Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T19:14:23.032Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Understanding Others in an Alienating World: Comments on Lori Gruen's Entangled Empathy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Abstract

Is moral theory alienating? This question, and the worries that lie behind it, motivate much of Lori Gruen's distinctive approach to animal ethics in Entangled Empathy. According to Gruen, the “traditional” methods of moral theory rely on abstractions that strip away the details that give our lives meaning. Although I am deeply sympathetic to these worries, as well as to the alternative ethics Gruen proposes in response to them, in this article I express a few reservations about the argument Gruen uses to motivate her worries and to establish her solution. First, I raise some questions about her conception of “traditional” moral theory and the possible historical figures she means to indict. I then suggest that the principal gear of her argument—her conception of “entangled empathy”—suffers from some inconsistency in application, which risks leading her to posit a thicker notion of empathy than she should want. In particular, her argument risks setting a standard of correctness for “successful” empathy that is implausible on its own terms, but that is also a standard of correctness with morally and politically questionable implications in the human context.

Type
Symposium on Lori Gruen's Entangled Empathy: An Alternative Ethic for Our Relationships with Animals
Copyright
Copyright © 2017 by Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Debes, Remy. 2010. Which empathy? Limitations in the mirrored “understanding” of emotion. Synthese 175 (2): 219–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Debes, Remy. 2015. From Einfühlung to empathy: Sympathy in early phenomenology and psychology. In Sympathy: A history, ed. Schliesser, Eric. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Debes, Remy. Forthcoming. Understanding persons and the problem of power. In Making sense of the world: New essays in the philosophy of understanding, ed. Grimm, Stephen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 2006. Simulating minds. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gruen, Lori. 2015. Entangled empathy: An alternative ethic for our relationships with animals. Brooklyn, NY: Lantern Books.Google Scholar
Jenkins, Katharine. 2016. Amelioration and inclusion: Gender identity and the concept of Woman*. Ethics 126: 394421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Medina, José. 2013. The epistemology of resistance: Gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and resistant imaginations. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, Iris. 1970. The idea of perfection. In The sovereignty of the good. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sherman, Nancy. 1998. Empathy and imagination. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 22 (1): 82119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Adam. 1759/2001. The theory of moral sentiments. Edited by Raphael, D. D. and Mackie, A. L.Indianapolis, Ind.: Liberty Fund Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stueber, Karsten. 2014. Empathy. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Zalta, E. N.https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/empathy/ (accessed January 14, 2017).Google Scholar