Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T07:36:26.183Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Humanity: What is it and how does it influence international law?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 April 2010

Résumé

Pour I'auteur, le principe de l'humanité inclut la possibilité et la volonté de réduire la capacité de se livrer à la violence armée et d'en limiter les effets sur la sécurité et la santé. L'humanité ainsi interprétée englobe l'humanitarisme, la moralité, le développement, les droits de l'homme et la sécurité humaine. À ce titre, elle est une des principales sources du droit international en général et du droit international humanitaire en particulier. Dans cet article, l'auteur décrit les conséquences du lien étroit qui existe entre humanité et droit international.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © International Committee of the Red Cross 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 The “laws of humanity” are referred to in the St Petersburg Declaration of 1868, and in what is now known as the Martens Clause derived from the preamble to Convention (IV) respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land, adopted by the 1907 International Peace Conference at The Hague. Legal recognition of crimes against humanity originated in the jurisprudence of the Nuremberg Tribunal; such acts also constitute a category of crime in the 1998 Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court. – Brownlie states that humanity is a source of international law. He cites as a classic reference the judgment in the Corfu Channel case (I.C.J. Reports 1949, p. 22): the court relied on certain “general and well recognised principles”, including “elementary considerations of humanity, even more exacting in peace than in war”. Brownlie, I., Principles of Public International Law, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1998, p. 28.Google Scholar

2 See generally Diamond, J., Guns, Germs and Steel: a Short History of Everybody for the Last 13,000 Years, Vintage, London, 1998Google Scholar; The Economist, Special Millennium Edition, 31 December 1999, pp. 10–14; Ehrenreich, B., Blood Rites, Metropolitan Books, New York, 1998, pp. 175193.Google Scholar

3 Keegan, J., A History of Warfare, Pimlico, London, 1993, pp. 386392.Google ScholarPubMed

4 Chapter I of the UN Charter. See also Boutros-Ghali, B., “The United Nations at fifty”, Melbourne University Law Review, vol. 20, 1995, pp. 913Google Scholar. Farer, T., “International Law: The Critics are Wrong”, Foreign Policy, 1988, pp. 2245.Google Scholar

5 Op. cit. (note 3).

6 The definition of violence adopted by the World Health Organization is: “[T]he intentional use of physical force or power, threatened or actual, against oneself, another person, or against a group or community, that either results in or has a likelihood to result in injury, death, psychological harm, maldevelopment or deprivation.” From Koplan, J. et al. Violence Prevention: A Public Health Policy, Atlanta, Centers for Disease Control, 1998Google Scholar. See also Coupland, R., “Armed violence”, Medicine and Global Survival, vol. 7, 2001, pp. 3337.Google Scholar

7 Oxford English Dictionary, 2nd ed., Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1989.Google ScholarPubMed

8 Pictet, J., Red Cross Principles, ICRC, Geneva, 1956, pp. 1431.Google Scholar

9 Durand, A., The International Committee of the Red Cross, ICRC, Geneva, 1981, p. 54.Google Scholar

10 Pictet, J., Development and Principles of International Humanitarian Law, Martinus Nijhoff/Henry Dunant Institute, Dordrecht, 1983, p. 5.Google Scholar

11 In the 1868 St Petersburg Declaration, the use of explosive projectiles of less than 400g in weight is deemed to be contrary to the “progress of civilization” and the “laws of humanity” because they would “uselessly aggravate the sufferings of disabled men, or render their death inevitable”.

12 Lauren, P., The Evolution of Human Rights, University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, 1998, pp. 436Google Scholar. See also Abou, Selim, “Natural and philoso phical foundations of ethics”, Diogenes, vol. 43, 1995, pp. 3554.Google Scholar

13 Kingsbury, B./Roberts, A., “Introduction: Grotian thought in international relations”, in Bull, H./Kingsbury, B./Roberts, A. (eds), Hugo Grotius and International Relations, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1990, pp. 164.Google Scholar

14 Quoted in Greenwood, C., in Fleck, D. (ed.), The Handbook of Humanitarian Law in Armed Conflicts, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1995, para. 112.Google Scholar

15 1907 Hague Convention (IV) respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land, preambular paragraph.

16 Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (Protocol I), 8 June 1977.

17 Art. 1(2) of Protocol I reads: “In cases not covered by this Protocol or by other international agreements, civilians and combatants remain under the protection and authority of the principles of international law derived from established custom, from the principles of humanity and from the dictates of public conscience.”

18 Ticehurst, R., “The Martens Clause and the Laws of Armed Conflict”, IRRC, No. 317, March-April 1997, pp. 125134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 Commission on the Responsibility of the Authors of the War and on Enforcement of Penalties, Report Presented to the Prelimi nary Peace Conference, 29 March 1919, reprinted in AJIL, 1920, No. 95, p. 115.

20 Op. cit. (note 18), p. 144.

21 Separate Opinion of President Nagendra Singh, Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. the United States of America), Merits, I.C.J. Reports 1986, pp. 143 and 146 respectively.

22 Statute of the International Criminal Court, Art. 5.

23 The obvious exception is the crimes cited in Art. 7(1)(g): rape, sexual slavery, enforced prostitution, forced pregnancy, enforced sterilization, or any other form of sexual violence of comparable gravity. Whilst this category of crime could clearly be committed without weapons, the power differential required to commit them is given by weapons and also by the difference in physical build between most men and women.

24 Robertson, G., Crimes against Humanity: the Struggle for Global Justice. Ringwood, Penguin Books Australia, 2000, p. 239.Google Scholar

25 Blondel, J. L., “The meaning of the word “humanitarian” in relation to the Fundamental Principles of the Red Cross and Red Crescent, IRRC, No. 273, November-December 1989, pp. 507515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

26 Gilbert, A., Betting on the Better Angels, The Inaugural Henry Dunant Lecture, Australian Red Cross, Melbourne, 1999.Google Scholar

27 “The quality of being inhuman or inhumane; want of human feeling and compassion; brutality, barbarous cruelty”, op. cit. (note 7).

28 Glover, J.. Humanity: A Moral History of the Twentieth Century, Jonathan, Cape, London, 1999, pp. 411413.Google Scholar

29 Op. cit. (notes 17, 25, 26 and 28, respectively).

30 Coupland, op. cit. (note 6).

31 The definition of health as given in the World Health Organization's mission statement is: “A state of complete physical, mental and social well-being and not merely the absence of disease or infirmity.” WHO website.

32 Jackson, R., The Global Covenant: Human Conduct in a World of States, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2000, pp. 185215.Google Scholar

33 See note 31. The definition of security is “the state of being or feeling secure”, and of secure: “certain to remain safe and unthreat- preened; protected against attack or other criminal activity; feeling free from fear and anxiety”, op. cit. (note 7).

34 Perrin, P., “War and public health: Extending the concept of public health for the victims of armed conflict”, Editorial, Health in Emergencies, issue 3, WHO, Geneva, 1998, p. 1.Google ScholarPubMed

35 Meddings, D., “Human security as a preened; requisite for health”, British Medical journal, vol. 322, 2001, p. 1553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

36 Hobbes, T., Leviathan, Ed. Tuck, R., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1996, p. 89.Google Scholar

37 Locke, J., Second Treatise of Government: Of the Beginning of Political Societies (1690), Blackwell, Oxford, 1976, p. 49.Google Scholar

38 Ibid., p. 6.

39 See note 31.

40 UN Charter, Art. 2(7).

41 UN Charter, Art. 1(1).

42 UN Charter, Art. 40.

43 See Teson, F., “Collective humanitarian intervention”, Michigan journal of International Law, vol. 17, 1996, pp. 323371Google Scholar; Glennon, M., “The new interventionism”, Foreign Affairs, 1999, pp. 27Google Scholar. Simma, B., “NATO, the UN and the use of force: Legal aspects”, EJIL, 1999, vol. 10, pp. 122Google Scholar; Chomsky, N., The New Military Humanism: Lessons Learnt from Kosovo, Pluto Press, London, 1999.Google Scholar

44 Human Development Report, UNDP, New York, 1994, pp. 22–40.

45 This is a reference to Franklin D. Roosevelt's “Fundamental Freedoms” speech of 1941. The four freedoms are: freedom from fear, freedom from want, freedom of speech and freedom of worship.

46 Commission on Global Governance, Our Global Neighbourhood, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1995.Google ScholarPubMed

47 Human Security: Safety for People in a Changing World, Department of Foreign Affairs and International Trade, Ottawa, April 1999.

48 The right to health arises from Art. 25 of the 1948 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Art. 12 of the International Covenant of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, Art. 12 of the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women, and Art. 24 of the Convention on the Rights of the Child.

49 Coupland, op. cit. (note 6).

50 Grossman, D., On Killing: The Psychological Cost of Learning to Kill in War and Society, Little Brown, Boston, 1995, pp. 516.Google Scholar

51 Plotkin, H., Evolution in Mind: An Introduction to Evolutionary Psychology, Penguin, London, 1997Google Scholar. See also Trivers, R., “The evolution of reciprocal altruism”, Quarterly Review of Biology, vol. 46, 1971, pp. 3557.Google Scholar

52 D'Amato, A., “Trashing customary international law”, AJIL, vol. 81, 1987, pp. 101105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

53 Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. the United States of America), Merits, Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 1986, paras. 187 to 201.

54 UN Charter, Arts 1(1) and (2), and Art. 51.

55 Examples are the 1968 Nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty, the 1972 Biological Weapons Convention and the 1993 Chemical Weapons Convention.

56 Matthews, R./McCormack, T., “The relationship between international humanitarian law and arms control.”, in Durham, H./McCormack, T. (eds), The Changing Face of Conflict and the Efficacy of International Humanitarian Law, Kluwer, The Hague, 1999, pp. 6598.Google Scholar

57 Matthews, R.,/McCormack, T., “The influence of humanitarian principles in the negotiation of arms control treaties”, IRRC, No. 834, June 1999, pp. 331352.Google Scholar

58 Art. 1(3) of the UN Charter addresses States' obligations to uphold human rights. The 1948 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the 1976 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and the 1976 International Covenant on Economic, Social personand Cultural Rights together are seen as an international bill of rights from which have flowed other human rights instruments.

59 The principle treaties of international humanitarian law are the 1949 Geneva Conventions for the protection of war victims and the 1977 Additional Protocols thereto. Some other treaties are considered part of international humanitarian law, such as the 1980 UN Convention on Conventional Weapons and the 1997 Ottawa Anti-personnel Mines Treaty.

60 Op. cit. (note 28), p. 410. P. Alston, “The myopia of handmaidens: International lawyers and globalization”, EJIL, vol. 3, 1997, pp. 435–448.

61 To coincide with the 50th anniversary of the 1949 Geneva Conventions, the British Medical Journal published a special theme issue on 14 August 1999 entitled “Medicine and international law.” It examined the role of health professionals in the upholding of human rights and international humanitarian law.

62 Slim, H., “Sharing a Universal Ethic: the Principle of Humanity in War”, International Journal of Human Rights, vol. 2, 1998, pp. 2848.CrossRefGoogle Scholar