes the two major elements of Bull's version of the contemporary ‘anarchical society’. However, the global political order of which system and society are elements does not arise for Bull until the end of the 19th century. If a global anarchical society is present even at the beginning of the expansion process, the difference that the expansion narrative arose to explain – between a world of multiple political orders and a systematically unified global order – is glossed over. The global quality of the present international order – the quality that marks its novelty, according to Bull – is posited as a condition that brings about the globalization of the European system of states.

Similarly, Andrew Phillips builds on Bull's claim that ‘the states system has always been part of a wider system of interaction in which groups other than the state are related to each other’,Footnote 82 to argue that while ‘from the late fifteenth century, Western Europeans undeniably spearheaded a qualitatively higher increase in global interaction…they did so off a foundation of pre-existing hemispheric interconnections’.Footnote 83 Phillips demonstrates the way that ‘before European international society spearheaded early modern globalization, it had itself first been constituted through an earlier wave of Afro-Eurasian hemispheric integration’.Footnote 84 However, if the expansion of the European system of states is explained with reference to a global political system, the key difference articulated by Bull in his theory of international order – between a world of multiple political orders and a world of one – is difficult to explain. By studying the development of the European states system as an effect of a broader set of dynamics of a world political system, Welsh and Phillips add to our historical understanding of the development of European system of states but are unable to explain what makes the present international political system more ‘global’ than any previous – the question that spurred investigation into the globalization of the European international system in the first instance.

The consequence of this approach is that the difference Bull's expansion narrative claims to explain, between a world of many political orders and a world of a single, positive political order, is eliminated. On this account, the development of a global international political order is explained with reference to the prior existence of a global international political order. To theorize this global interplay, contributors to The Globalization of International Society posit the historical existence of a condition that is said to be the result of the expansion process – a condition of political unity expressed by an international political order that is both systemic and societal, coextensive with the surface of the globe. Returning to the origin of global international society seems to land us back where the inquiry began: in a global international order (system) described as an anarchical society. The order that is said to be the result of the globalization of international society is posited as its origin.

The result is that the distinction between ‘world order’ and ‘global international system’ is glossed over. Welsh, for example, explains that:

There is currently a substantial category of non-UN member states in the international system, which includes Taiwan, the Turkish Republic of Northern Cyprus, Palestine, Abkazia, South Ossetia, and Kosovo. These territorial units are not universally recognized as sovereign, yet in many cases they have governmental structures responsible for conducting foreign policy.Footnote 85

Here, despite lacking formal membership, these states are still considered part of a global international system. The lack of formal recognition of a given state is not considered to threaten the ‘global’ status of this order, because it is understood as an already accomplished systematic unification that makes the global political order irreducible to its component parts (in this case states).

Thus, what for Bull is a historically specific, positive political order becomes the eternal form of a world order in which change is measured only through differences in its arrangement. Erasing the distinction between order and disorder on which accounts of the globalization of international society are based results in a theorization of global order in terms of a structural permanence that is difficult to distinguish from Kenneth Waltz's paradigmatic account of international structure. The projection of a hybrid (system and society) global order like the present one projected back into centuries may differ in content but not in form from Waltz's position, criticized for decades, that ‘the anarchic character of international politics accounts for the striking sameness in the quality of international life through the millennia’.Footnote 86 Given the difficulties of distinguishing between system and society noted by scholars of international society, histories of the international that begin with a global international system do tell a story historical change, but also one of profound structural permanence.

This problem is also present in work that makes similar analytical moves beyond the Globalization volume. Keene, for example, recommends moving from the problem of expansion to that of ‘stratification’.Footnote 87 Like Welsh, he argues that too much emphasis has been put on states' entry into the 19th century European ‘family of civilised nations’ than on the much wider range of diplomatic activity and interstate agreements that can be found during this period. Rather than being synonymous with international society itself, the European family of nations, on this account, is part of ‘a larger – indeed, effectively global – international social system’.Footnote 88 According to Keene, this shift transforms the guiding research question from who gained membership to the European family of nations and when to the relative positions of actors within an existing global international system. This permits greater historical analysis of a wider range of 19th century social relations and attention to changing roles and statuses within international order. However, it also projects backwards in time a form of world order – the global international system – that for Bull was only established at the turn of the 20th century. As we have seen above, Bull readily admits that ‘expansion’ takes place within a wider complex of social relations, yet crucially for him, political order is not reducible to these. Once again, the phenomenon that scholarship on the expansion sought to explain – an international political order of global scope – becomes the ground for historical analysis rather than its explanandum. As a result, what is unique about that phenomenon according to Bull – its claim to global political unity – is naturalized and cut off from critical analysis and explanation. The subject of historical analysis is restricted to differences in the arrangement of an existing political system rather than the constitution of world political order itself.

This problem is also evident in the way that Dunne and Reus-Smit, drawing on Bruno Latour, theorize global international society as ‘something that is, at any given point in time, “already assembled”’.Footnote 89 On this model, the present configuration of global international order in the form of a system of states is only the latest iteration of a series of global international systems stretching back centuries. The present order is thus ‘a distinctive governing assemblage’ which has ‘evolved over the course of the past five centuries within a context of and through interaction with, a shifting panoply of individuals and institutional actors, coalescing around diverse social and political assemblages, each of which has constituted a distinct locus of social and political power – a world political system’.Footnote 90 This critique is premised on an understanding of the world political system that departs significantly from Bull's and that misses the significance of the concept in relation to world order for Bull: its novelty.

If the primary distinguishing feature of the current world political system is its ‘global’ character, these approaches are unable to answer the question of the difference between before and after the globalization of the European system of states. If global political order in part explains this globalization, it is not clear what it consists of, since it is precisely the now-global condition of the previously local or regional international political system that the expansion process purports to explain. What is missed is the ordering function of discourses of the international system and its globalization in affirming a single planetary political order of a very particular form. Although they have added much depth to the expansion narrative, and are well-positioned to add even more, when the influence of Bull's metaphysics of order is considered, existing critiques of the expansion narrative appear less like challenges to the expansionist thesis than stories of the structural permanence of a global international system that rival even the most comforting ‘Grotian pastorale’.

World political order in question

The way a global international system is projected backwards onto world order in scholarship on the globalization of international society is at odds with the relative openness with which Bull considers the potential limits of global international society and the possibility of alternative forms of world order. Emphasizing its historical novelty, Bull writes that ‘the form of the states system has been the exception rather than the rule’ and therefore ‘world order could in principle be achieved by other forms of universal political organisation, and a standing question is whether world order might not be better served by such other forms’.Footnote 91 This is a key point given the way that Bull considers the idea that the states system is no longer adequate to the ends of human beings on earth in relation to peace and security, social and economic justice, and man and the environment.Footnote 92 Although Bull defends the states system against these criticisms, they have only intensified in subsequent decades.

Moreover, Bull ends The Anarchical Society by considering possibilities for alternative forms of world order both in terms of different kinds of states system as well as possibilities that lie beyond it. Bull envisions, for example, a completely disarmed international system as well as one in which nuclear weapons proliferate and are universally available.Footnote 93 Beyond the states system, Bull explores the possibility of a world government, a new medievalism, and what he calls non-historical alternatives, ‘new forms of universal political organisation may be created in the future that do not resemble those that have existed in the past.Footnote 94 Bull's reflections on these possibilities are clearly limited in a variety of ways. Yet they indicate a sensitivity to the novelty and historical particularity of the world order established along the lines of a global international system. Alongside the universalizing effects of the transition from the expansion to the globalization of international society, and of Bull's metaphysics of order, these reflections raise a range of considerations for future studies of political globalization.

First, they point to the continued importance of taking the claims to globality and universality that underlie most theories of international politics as questions and problems rather than as explanations of contemporary political phenomena. This involves at a minimum recognizing the form of political universality expressed by the international system as one form of universality among many. Moreover, to the extent that our politics is oriented by a vision of political universality that in some respects has become practical, this ‘universal’ condition must be addressed as a political predicament that bears on how to envision the past, present, and future of world order. What responses can we cultivate to the predicament of political universality other than reactionary nationalism and progressive complacency and universalization? What novel diagnoses might produce unfamiliar descriptions of the origins and possible transformations of political order on earth?

One key dimension of this predicament, this article suggests, is a deep-seated attachment to a particular ontology of order. Inquiry into past and future transformations of world order thus requires critical attention to questions relation to form, order, and structure in terms of how these concepts themselves are understood and the consequences of those understandings for world politics. Developing alternatives possibilities for world politics is a conceptual as much as it is a historical problem. This is evident in the way Bull inaugurates a theory of world politics through a highly abstract account of order based on a key distinction between aggregate and system. The way this distinction structures decades of scholarship on the globalization of international society points to the powerful effects of such distinctions and the importance of subjecting them to detailed analysis. This is especially the case in relation to concepts like order, globe, and world given their relation to difficult and highly contested claims to totality and universality.

By putting narratives of globalization in question, this analysis also points to key links between scholarship on the globalization of international society and the geopolitical thought of figures like Halford Mackinder and Carl Schmitt that merit further exploration. Edward Keene's study of the dynamics of toleration between European states and civilization between European and non-European states, for example, resonates with Carl Schmitt's diagnosis of the end of the Jus Publicum Europaeum.Footnote 95 For Keene and Schmitt, political globalization upsets the relationship between hierarchy and equality resolved through the spatial differentiation between a society of states and its outsides. Exploring the links between accounts of the globalization of international society and the problems of globalization addressed in geopolitical thought introduces problems that can transform such accounts into urgent contemporary political questions.

Conceiving of the global international system as the explanans of historical-political phenomena, past or present, changes the kind of questioning available to students of international politics. The novelty that provoked the questions of Bull and earlier scholars of expansion – the sense that the international system of the late 19th century constituted the first political order of global scope – is displaced in favour of the notion that the global international system is only the latest iteration of the long history of world political order. The form that this order takes among subsequent authors, however, is of the global international system that is understood to be ‘very young’.Footnote 96 The question of the globalization of the international system transforms from one about the transformation of a world that consists of an aggregate of local political orders into a single world political order into one that concerns the arrangement of an existing world political order. This turns a historically and conceptually specific form of universality into a universal form of universality on which accounts of the past, present, and future of world order are based.

In the difference between aggregate and system lie the distinctions between natural and positive law and imperial and international that continue to structure contemporary accounts of world order. Although Watson insists that ‘there is no abrupt gulf or revolutionary dividing line between the European state system and the present global one’,Footnote 97 this is difficult to reconcile with the way Bull conceives of the difference between a world of multiple political orders and world political order in such stark terms – between aggregate and system. Beginning analyses on one side of the distinction between natural and positive law, imperial and international world order precludes analysis of the claim to a single, global political order that is the starting point of most theories of IR and hides the constitutive effects of a metaphysics of order that makes a ‘world’ and an ‘order’ out of its outsides and its opposites. It is also evidence of the way historical change is measured in relation to a background of structural permanence. In this case, that structure is an irreducible parts-whole relation named by the term ‘system’.

The problem of the ontology of order implied by the concept of system is not unique to Hedley Bull and the literature on international society. The systemic quality of the international is a truism that is presumed by many accounts of international politics across conventional disciplinary divides. The difficulties outlined above are no doubt related to the challenges of thinking political order on world scale and the analytical and political dilemmas related to structure that they engender. The above analysis therefore represents a small effort to point towards a broad set of problems related to the metaphysics of order expressed by the concept of system used to theorize the international. These are of serious concern given that many of the most daunting political challenges of today call for a questioning of world order not only at the level of content and arrangement, but the level of form and structure. Ensuring this remains a question requires critical attention to the concepts of order that structure stories of political globalization and their constitutive effects on world politics today.

Acknowledgements

A version of this paper was presented at the University of Victoria's Centre for Global Studies and was completed with the help of funding from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

Conflict of interest

The author declares none.

Footnotes

1 Bull Reference Bull1977, 19.

2 Hobson Reference Hobson2012, 190.

4 Dunne and Reus-Smit Reference Dunne and Reus-Smit2017, 18.

5 Hempel and Oppenheim Reference Hempel and Oppenheim1948, 135–75.

6 Dunne and Reus-Smit Reference Dunne and Reus-Smit2017, 3.

11 Footnote Ibid., 120.

13 Saurin Reference Saurin2006, 35.

14 Zarakol Reference Zarakol2022, 4.

17 Edkins and Zehfuss Reference Edkins and Zehfuss2005.

19 Bull and Watson Reference Bull and Watson1984, 6.

22 Bull and Watson Reference Bull and Watson1984, 1.

24 Bull Reference Bull1977, 19.

25 Footnote Ibid., 19–20.

26 McKeil (Reference McKeil2022) shows how a purposive conception of disorder in world politics is also present in Bull's work. Here I'm referring to the disorder that for Bull precedes any purposiveness and is expressed through the distinction between aggregate and system.

28 Watson Reference Watson1987, 152; Zhang Reference Zhang1991, 4; Neumann Reference Neumann2011, 466.

31 Bain Reference Bain2020, 30.

33 Odysseos Reference Odysseos2007, 14.

34 Bain Reference Bain2020, 185.

35 Bull Reference Bull1977, 3.

40 Footnote Ibid., 16.

41 Along with many possible additions. For recent examples, see Falkner and Buzan Reference Falkner and Buzan2017; Nantermoz Reference Nantermoz2020.

42 Bull Reference Bull1977, 16–18.

44 Footnote Ibid., 4–5.

48 Footnote Ibid., 25.

49 Footnote Ibid., 24.

50 Jackson Reference Jackson2000, 113.

51 Edkins and Zehfuss Reference Edkins and Zehfuss2005, 456.

52 Bull Reference Bull1977, 4.

53 Footnote Ibid., 95–124.

54 Neumann Reference Neumann2011, 470.

55 Suzuki Reference Suzuki2005, 137.

56 Ejdus Reference Ejdus2014, 448.

57 Bátora Reference Bátora2014, 456.

58 Kayaoglu Reference Kayaoglu2010; Buranelli Reference Buranelli2014, 818–19.

59 Zhang Reference Zhang1991, 15.

60 Colàs Reference Colàs2016, 841–42.

61 Phillips Reference Phillips2016, 63.

62 Neumann and Welsh Reference Neumann and Welsh1991

63 Neumann Reference Neumann2011, 465.

64 Footnote Ibid., 467.

65 Dunne and Reus-Smit Reference Dunne and Reus-Smit2017, viii.

66 Footnote Ibid., 33.

68 Footnote Ibid., 34.

69 Footnote Ibid., 32.

71 Bull Reference Bull1977, 19.

72 Footnote Ibid., 20.

73 Footnote Ibid., 268.

74 Footnote Ibid., 22.

77 Bull Reference Bull1977, 266.

78 Footnote Ibid., 269.

81 Footnote Ibid., 147.

82 Bull Reference Bull1977, 268. This passage is cited in Phillips Reference Saurin2019, 43.

84 Footnote Ibid., 43.

86 Waltz Reference Waltz1979, 66.

87 Keene Reference Keene2014, 652.

89 Dunne and Reus-Smit Reference Dunne and Reus-Smit2017, 34.

92 Bull Reference Bull1977, 273–85.

93 Footnote Ibid., 226–35.

94 Footnote Ibid., 20–21.

96 Dunne and Reus-Smit Reference Dunne and Reus-Smit2017, 18.

97 Watson Reference Watson1992, 277.

References

Arendt, Hannah. 1963. On Revolution. New York: The Viking Press.Google Scholar
Bain, William. 2020. Political Theology of International Order. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bátora, Jozef. 2014. “Lost in Translatio Imperii: Slovakia's Layered Entry into International Society.” International Relations 28 (4): 456–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benjamin, Walter. 1978. “Critique of Violence.” In: Reflections, edited by Demetz, Peter, 277300. New York: Schocken.Google Scholar
Berridge, Geoffrey. 1980. “The Political Theory and Institutional History of States Systems.” British Journal of International Studies 6: 8292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boli, John W., Thomas, George M., and Ramirez, Francisco O.. 1997. “World Society and the Nation State.” American Journal of Sociology 103 (1): 144–81.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1977. The Anarchical Society. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1979. “The Revolt against the West.” In The Expansion of International Society, edited by Bull, Hedley and Watson, Adam, 217–28. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1984. “The Emergence of a Universal International Society.” In The Expansion of International Society, edited by Bull, Hedley and Watson, Adam, 117–26. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley, and Watson, Adam, eds. 1984. The Expansion of International Society. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Buranelli, Filippo Costa. 2014. “Knockin’ on Heaven's Door: Russia, Central Asia and the Mediated Expansion of International Society.” International Relations 28 (4): 817–36.Google Scholar
Buzan, Barry. 2004. From International to World Society? English School Theory and the Social Structure of Globalisation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Çapan, Zeynep Gülşah. 2017. “Enacting the International/Reproducing Eurocentrism.” Contexto Internaçional 39: 655–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakrabarty, Dipesh. 2009. Provincializing Europe. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Colàs, Alejandro. 2016. “Barbary Coast in the Expansion of International Society: Piracy, Privateering, and Corsairing as Primary Institutions.” Review of International Studies 42 (5): 840–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Kathleen. 2012. Periodization and Sovereignty: How Ideas of Feudalism and Secularization Govern the Politics of Time. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques. 2002. “Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority.’” In Acts of Religion, edited by Anidjar, Gil, 228310. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dunne, Tim, and Reus-Smit, Christian, eds. 2017. The Globalization of International Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edkins, Jenny, and Zehfuss, Maja. 2005. “Generalising the International.” Review of International Studies 31 (3): 451–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ejdus, Filip. 2014. “Entry into International Society: Central and South East European Experiences.” International Relations 28 (4): 446–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falkner, Robert, and Buzan, Barry. 2017. “The Emergence of Environmental Stewardship as a Primary Institution of Global Civil Society.” European Journal of International Relations 25 (1): 131–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fasolt, Constantin. 2004. The Limits of History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Green, Daniel M. 2020. “The Nineteenth Century Liberal Tradition and the English School Historical Narrative.” Journal of International Political Theory 16 (2): 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl Gustav, and Oppenheim, Paul. 1948. “Studies in the Logic of Explanation.” Philosophy of Science 15 (2): 135–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobson, John. 2012. The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurrell, Andrew. 2006. “The State of International Society.” In The Anarchical Society in a Globalized World, edited by Little, Richard and Williams, John, 191215. New York: Palgrave-MacMillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Robert. 2000. The Global Covenant: Human Conduct in a World of States. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
James, Alan. 1993. “System or Society?Review of International Studies 19: 269–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaczmarska, Katarzyna. 2019. “Reification in IR: The Process and Consequences of Reifying the Idea of International Society.” International Studies Review 21 (3): 347–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kayaoglu, Turan. 2010. “Western Eurocentrism in International Relations Theory.” International Studies Review 12 (2): 193217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keene, Edward. 2002. Beyond the Anarchical Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keene, Edward. 2014. “The Standard of ‘Civilisation’, the Expansion Thesis and the 19th-Century International Social Space.” Millennium 42 (3): 651–73.Google Scholar
Little, Richard. 2015. “Reassessing the Expansion of International Society.” In System, Society and World, edited by Murray, Robert W., 1924. London: E-International Relations Publishing.Google Scholar
McKeil, Aaron. 2022. “Global Disorder: A Blind Spot or Distinct Concept of the International Society Approach? Global Studies Quarterly 2 (4): 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nantermoz, Olivia. 2020. “International Refugee Protection and the Primary Institutions of International Society.” Review of International Studies 46 (2): 256–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neumann, Iver. 2011. “Entry into International Society Reconceptualised: The Case of Russia.” Review of International Studies 37: 463–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neumann, Iver, and Welsh, Jennifer. 1991. “The ‘Other’ in European Self-Definition: An Addendum to the Literature on International Society.” Review of International Studies 17: 327–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Odysseos, Louiza. 2007. The Subject of Coexistence: Otherness in International Relations. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Pasha, Mustapha Kamal. 2017. “Decolonizing the Anarchical Society.” In The Anarchical Society at 40, edited by Suganami, Hidemi, Carr, Madeleine, and Humphreys, Adam, 92109. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Phillips, Andrew. 2016. “Global IR Meets Global History: Sovereignty, Modernity, and the International System's Expansion in the Indian Ocean Region.” International Studies Review 18: 6277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saurin, Julian. 2006. “International Relations as the Imperial Illusion, or, the Need to Decolonize IR.” In Decolonizing International Relations, edited by Branwen Gruffydd Jones, 2342. New York: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 1985. Political Theology. Translated by George Schwab. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. 2006. The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus Publicum Europaeum. Translated by G. L. Ulmen. Candor, NY: Telos Press.Google Scholar
Suzuki, Shogo. 2005. “Japan's Socialization Into Janus Faced European International Society.” European Journal of International Relations 11 (1): 137–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vincent, Raymond John. 1990. “Order in International Politics.” In Order and Violence: Hedley Bull and International Relations, edited by Miller, J.D.B. and Vincent, R.J., 38–64. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Walker, R.B.J. 2010. After the Globe/Before the World. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth. 1979. Theory of International Politics. London: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Watson, Adam. 1987. “Hedley Bull, States Systems, and International Societies.” Review of International Studies 13: 147–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, Adam. 1992. The Evolution of International Society. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Welsh, Jennifer. 2017. “Empire and Fragmentation.” In The Globalization of International Society, edited by Dunne, Tim and Reus-Smit, Christian, 145–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, John. 2006. “Order and Society.” In The Anarchical Society in a Globalized World, edited by Little, Richard and Williams, John, 13–34. New York: Palgrave-MacMillan.Google Scholar
Williams, John. 2013. “The International Society–World Society Distinction.” In Guide to the English School in International Studies, edited by Navari, Cornelia and Green, Daniel M., 127–42. London: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2022. Before the West: The Rise and Fall of Eastern World Orders. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhang, Yongzhin. 1991. “China's Entry into International Society: Beyond the Standard of ‘Civilization.’Review of International Studies 17 (1): 316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar