Introduction
The 1990–91 Gulf War was the main starting point for doctrinal reflections on how to enhance the protection of the environment in armed conflict through international environmental law (IEL). The devastating environmental damage caused by that war showed the weaknesses of the rules of international humanitarian law (IHL) that were specifically devoted to the protection of the environment at the time.Footnote 1 Attempts were made as early as June 1991 to provide additional IHL rules on the protection of the environment through the adoption of a new convention;Footnote 2 however, this proposal for a “Fifth Geneva Convention” did not have any follow-up.
It is not surprising, therefore, that, shortly after the Gulf War, States considered the issue of the interplay between IHL and IEL. In October 1991, the delegate of the Netherlands stated at the United Nations (UN) General Assembly Sixth Committee, on behalf of the European Community, that it would
be necessary to examine the relationships between international environmental law and humanitarian law, which seemed to be developing along rather independent lines, even though the developments of environmental law had consequences for the interpretation of rules concerning the protection of the civilian population.Footnote 3
In the same vein, a group of experts convened by the International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC) in 1992, in the context of the General Assembly's work on the topic, identified several “most important matters requiring study”, including the “[r]elationship between international humanitarian law and international environmental law (regional and universal regulations)”.Footnote 4
Thirty years later, that issue has still not been comprehensively addressed. The ICRC's 2020 Guidelines on the Protection of the Natural Environment in Armed Conflict still raise the concern raised by the ICRC-convened group of experts in 1992: the need to continue clarifying the interaction between the two bodies of law when a rule of IEL and a rule of IHL are found to apply in parallel.Footnote 5 In 2022, numerous States and organizations criticized the Draft Principles on Protection of the Environment in Relation to Armed Conflicts adopted by the International Law Commission (ILC) in 2019 as not providing enough guidance on the interplay between IHL and IEL.Footnote 6 That being said, at least some aspects of the issue have been implicitly or expressly addressed by the ILC and the ICRC, as well as by scholars. In addition, two comprehensive studies have recently been devoted to the topic,Footnote 7 with one of them also considering the interactions of IEL and IHL with international human rights law (IHRL).Footnote 8 A general survey of those works shows that two main processes have been considered for enhancing the protection of the environment in warfare through IEL.Footnote 9 The first is the application of that body of law, including its treaties, in armed conflict alongside IHL. This “application process” was envisaged soon after the 1990–91 Gulf War.Footnote 10 The application of IEL in armed conflict was notably asserted in July 1991 by the participants at the Conference of Experts on the Use of the Environment as a Tool of Conventional Warfare co-sponsored by the Canadian Ministry of External Affairs and the UN.Footnote 11 The other process, which was envisaged much later in legal literature, is the “interpretation process”, whereby IHL concepts or norms, such as the IHL notion of the “natural environment”, are interpreted in light of IEL.Footnote 12
The aim of this paper is to provide a critical assessment of the work of legal scholars dealing with those two processes, including the work of institutions like the ILC, the ICRC and the UN Environment Programme (UNEP). In such works, including the most comprehensive ones, developments may be missing or may be confusing or contradictory in relation to both processes. This paper is mainly concerned with two aspects of the interplay between IHL and IEL, namely the conditions for such interplay and the mechanisms used to solve conflicts between these two bodies of law.
Conditions for IHL–IEL interplay
The conditions for IHL–IEL interplay are different depending upon whether IEL is used to complement IHL through its application in armed conflict (the application process) or through the interpretation of IHL in light of its rules or concepts (the interpretation process). This section will examine the relevant conditions applicable to each process.
The application process
IHL is expected to interact with IEL under the application process only when the two bodies of law enter into conflict. This requires, as a precondition, that they apply to the same conduct and that their respective scopes of application overlap. One must therefore first address the issue of the overlapping scopes of application of IHL and IEL before examining when conflicts arise between the two bodies of law and how to deal with such conflicts.
Overlapping scopes of application
In order to determine the extent to which the respective scopes of application of IEL and IHL may overlap, the different aspects of the IEL scope of application must be examined. The first relates to its temporal scope; this is the well-known issue of the applicability of IEL in armed conflict. The two other aspects, which are rather neglected in legal literature, include the personal and geographical scopes of IEL.
Temporal scope
IHL and IEL may overlap both in times of peace and war. Whereas IHL primarily applies in armed conflict, it contains certain rules that also apply before an armed conflict begins, like the rules prescribing precautionary measures against the effect of attacks,Footnote 13 or that extend beyond the end of hostilities, such as the obligations relating to remnants of war.Footnote 14 Likewise, although IEL primarily applies in times of peace and contains relevant rules such as those imposing preventive measuresFootnote 15 or dealing with access to environmental information,Footnote 16 it does not necessarily cease to apply during war. It has indeed been extensively debated in legal literature whether IEL continues to apply once an armed conflict has broken out.Footnote 17
Usually, scholars agree that IEL treaties continue to apply to States at least in non-international armed conflict (NIAC), as well as between the belligerent and neutral States in international armed conflict (IAC).Footnote 18 As between belligerents in IAC, scholars usually start by looking at the terms of the treaties,Footnote 19 before submitting a theory to settle the issue in the numerous instances where the treaties are silent.Footnote 20 Since the adoption of the Articles on the Effects of Armed Conflict on Treaties by the ILC in 2011,Footnote 21 scholars also abundantly refer to these articles to assert the continued applicability of IEL treaties in armed conflict,Footnote 22 even though, as stressed in legal literature,Footnote 23 the rebuttable presumption of such applicability provided in the annex to those articles is not based on any firm practice. Other scholars tend to complement the ILC work by relying on “specific State practice”, namely declarations made by belligerents in a particular conflict.Footnote 24 As a result, it is now often stated in legal scholarship that IEL, including its treaties, continues to apply in armed conflict unless expressly provided otherwise.Footnote 25 Elements other than those usually mentioned in legal scholarship, however, could be submitted to support that view. The most interesting one is “general State practice”, in the sense of the practice taking the form of general State declarations on the topic, which may supplement “specific State practice”. Although they were quite scarce after the 1990–91 Gulf War, such declarations have flourished for the last decade, especially in the context of the ILC's work on the protection of the environment in relation to armed conflicts.Footnote 26
In addition, it is intriguing to observe that many scholarly works examine the issue of the applicability of IEL in armed conflict in relation to IEL itself, as a “special regime”, or IEL treaties.Footnote 27 Few scholarly writings focus on that issue in relation to the rules of IEL, even though certain scholars rightly stress that such an issue must ultimately be settled at that level when treaties do not contain any indication on their applicability in armed conflict.Footnote 28 The traditional test based on the compatibility of a treaty with a state of war might prove useful in this regard.Footnote 29 It could exclude the applicability of certain IEL obligations whose performance would be unrealistic between belligerents, such as obligations of cooperation when they are directly connected to the military effort of the belligerents and do not provide a solution that would make them compatible with a state of war.Footnote 30 This may actually have a significant impact on the applicability of IEL during warfare, since obligations of cooperation constitute the core business of IEL; that body of law is indeed primarily driven by the principle of good neighbourliness. Alternatively, classical mechanisms provided in the law of international responsibility, such as force majeure, or in treaty law, like the recognition of a fundamental change of circumstances, might be invoked in certain circumstancesFootnote 31 to exclude the operation of the incompatible IEL obligation.Footnote 32
That being said, certain arguments often developed in legal scholarship, or by authoritative institutions, in relation to the issue of the continued applicability of IEL in armed conflict must be either rejected or developed. One of them, supported by scholars,Footnote 33 the ICRCFootnote 34 and the ILC Rapporteur,Footnote 35 is to make the continued applicability of IEL dependent upon a consistency test with IHL. This argument is questionable as it confuses the applicability of a rule with its application to a given conduct. It is only when two rules are applicable that this test can operate to determine which rule applies. This is actually the reasoning adopted by human rights bodies. Those bodies do not question the applicability of an IHRL rule in the case of conflict with IHL, while applying the regime provided under IHL to the concrete conduct at stake.Footnote 36 This has the advantage of maintaining the applicability of the inconsistent IEL rule and of providing the State(s) victim of the violation of that rule with an opportunity to seize the enforcement mechanisms provided by the relevant IEL treaty. The argument based on a consistency test with IHL would also have the inconsistent effect that IEL norms would remain applicable between belligerents because they are consistent with IHL, like obligations of cooperation requiring notifications of data related to the war effort, although those norms are clearly incompatible with a state of war.
Another questionable argument frequently advanced by scholars,Footnote 37 or by institutions like the ILC,Footnote 38 is to build their position in favour of the continued applicability of IEL in warfare on the Advisory Opinion on the Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons (Nuclear Weapons Advisory Opinion) issued by the International Court of Justice (ICJ). Although, as detailed below, in this Opinion, the ICJ asserted that environmental considerations had to be taken into account when applying IHL,Footnote 39 it nonetheless stopped short of addressing the issue of the applicability of IEL in armed conflict.Footnote 40 The Court acknowledged that States’ views on the matter were divided and expressly stated that “the issue [before it was] not whether the treaties relating to the protection of the environment [were or not] applicable during armed conflict”.Footnote 41
Finally, several scholars argue that IEL treaties must continue to apply between belligerents that are party to them, otherwise unlawful damage would be caused to the neutral States that are also party to those treaties.Footnote 42 This would also run against the indivisible nature of such treaties.Footnote 43 Such an argument is only partly relevant. First, it is only valid with respect to IEL treaties that regulate global environmental concerns, such as biodiversity, climate change or the ozone layer, the protection of which is sought for the benefit of all States. Second, even with respect to those treaties, the suspension or termination of their applicability might concern only certain obligations, the non-performance of which would not result in any damage to neutral States.
Personal and geographical scopes
Both IHL and IEL bind States and at least apply within the respective territory of those States. By contrast, it is unclear whether, unlike IHL, IEL is also binding upon armed groups and applies extraterritorially. This issue, which relates to the personal and geographical scopes of application of IEL, is generally overlooked by scholars.Footnote 44 It is, however, a crucial issue to consider given that many armed conflicts are non-international in nature, and therefore involve non-State armed groups, and given that IACs, including those involving situations of occupation, necessarily imply an extraterritorial dimension. This issue is thus in urgent need of further development by scholars.
As detailed elsewhere,Footnote 45 IEL could arguably be applicable to non-State armed groups under two main conditions. First, the applicable IEL should be well delineated. It would be meaningless to assert the applicability of IEL in general to non-State armed groups given the heterogeneous nature of IEL. One such delineation would involve basing the binding nature of IEL for non-State armed groups on the doctrine of legislative jurisdiction.Footnote 46 This implies that the applicable IEL would only include the rules binding upon the State against which, or in the territory of which, the non-State armed group is fighting, in addition to any rules that the non-State armed group would have unilaterally committed to respect. Second, as increasingly – but still controversially – claimed in relation to the applicability of IHRL to non-State armed groups, the relevant IEL norms should only be applicable to those groups that have enough capacity to comply with them, in particular to those having territorial control and exercising State-like functions.Footnote 47 Alternatively, the relevant IEL norms should be applicable to any non-State armed group, providing that the positive obligations of result are modulated and rephrased as obligations of means in order to be adapted to the specific material capacity of any such group.
Regarding the extraterritorial applicability of IEL,Footnote 48 it is argued that any enquiry on that issue must start from the terms of the treaties, as is usually done in relation to the more general issue of the continued applicability of IEL in armed conflict. Certain IEL treaties, like the 1992 Convention on Biological Biodiversity (Biodiversity Convention), are explicit on this issue and provide for their extraterritorial applicability or at least the extraterritorial applicability of some provisions. Otherwise, each rule must be scrutinized and its exterritorial applicability determined in light of its terms or the nature of the obligation that it provides. Ultimately, where no indication can be found in the treaty or its provisions, IEL treaties could be presumed to apply extraterritorially given the object and purpose of IEL, as IEL primarily aims at mitigating transboundary environmental harm. However, as suggested in relation to the applicability of IEL to non-State armed groups, the applicable IEL would only be extraterritorially binding upon States either if they have sufficient territorial control abroad or if the applicable positive obligations of result are mitigated and formulated as obligations of means.
Conflicting norms or interpretations
When the respective scopes of application of IHL and IEL overlap but the two bodies of law do not come into conflict, IEL is expected to apply alongside IHL without affecting it or being affected by it. In that case, IEL has no impact on IHL as such but only has impact on the regulation of armed conflict, by adding rules to those already provided by IHL on the matter. This is likely often to be the case for matters arsing before or after the armed conflict, since IHL contains few rules applying during those periods, unlike IEL.Footnote 49 In times of war, IEL may also play a complementary role with respect to IHL. Even in such cases, though, modulations of the applied IEL norms might then be needed, in cases where those norms, as further explained below, are not formulated in a sufficiently flexible way to accommodate the realities of war.
By contrast, when IHL conflicts with IEL, both bodies of law necessarily interplay. The notion of conflict is therefore pivotal to dealing with such interplay, but very few studies on the topic have delved into it. Most often, it is broadly stated that IHL should apply as the lex specialis and therefore prevail over IEL.Footnote 50 The most well-known type of conflict is the conflict of norms. As developed by one scholar in a study devoted to the interplay between IHL and IEL,Footnote 51 such conflict might be construed in two ways: (1) either strictly, as implying that the norm of one body of law obliges its addressees to adopt conduct prohibited by a norm of the other body of law; or (2) more broadly, as involving norms that provide for different, but not contradictory, results. The ILC made such distinction in its work on the fragmentation of international law and opted for the second, broader, meaning.Footnote 52 It seems that this is the only conflict of norms that might exist between IHL and IEL, as arguably, no IHL norm imposes on belligerents an obligation to act in contravention to an applicable IEL norm.Footnote 53 IHL at most permits rather than prescribes belligerents to act in such a way. That permission encompasses acts such as causing damage to civilian objects, including the environment, as non-excessive incidental damage or as direct damage when and for such a time as that object becomes a military objective, providing that the damage is not widespread, long-term and severe.
Such permission is hardly compatible with the absolute prohibition provided in certain IEL treaties against causing any damage to parts of the environment that they protect. This is arguably the case with respect to Article 22 of the Biodiversity Convention, which provides that the Convention may “affect the rights and obligations of [the States Parties] deriving from any existing international agreement … [when] those rights and obligations would cause a serious damage or threat to biological diversity”.Footnote 54 This is more clearly the case with respect to Article 6(3) of the 1972 Convention Concerning the Protection of the World Cultural and Natural Heritage (World Heritage Convention), which provides that “[e]ach State Party to [the] Convention undertakes not to take any deliberate measures which might damage directly or indirectly the cultural and natural heritage … situated on the territory of other States Parties to this Convention”.Footnote 55 Admittedly, as emphasized by certain scholars,Footnote 56 the relevant norms of the two bodies of law would not come into conflict if the belligerents were to decide to abstain from using the IHL permission to cause environmental damage, and to refrain from attacking a site or area protected by IEL treaties such as the Biodiversity Convention or the World Heritage Convention. This decision would include refraining from causing harm to a specific part of the environment even when it is considered a military objective or is so closely located to a military objective that it is likely to be subjected to incidental damage. However, such abstention would result merely from the free will of the belligerents and not from the law. In such a case, a conflict of norms must therefore be considered to exist between IHL and IEL and should be solved by displacing the inappropriate norm in accordance with the approach detailed below.
Legal scholarship often fails to identify another type of conflict between IHL and IEL, namely a conflict between interpretations of the two norms rather than between the norms themselves. Contrary to conflicts of norms, conflicts of interpretation arise when the applicable IEL norm contains open-ended terms which might be subject to either an interpretation based on IEL or an interpretation involving an IHL paradigm. This is the case, for example, with the open-textured Article 3 of the Convention on Wetlands of International Importance Especially as Waterfowl Habitat (Ramsar Convention), which provides that “[t]he Contracting Parties shall formulate and implement their planning so as to promote the conservation of the wetlands …, and as far as possible the wise use of wetlands in their territory”.Footnote 57 A conflict of interpretation does not require displacing any norm, as is the case for conflicts of norms; rather, it requires interpreting the open-ended IEL term in light of the appropriate applicable regime. This still, nonetheless, implies displacing one regime in favour of another and therefore amounts to a conflict. This is well known in the practice regarding IHL–IHRL interplay. As stated by the ICJ in the Nuclear Weapons Advisory Opinion, the human right not to be arbitrarily deprived of one's life must be interpreted in light of the relevant IHL rules rather than the IHRL paradigm when applied in armed conflict.Footnote 58 Applying the same standard to IEL–IHL conflicts of interpretation would imply that, in the context of armed conflict, open-ended terms of an applicable IEL norm should be interpreted in light of relevant IHL rules. Such interpretation is needed in order to adapt IEL to the realities of war when applied in armed conflict.
The interpretation process
The application of IEL in times of war, with its potential adaptations in case of conflicts with IHL, is not the only process through which IEL may further enhance the protection of the environment in armed conflict; this may also be achieved by resorting to IEL as a means for interpreting IHL norms or concepts. Several suggestions as to how this can be done have already been put forward in legal literature, such as interpreting the IHL principles of proportionality and precaution relating to the conduct of hostilities in light of the IEL precautionary principle,Footnote 59 the IEL principle of preventionFootnote 60 or the IEL requirement to conduct an environmental impact assessment.Footnote 61 As will be seen in the following sections, this interpretation process, whereby IHL is interpreted in light of IEL, is different from the application process in several respects. Notably, it does not raise the issue of the overlapping scopes of application of IHL and IEL or the issue of conflicts of norms or interpretation. In addition, it necessarily involves the interplay between the two bodies of law since IEL is incorporated into IHL. Legal scholarship is, however, often confused about the conditions for such interplay.
The irrelevance of the scope of application
Many scholars assume that IEL must apply in armed conflict in order to serve as a means for interpreting IHL.Footnote 62 Practice in fact shows that definitions have been borrowed from particular treaties to inform IHL concepts, although those treaties expressly provide that they do not apply in wartime. For instance, both the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY)Footnote 63 and the Special Court for Sierra Leone (SCSL)Footnote 64 acknowledged that the notion of hostage-taking contained in the relevant IHL treaties could be built upon the definition provided in the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages (Hostage Convention). The Hostage Convention, however, contains a clause excluding its applicability in armed conflict in so far as the act of hostage-taking is regulated by those IHL treaties.Footnote 65 In addition, the salient aspects of the elements of the war crime of hostage-taking provided in the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (ICC) in relation to both IACs and NIACs are taken from the definition enshrined in the Hostage Convention.Footnote 66 Such an interpretative approach is also followed in relation to IEL: scholars do not hesitate to refer to definitions of the environment contained in certain IEL instruments in order to inform the meaning of the notion of the “natural environment” used in IHL,Footnote 67 even when those instruments expressly provide that they are not applicable in armed conflict.
In addition, even when the norm used to inform IHL applies in armed conflict, practice clearly shows that this norm must not necessarily have the same scope of application as the IHL interpreted rule.Footnote 68 In particular, that norm, unlike IHL, must not necessarily be extraterritorially applicable or applicable to non-State armed groups. Courts such as the ICTYFootnote 69 and the ICC,Footnote 70 as well as institutions like the ICRC,Footnote 71 have abundantly resorted to IHRL, the application of which to non-State armed groups remains controversial, to inform IHL norms applicable to any NIAC and, therefore, to any non-State armed group party to such conflict.
Indeed, the underlying rationale for such an interpretive approach is not that both the interpretative and interpreted norms apply in armed conflictFootnote 72 or, more generally, that they have a similar scope of application. It is rather that the notions contained in these norms are similar and that one body of law provides for a workable definition for the other. This is what provides the interpretation process with added value for strengthening the protection of the environment in armed conflict. Under the application process, the potential for IEL to enhance that protection is indeed dependent upon IEL's own scope of application, which is seemingly more limited than that of IHL. Notably, as explained above, it is unclear whether IEL could apply to non-State armed groups and extraterritorially in armed conflict. By contrast, when IEL is incorporated into IHL through the interpretation process, it becomes part of IHL and indisputably applies to any conduct to which the interpreted IHL norm applies, including to non-State armed groups and extraterritorially.
That being said, as with the application process, IEL might require adaptations when being incorporated into an IHL norm, notably in order to conform to IHL structural features such as the principle of equality between belligerents. This is the exact principle that pushed the ICTY to exclude the condition of the involvement of a State agent required by IHRL in the definition of torture when using that definition to inform the same notion under IHL.Footnote 73 Adaptations of the IEL interpretative standard may also be needed to accommodate the limited capacities of States when acting abroad, or those of armed groups. It is highly unfortunate in this respect that the ICC failed to make such adaptations in the Al Hassan case, when it interpreted the IHL fair trial guarantees applicable in NIACs in light of IHRL.Footnote 74 The Court incorporated in its entirety the relevant IHRL regime in those IHL guarantees, including certain human rights that may hardly be complied with by any armed group, such as the right for the accused to take proceedings before a court in order to decide on the legality of the accused's deprivation of liberty.Footnote 75
The distinction between IEL and environmental considerations
Another significant confusion in legal scholarship regarding the interpretation process is the lack of distinction between IEL and environmental considerations as a means for interpreting IHL.Footnote 76 While IEL is the body of codified and customary international law that deals with the protection of the environment, environmental considerations are a vaguer concept that does not stick to the law and includes any concern on the protection of the environment.Footnote 77
The ICJ notably advanced the view that environmental considerations must be taken into account to interpret IHL norms in the 1996 Nuclear Weapons Advisory Opinion. The Advisory Opinion is often misunderstood by scholars. Besides being silent on the issue of the continued applicability of IEL treaties in armed conflict, it does not indicate whether the IHL conditions of necessity and proportionality – or even IHL in general – must be interpreted in light of IEL. It merely refers to environmental considerations or factors as interpretative means.
Three ICJ statements, which are often indistinctly mentioned in legal literature,Footnote 78 are of relevance here. In the first one, the Court asserts that “States must take environmental considerations into account when assessing what is necessary and proportionate in the pursuit of legitimate military objectives”.Footnote 79 As emphasized by certain States,Footnote 80 that assertion is ambiguous as it is unclear whether it deals with jus ad bellum or IHL: while immediately preceded by considerations specific to the right of self-defence and referring to the condition of necessity rather than the IHL concept of “military necessity”, the Court statement nonetheless ends with the IHL notion of “legitimate military objective”.
The second relevant ICJ statement is much clearer and univocally deals with IHL. The Court expressly acknowledges “the general view according to which environmental considerations constitute one of the elements to be taken into account in the implementation of the principles of the law applicable in armed conflict”.Footnote 81 Only environmental considerations, rather than IEL, are mentioned as potential interpretative means for IHL.
Admittedly, in the third relevant statement, the Court refers to IEL and asserts that
the existing international law relating to the protection and safeguarding of the environment … indicates important environmental factors that are properly to be taken into account in the context of the implementation of the principles and rules of the law applicable in armed conflict.Footnote 82
However, the interpretative standard envisaged by the Court is not IEL as such but the “environmental factors” indicated by IEL. At most, such a statement shows that there might be a thin line between IEL and environmental considerations or factors. This is arguably the case when environmental concerns are expressed in the preamble of IEL treaties, like the fundamental role of biological diversity in “maintaining life sustaining systems of the biosphere”, as indicated in the preamble of the Biodiversity Convention. It is controversial whether such concerns may indeed be used to inform IHL notions, like the test of excessive damage under the IHL rule of proportionality, as environmental considerations or as part of IEL as such.Footnote 83
The distinction between IEL and environmental considerations nonetheless remains noteworthy. Obviously, it is only when IEL is used to interpret IHL that interplay might exist between the two bodies of law. More fundamentally, the mechanism designed to guide such interplay varies depending upon whether IHL is interpreted in light of IEL or environmental considerations. The mechanisms for the interpretation of IHL through IEL are more specific and constraining, notably because, as developed in detail below, all the States bound by the interpreted IHL norm must normally also be bound by the interpretative IEL rule. Such a constraint does not apply to the interpretation of IHL in light of environmental considerations. It is, however, unclear which particular kind of interpretation is then involved and through which specific mechanisms such an interpretation may legally be justified. The least unsatisfactory solution is to classify it under the generic term of “evolutionary interpretation”, which covers interpretations made by several courts in many fields of international law on the basis of various mechanisms in order to adapt the terms of a treaty not only to the developing international legal context but also to evolving values, facts and concerns.Footnote 84
In any case, it seems useful that environmental considerations may act as an autonomous means for the interpretation of IHL. However, in the last steps of the ILC's work on the protection of the environment in relation to armed conflicts, the ICRCFootnote 85 and some StatesFootnote 86 opposed the draft principle that “[e]nvironmental considerations shall be taken into account when applying the [IHL] principle of proportionality and the [IHL] rule on military necessities”.Footnote 87 One of the reasons for this was that the notion of “environmental considerations” was too vague and that, in turn, this would risk undermining the application of the rule of proportionality. The draft principle has therefore been deleted and is considered as implicitly contained in the preceding draft principle, which acknowledges “the application of the law of armed conflict [in particular the principles and rules of distinction, proportionality and precaution] to the environment”.Footnote 88
However, it is mainly on the basis of the (vague) notion of environmental considerations (or concerns) that the environment historically started to be considered as a civilian object or a(n) (enemy) property under IHL. The relevant IHL rules have then been considered as applicable to the environment, including the main IHL rules on the conduct of hostilities as well as those dealing with (enemy) property under the control of the adversary, such as in cases of occupation.
This can be traced back to the aftermath of the 1990–91 Gulf War. For example, participants at the Conference of Experts on the Use of the Environment as a Tool of Conventional Warfare, held in Ottawa in 1991, emphasized that “the application and development of the law of armed conflict [had] to [take] account of the evolution of environmental concerns generally” and asserted that the “customary laws of war … now [included] a requirement to avoid unnecessary damage to the environment”.Footnote 89 In its Resolution 47/37 of 1992, the UN General Assembly also recognized the application to the environment of the Hague rule that prohibits “the destruction … of property not justified by military necessity and carried out unlawfully and wantonly”.Footnote 90 In its Nuclear Weapons Advisory Opinion, the ICJ expressly viewed the General Assembly's assertion as being due to the fact that the Assembly took into account “environmental considerations … in the implementation of principles of the law applicable in armed conflict”.Footnote 91
The recognition of the application of the relevant general IHL rules to the environment, which is now well established, constituted a major step towards strengthening the protection of the environment in armed conflict – in fact, according to Hulme, this recognition “has done more to protect [the environment] than any environmentally specific rule of international humanitarian law”.Footnote 92 That being said, the notion of environmental considerations should still be used to further protect the environment in armed conflict. Its vagueness might be seen as an advantage rather than an obstacle to that end; indeed, it may constitute a flexible means for adapting the interpretation or application of IHL to the various and evolving environmental concerns. Such a role is clearly apparent with respect to IHL rules like the principle of proportionality. Environmental considerations might be helpful for those who plan or prepare an attack when determining the expected environmental damage to be balanced against the direct and concrete military advantage anticipated from that attack. Based on recognized scientific knowledge, which may evolve over time, or any information that commanders knew or should have known at the time of the attack, those considerations are particularly useful for assessing the weight or value of such damage and its foreseeability.Footnote 93 For example, attackers might know or should have known from information available in recognized environmental studies or from information specifically transmitted to them that the area to be attacked is of particular importance for biodiversity and that the destruction of that area would cause the extinction of a species, which would in turn affect an entire ecosystem of great value for a particular civilian population.
Mechanisms guiding IHL–IEL interactions
As demonstrated above, IHL–IEL interplay only arises in case of conflicts of norms or interpretation under the application process or when IEL is incorporated into IHL under the interpretation process. Formal mechanisms have been identified in legal scholarship, which may provide guidance on the outcome of such interplay, though certain scholars argue that solutions must be found beyond such mechanisms in some cases. These formal mechanisms will accordingly be first examined before appraising the approaches providing solutions that go beyond such mechanisms.
Starting with formal mechanisms
Two main formal mechanisms are considered in legal scholarship with respect to IHL–IEL interplay, namely the principle of systemic integrationFootnote 94 and the lex specialis principle,Footnote 95 although the former is much less often mentioned than the latter. Moreover, a series of other specific mechanisms are proposed by scholars, but only in relation to the interpretation process. This section will review the two formal mechanisms and those other mechanisms.
The principle of systemic integration
The principle of systemic integration is based on Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT), according to which a treaty shall be interpreted in light of “any relevant rules of international law applicable in the relations between the parties”. Scholars have raised some objections against the principle's applicability to IEL–IHL interplay.Footnote 96 The first objection concerns the interplay arising in case of a conflict of norms. This objection is clearly valid: the principle of systemic integration is only relevant when interpreting a norm or a concept, not for settling a conflict between two norms whose content is already clear.Footnote 97
Two other, more controversial objections are raised in legal scholarship. The first is the condition of the identity of the parties, according to which parties to an interpreted treaty must be the same as (or at least include) the parties to the treaty serving as a means for interpretation.Footnote 98 Otherwise, interpretations based on a treaty could be binding upon States not party to that treaty, which would hardly be acceptable for those States. The second, more disputable objection is that only legal sources can be used as a standard for interpretation. It is true, as emphasized in legal scholarship,Footnote 99 that these two objections are particularly relevant with respect to IEL–IHL interplay due to the specific features of IEL, notably that most IEL treaties are ratified by far fewer States than IHL treaties, and that soft-law instruments play a major role in the growth and implementation of IEL. Those objections must not, however, be overemphasized. They do not concern the interpretation of IEL in light of IHL under the application process: first, States parties to the IEL treaty are typically also parties to the IHL treaty, and, second, the IHL interpretative standard is normally a legal norm.
That being said, even when concerning the interpretation of IHL by IEL under the interpretation process, these objections may be mitigated. Regarding the condition of the identity of the parties, it must first be observed that certain IEL treaties, like the Biodiversity Convention, the World Heritage Convention and the Ramsar Convention, are nearly universally ratified; in fact, some have more ratifications than certain IHL conventions, including the two Additional Protocols to the 1949 Geneva Conventions. Second, norms provided in an IEL treaty may be used to interpret any IHL rule, even though that treaty is ratified by a small number of States, providing that the IEL interpretative norm also has a customary nature or that the interpretation of IHL based on the IEL treaty is at least tolerated or accepted by the States not party to it.Footnote 100
Moreover, it is not uncommon that States party to an armed conflict, although bound by the same IHL rules according to the principle of equality between belligerents, will have a different interpretation of those rules. That practice could provide an alternative as well: an interpretation of IHL based on IEL could only be binding upon the States party to the interpretative IEL treaty. Although sound at the theoretical level, such an approach risks being unworkable on the ground. It would lead to a fragmentation of the meanings of the IHL rules, depending upon which IEL treaties have been ratified by the belligerents. Ultimately, if the requirement of the identity of the parties cannot be fulfilled even when mitigated, the interpretation of the IHL norm could be based upon the environmental considerations underlying the interpretative IEL treaty, providing that those considerations are based upon recognized scientific knowledge.
Regarding the requirement that the interpretative standard must be a rule of law, first, practice shows cases in which soft-law environmental instruments, such as Agenda 21,Footnote 101 have been relied upon among the materials used for the interpretation of a treaty in accordance with the principle of systemic integration.Footnote 102 Second, no problem arises when the norm or principle whose legal status is controversial is expressly provided in a treaty, such as the precautionary principle contained in the 2000 Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety to the Biodiversity Convention.Footnote 103 Again, alternatively, environmental considerations could be used as a last resort to inform the IHL norm or concept. In any case, while the principle of systemic integration can validly be used to guide the incorporation of IEL into IHL under the interpretation process, caution is required when proceeding to such an incorporation.
The lex specialis principle
Although often mentioned in legal literatureFootnote 104 and by StatesFootnote 105 in relation to IHL–IEL interplay, the lex specialis principle is subject to strong criticisms by the few scholars who have devoted an in-depth analysis to the topic.Footnote 106 They first emphasize that the lex specialis principle can only act as a mechanism for solving conflicts between IHL and IEL in circumstances where both fields of law apply but provide different results.Footnote 107 Admittedly, the lex specialis principle is better suited than the principle of systemic integration in that respect, since, as demonstrated above, the principle of systemic integration is not a tool for settling conflicts of norms.
However, the lex specialis principle can also arguably act as an interpretative tool for guiding the interpretation of IEL in light of IHL under the application process. Such a role is clearly acknowledged in relation to IHL–IHRL interplay: there is indeed an abundant and uniform practice confirming that the lex specialis principle may be used to settle conflicts of interpretation that may arise between IHL and IHRL, and that its effect is to prioritize the interpretation based on the special regulation.Footnote 108 It is therefore argued that, even though the lex specialis principle has traditionally been seen as a rule of norm conflict resolution, together with the lex superior and lex posterior principles,Footnote 109 such meaning has evolved overtime. In light of contemporary practice, the lex specialis principle is now also recognized, in accordance with numerous scholarsFootnote 110 and the ILC,Footnote 111 as a tool for solving conflicts of interpretation in order to avoid conflicts of norms between two bodies of law.
In fact, the principle of lex specialis seems better suited than the principle of systemic integration in the context of the application process, since its role is precisely to offer a solution by prioritizing the special rule in order to settle a conflict, whether of norms or interpretation. On the other hand, the principle of systemic integration appears to be better suited than the principle of lex specialis to act as a tool for guiding the incorporation of IEL into IHL under the interpretation process. That process does not involve solving any conflict of norms or interpretation. It merely consists in interpreting or clarifying an unclear or undefined concept against a general legal background, which is the function classically assigned to the principle of systemic integration.Footnote 112 The traditional rationale underlying that principle is that a legal concept or norm must be read in light of its surrounding legal context in order to safeguard the coherency of the international legal system as a whole.
That being said, even when admitting that the lex specialis principle can act as a tool for solving conflicts of norms, some scholars nonetheless emphasize that this principle is meaningless. They argue that it lacks any normative content that would allow the identification of which rule is special and must be prioritized.Footnote 113 However, the fact that the lex specialis principle is a mere formal tool does not mean that it should be overlooked. Its function is not to provide normative content, but rather to indicate that, in case of conflict, one norm or interpretation must displace the other. There is therefore no reason to set the principle aside – instead, it must be supplemented by a test, based on substantial considerations, which allows for determining the rule or interpretation that must take precedence over the other one in a particular case. The same is actually true with respect to the principle of systemic integration since, as a formal mechanism, it does not provide any normative indication on which rule is “relevant” and must be taken into account to interpret another rule or concept. As developed below, this might be resolved by adopting a coherency-based approach.
Other mechanisms?
The principle of systemic integration and the lex specialis principle are not the only mechanisms mentioned in legal literature in relation to IHL–IEL interplay. Scholars also refer to other mechanisms with respect to the incorporation of IEL into IHL under the interpretation process; however, those mechanisms do not prove useful or reliable.
The first of such mechanisms, notably mentioned by the ILC Rapporteur on the Protection of the Environment in Relation to Armed Conflicts,Footnote 114 is the “evolutionary interpretation”, which means that a norm must be interpreted taking into account the legal or factual context existing when the norm is interpreted rather than when it emerged. This seems particularly appropriate for the interpretation of IHL in light of IEL since most IHL treaties were drafted when commitment to the protection of the environment was not as significant as it is today and when IEL was non-existent or had just started emerging. However, the notion of “evolutionary interpretation” is a generic term, the purpose of which is merely to emphasize the type of interpretation that is sought, namely an evolutive interpretation. It is not an interpretative mechanism as such and it must therefore be based on true interpretative mechanisms. With respect to the incorporation of contemporary international law, and in particular IEL, into IHL, it seems that an evolutionary interpretation may be achieved through the principle of systemic integration. It is illustrative that several judicial decisions in which an evolutionary interpretation has been sought expressly or implicitly refer to the principle of systemic integration.Footnote 115
The second mechanism is the “ordinary meaning”, as provided under Article 31(1) of the VCLT.Footnote 116 Unlike the preparatory works of that article, case law suggests that the ordinary meaning of a term might include not only its everyday meaning but also its meaning derived from international law, including treaties.Footnote 117 This means that an IHL term could be informed by IEL treaties on the basis of the ordinary meaning of that term. However, when courts rely on international law to clarify the ordinary meaning of a term, they usually seek the meaning that is commonly shared under that law.Footnote 118 This actually amounts to identifying the customary meaning, but it comes close to interpreting a term based on the principle of systemic integration, which, as already seen, involves the interpretation of a term or norm against the general legal background. In that sense, the ordinary meaning would not allow interpretations that are not permitted under the principle of systemic integration, such as interpreting the IHL concept of the “natural environment” in light of a definition provided by a particular IEL instrument.Footnote 119 Moreover, unlike the principle of systemic integration, the ordinary meaning is not specific to interpretations based on the law but also serves interpretations based on various elements, including dictionaries or technical manuals.Footnote 120
A third mechanism is the Martens Clause, as provided in several IHL treaties and in customary law.Footnote 121 While the “greening” of that clause seems now well established, meaning that the clause also applies to the protection of the environment,Footnote 122 it is argued in legal literature that this clause can act as a legal mechanism for the interpretation of IHL in light of IEL.Footnote 123 One proposed example is the interpretation of the IHL principle of precaution in light of the IEL principle of prevention.Footnote 124 However, such an outcome may again be achieved through the normal operation of the principle of systemic integration. Moreover, it seems preferable to rely on that classical mechanism, the use of which is well known in practice, rather than on a clause the legal effects of which are still uncertain and debated.Footnote 125
The last mechanism is based on general principles of international law. Although the definition of such principles remains debated, the functions ascribed to them vary and include serving as a guidance for interpretation processes.Footnote 126 However, the general principles envisaged in legal literature to guide the interpretation of IHL in light of IEL merely consist in IEL principles, such as the precautionary principle, the incorporation of which into IHL is sought.Footnote 127 Yet, principles cannot at the same time be incorporated into a norm and guide such an incorporation process. The problem is that the mobilized principles are part of the IEL primary norms or at least have a specific normative-like nature when not expressly provided in treaties. Instead, principles designed to guide the interpretation of a rule of a legal system must be all-encompassing. They must constitute the underlying rationale for the whole of that system and hold all its rules together in a meaningful way. As detailed below, such an approach is possible with respect to IHL–IEL interplay, if both bodies of law are considered as being part of one common legal system and the coherency of that system is ensured by a foundational principle.
Going beyond the formal mechanisms
The two recent comprehensive studies on the interplay between IHL and IEL have emphasized the shortcomings of the lex specialis principle and the principle of systemic integration.Footnote 128 Each of them therefore proposes an approach, namely the “reconciliatory approach”Footnote 129 and the “multi-layered approach”,Footnote 130 that goes beyond these above-mentioned mechanisms. This section will accordingly examine these two approaches – however, it will be shown that such approaches themselves raise certain difficulties. A third approach, based on the notion of normative coherency of legal systems, will therefore be proposed.
The reconciliatory approach
Under the reconciliatory approach, which has been developed by Sjöstedt, reconciliation is sought between multilateral environmental agreements (MEAs) and IHL. Such reconciliation is mainly based on the broad mandate and non-confrontational character of the bodies established by MEAs, as well as on the flexible terms of the provisions enshrined in these agreements.Footnote 131 It is argued that those treaty bodies are then able to take diverse measures adapted to the concrete realities of war and therefore to enhance the protection of the environment in armed conflict. This approach is presented as going beyond the traditional mechanisms designed to solve normative tensions between IHL and IEL because those mechanisms are considered as inapplicable in such cases.
The reconciliatory approach nonetheless admits that the principle of systemic integration might constitute one of the available means when IHL is interpreted in light of IEL.Footnote 132 As emphasized above, however, the operation of that principle raises much more concern in that case than in the case where IEL is interpreted in light of IHL to solve normative tensions when both bodies of law are applicable. Moreover, while giving a key reconciliatory role to treaty bodies, the approach seems to overestimate the power of those bodies by contending that they “can overlook the limitations of the interpretation tools because they are empowered to perform tasks beyond treaty interpretation in their application of the MEA provisions”.Footnote 133 In fact, any treaty body is normally bound to apply the relevant mechanisms provided under general international law to settle normative tensions between the different branches of that law. This is clearly confirmed by the practice of the various treaty bodies supervising the application of IHRL treaties,Footnote 134 or the World Trade Organization (WTO) Agreements.Footnote 135 When faced with interplay between branches of international law, including IEL, those treaty bodies use the relevant formal mechanisms, such as the lex specialis principle or the principle of systemic integration.
More fundamentally, it is questionable whether the true purpose of the reconciliatory approach is to serve as a theoretical guiding tool for the interplay between IEL and IHL. Its purpose seems rather to refute the view recurrently upheld in legal scholarshipFootnote 136 that the open-ended and malleable nature of the MEA provisions renders those agreements unhelpful for regulating conduct in armed conflict and strengthening the protection of the environment in such situations. Under the reconciliatory approach, such flexibility, combined with the broad mandate of the treaty bodies, is instead considered as crucial in reconciling IEL with armed conflict and then in allowing IEL to play a critical role in complementing IHL with respect to the protection of the environment in warfare.
The three illustrative cases of normative tensions against which the reconciliatory approach is tested seem to confirm that such an approach is not actually designed to provide a theoretical framework to deal with the interplay between IHL and IEL. The first case involves a conflict of norms between the IHL permission to cause damage to the environment and the absolute prohibition against causing such damage provided in the World Heritage Convention. It is acknowledged that requiring a belligerent to refrain from launching an attack causing such damage “would only restrict the application of the law of armed conflict while the World Heritage Convention applies fully” and that reconciliation might not be possible in that case.Footnote 137 The two other cases, which actually involve conflicts of interpretation, are solved through the use of IHL as an interpretative standard for the interpretation of the relevant IEL open-ended treaty obligation, such as the obligation to make a “wise use of wetlands in their territory” provided in the Ramsar Convention.Footnote 138 Such a process is not explained under the reconciliatory approach, however, and no interpretative tool is mentioned.Footnote 139
The multi-layered approach
The multi-layered approach, which has been proposed by Dienelt (and which also considers the interactions of IHL and IEL with IHRL), starts from the observation that the “differences, parallels, and similarities” between IHL and IEL show “general compatibility” between these bodies of law.Footnote 140 Under this approach, a distinction must be made between the “clarifying function” of IEL with respect to IHLFootnote 141 and the “normative intensification” of IHL through IEL.Footnote 142 The first function is illustrated by the interpretation of the IHL concept of the “natural environment” in light of IEL,Footnote 143 and the second function by the concurrent application of the IHL and IEL regimes to the issue of protected sites and areas. Cases of conflicts of norms are discussed in relation to that second function.Footnote 144
The clarifying function is mainly based on a traditional mechanism, namely the principle of systemic integration.Footnote 145 By contrast, the normative intensification is operated in light of the “commonly shared objectives” across IHL and IEL, which arguably form together (also with IHRL) a “unifying ordre public transnational”.Footnote 146 Under this approach, the “parallel prioritization of the environment” that can be inferred from the respective regulation of the protected sites and areas under the different regimes “represents the unifying ordre public transnational”.Footnote 147 The proposal for this ordre public is built upon legal theories, elaborated by scholarsFootnote 148 such as Anne Peters,Footnote 149 Alexander ProelβFootnote 150 and Gunther Teubner,Footnote 151 that all “focus on shared objectives and unifying public interests”.Footnote 152 Such a proposal purports to go beyond the formal mechanisms in the sense that such mechanisms, especially the principle of systemic integration, are considered as inappropriate.Footnote 153 The apparently claimed reason for excluding the application of the principle of systemic integration with respect to the normative intensification process is based on the view that the condition of the identity of the parties required by that principle would not be fulfilled. The argument put forward is that normative intensification concerns “[o]bligations requiring specific conduct”, involving that “the state parties to the [applicable IHL and IEL] conventions in question” must be strictly identical. By contrast, the condition of the identity of the parties would not prevent the application of the principle of systemic integration in relation to the clarifying function. It is indeed claimed that this function concerns “[u]ndefined or unclear and ambiguous terminology of norms”, the clarification of which would be possible in light of other treaties “irrespective of states parties”, providing that “the treaties enjoy universal or quasi-universal membership and hence represent a common understanding of the term and [that] they address similar objects or the same situation”.Footnote 154
Yet, such reasoning is questionable. First, it is dubious that the condition of the identity of the parties required by the principle of systemic integration may vary depending upon whether the principle aims at interpreting an “unclear norm” or an “obligation requiring a specific conduct”. Second, it might be difficult to make such a distinction, since certain unclear terms are key elements of obligations of conduct, such as the term “precaution” as part of the IHL-specific obligation of conduct to take precautions. More generally, it seems that the operation of the principle of systemic integration must be excluded with respect to the normative intensification process not because of a required stricter application of the condition of the identity of the parties for that process, but because such a process does not raise any issue of interpretation and involves instead conflicts of norms. It is clear, as emphasized above, that the principle of systemic interpretation is helpless in this respect. This is apparent in the case of co-application of IHL and IEL regulation on protected areas and sites, which is presented as an illustrative case of the normative intensification process and in relation to which conflicts between the relevant IHL and IEL norms are discussed.Footnote 155
More fundamentally, by identifying the “parallel prioritization of the environment” as a shared objective between IHL and IEL (as well as IHRL) and as “represent[ing] the unifying ordre public transnational”,Footnote 156 the multi-layered approach tends to give prevalence to IEL over IHL with respect to the protection of certain areas and sites. It considers those areas and sites as immune to any attack even if IHL permits causing damage to them. Yet, this overlooks a specific feature that is common to IHL and IEL in such cases, namely that they are intended to regulate conduct in armed conflict and not in times of peace. The claimed “unifying ordre public transnational”, which notably gathers IHL and IEL together, ignores this common specific feature and the need, as detailed below, to counterbalance the prioritization of the environment, which is actually a shared peacetime objective, against considerations specific to armed conflict. Actually, the multi-layered approach has trouble entirely dispensing with such considerations. While claiming that the protected areas and sites remain immune to any attack, that view is immediately mitigated by conceding that this immunity remains “as long as a belligerent party does not systematically take advantage of the privileged protection of protected sites, zones and areas in order to achieve a military advantage”.Footnote 157 That being said, under this view, the transformation of the area or site into a military objective is made dependent upon a stricter condition than that normally required under IHL and incidental damage does not seem to be permitted, although lawful under IHL to the extent that it is not excessive.
The coherency-based approach
Unlike the reconciliatory and multi-layered approaches, the proposed “coherency-based approach” goes beyond the formal mechanisms to the extent that their application must be guided by substantial considerations. The coherency-based approach is thus all-encompassing. It serves as a theoretical framework for both the interpretation process, by guiding the incorporation of IEL into IHL, and the application process, by guiding the resolution of conflicts of norms and interpretation, as well as the mere application of IEL in armed conflict alongside IHL even when no interplay arises between these bodies of law.
This alternative approach starts from the key idea that the interplay between IHL and other bodies of law (directly or indirectly) regulating armed conflicts, such as IEL, is a matter of coherence.Footnote 158 Although the reconciliatory approach also emphasizes the need for legal coherence,Footnote 159 the coherency-based approach provides this idea with a conceptual framework based on legal theories on normative coherence of legal systems,Footnote 160 as further enriched by reflections on legal pluralism.Footnote 161 As detailed elsewhere,Footnote 162 according to those theories, a legal system must not be merely consistent, which means that no conflict exists between its norms, but it must further be coherent, in the sense that its norms must make sense when taken together. Consistency of a legal system is achieved by resorting (if needed) to formal mechanisms of displacement or interpretation, such as the lex specialis principle and the principle of systemic integration, while coherency further requires that the ensuing legal solutions must be compatible with substantial considerations, driven by the foundational principle of that system.
It is argued that a common regulation specific to armed conflict may be envisaged as amounting to such a system. That regulation would stem from the combination of IHL with norms of other branches of international law that also (directly or indirectly) regulate conduct in armed conflict, including IEL. It should then be as coherent as any legal system, and its coherency should be ensured by its foundational principle that serves as guidance for the operation of the formal mechanisms. It is submitted that the foundational principle of a common regulation specific to armed conflict is composed of two prongs. The first prong stems from the clear will expressed by States in numerous general declarations to further protect the environment in armed conflict. This means that IEL must be fully incorporated into IHL, through the interpretation process, and fully applied in armed conflict, through the application process. However, since that common regulation is specific to armed conflict, the first prong must be counterbalanced by a second prong, which is based on what fundamentally distinguishes a peacetime from a wartime regulation, namely military necessity. Unlike the approach to a unifying order public transnational, the coherency-based approach therefore involves taking into account the realities of war in order to make efficient fighting possible and to avoid the common regulation being disregarded. Such effectiveness-based considerations may result either from concrete circumstances or from the structural features of armed conflicts.
As a result, the combination of the two prongs of the relevant “coherency test” for the determination of the regulation of armed conflict dictates that the outcomes of the full incorporation of IEL into IHL, through the interpretation process, or of the cumulative application of IHL and IEL, through the application process, must be adjusted, but only if, and to the extent that, they conflict with those effectiveness-based considerations. This might lead either to the modulation or to the displacement of the “inappropriate” regulation; however, in most cases (contrary to those relating to IHL–IHRL interplay),Footnote 163 this will not be needed. Under the interpretation process, the interpreted IHL norm, like the obligation of precaution, may consist in an obligation of means and can then easily be interpreted in light of IEL, as including, for example, the demanding IEL requirement of an environmental impact assessment. On the other hand, the interpretative IEL norm, such as the principle of sustainable use, may be expressed in a sufficiently flexible way to serve as an appropriate standard for the interpretation of the IHL rule on usufruct in situations of occupation. Under the application process, the applicable IEL norm, like the obligation to take measures “as far as appropriate” to protect biodiversity,Footnote 164 may have an open-ended nature, which allows it to accommodate the realities of war.
Modulations or displacements are needed only in certain cases, such as in cases of conflicts of norms or interpretation under the application process. It may be argued that, given the specific circumstances of the case,Footnote 165 the IHL regime is the lex specialis and must be given prevalence over the IEL one, such as in the case of the targeting by a State of an adversary that uses a site protected under the Ramsar Convention for military purposes. The obligation for that State to make “wise use” of such a site should then be interpreted in light of the IHL regime as not preventing that State from causing incidental damage to the site.
However, it must not be forgotten that, albeit distinct from the application process, the interpretation process might apply to the same conduct even though it impacts different norms. Indeed, such targeting must comply with other IHL norms, like the principles of proportionality and precaution. Those principles should be informed by IEL and great constraints then put on the targeting State with respect to the protection of the site. This would result in a combination of the application and interpretation processes in relation to the same conduct, which allows the taking into account of the realities of war while at the same time strengthening the protection of the environment.Footnote 166
Conclusion
It is striking to observe a growing legal scholarship on the interplay between IHL and IEL. This is a fortunate evolution since it is well known that the environment needs further protection in armed conflict and that such protection could be achieved through IEL, which might fill the gaps left by IHL in that matter. The two main processes whereby IEL may play its gap-filling role are now well identified, namely in the interpretation of IHL in light of IEL and in the application of IEL alongside IHL. As they do not involve any modification of IHL, those processes have the advantage of accommodating States’ view that IEL may be used to enhance the protection of the environment in warfare providing that IHL is not modified.Footnote 167 However, legal literature on the topic is confusing and lacks systematicity. The interpretation process is often confused with the interpretation of IHL in light of environmental considerations rather than IEL; moreover, it is not clearly distinguished from the application process. The effects of those processes and the conditions for their application are, however, fundamentally different. The interpretation process means the incorporation of an IEL norm into IHL and therefore implies that such a norm applies to conduct to which it would not necessarily apply according to its own scope of application. By contrast, the application process involves interplay between IEL and IHL norms only when the respective scopes of application of those norms overlap. Legal scholarship fails to delve, in that regard, into the geographical and personal scopes of application of IEL, especially its extraterritorial application and its application to armed groups. Finally, the different types of conflicts are not distinguished, namely conflicts of norms and conflicts of interpretation.
The legal mechanisms mentioned in relation to IHL–IEL interplay also lack in-depth study, which contrasts with the significant literature on such mechanisms with respect to IHL–IHRL interplay. It has been argued, in accordance with the few studies on the matter, that the principle of systemic integration is the best-suited mechanism with respect to the interpretation process. Since it mobilizes international law, rather than environmental considerations, to interpret IHL, the principle must nonetheless be applied cautiously and its application must respect specific conditions, such as the identity of the parties bound by the interpreted and interpretative norms. On the other hand, contrary to the few studies on the subject, it has been submitted that the lex specialis principle is best suited for solving conflicts arising under the application process, be they conflicts of norms or of interpretation.
Finally, only two comprehensive approaches have been proposed so far in legal literature in relation to IEL–IHL interplay (with one also including IHRL). They share one fundamental common feature, namely that the application of the formal mechanisms is excluded with respect to the co-application of IHL and IEL, whereas the principle of systemic integration is nonetheless considered as applicable with respect to the interpretation of IHL in light of IEL. This has led the two approaches to propose a solution going beyond those formal mechanisms in relation to the application process. One of them, the reconciliatory approach, draws its solution from the vagueness of IEL and the flexibility of the mandate of the IEL treaty bodies, which enables the finding of solutions adapted to armed conflicts and, more generally, to any concrete situation. The other one, the multi-layered approach, infers from the parallel shared objectives of IHL and IEL (as well as IHRL) a unifying ordre public transnational, which serves as guidance in case of conflicts of norms. A coherency-based approach has been proposed as an alternative, mainly built upon legal theories on normative coherence of legal systems and applying those theories to the claimed legal system formed by all of the norms of international law regulating armed conflict, such as those of IHL and IEL. This approach construes the system as being coherent in the sense given to that term by those theories. This involves going beyond the mere consistency of that system, mainly through the operation of formal mechanisms that enables the avoiding of any conflict between its norms, and achieving its coherency through the guiding role played by a foundational principle that takes into account the realities of war.