Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T20:34:32.711Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mary Astell: Defender of the “Disembodied Mind”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2020

Abstract

This paper demonstrates how Mary Astell's version of Cartesian dualism supports her disavowal of female subordination and traditional gender roles, her rejection of Locke's notion of “thinking matter” as a major premise for rejecting his political philosophy of “social contracts” between men and women, and, finally, her claim that there is no intrinsic difference between genders in terms of ratiocination, the primary assertion that grants her the title of the first female English feminist.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1998 by Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arnauld, Antoine [1662] 1964. Port Royal logic: The art of thinking, trans. Dickoff, James and James, Patricia. Indianapolis: Bobbs‐Merrill.Google Scholar
Ashcraft, Richard 1986. Revolutionary politics and Locke's two treatises of government. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary [1694, 1697] 1970. A serious proposal to the ladies, Part 1. New York: Source Book Press.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary 1695. Letters concerning the love of God, between the author of the proposal to the ladies and Mr. John Norris. Bemerton nr. Sarum: J. Norris. Microfilm.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary [1697] 1970. A serious proposal to the ladies, Part I and Part II. New York: Source Book Press.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary 1704a. An impartial enquiry into the causes of rebellion and civil war in this kingdom. London: R. Wilkin. Microfilm.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary 1704b. Moderation truly stated. London: Richard Wilkin. Microfilm.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary 1705. The Christian religion, as profess'd by a daughter of the Church of England. London: R. Wilkin. Microfilm.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary 1706. Reflections upon marriage. The third edition. To which is added a preface, in answer to some objections. London: R. Wilkin. Microfilm.Google Scholar
Atherton, Margaret 1994. Women philosophers in the early modem period. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Bordo, Susan 1987. The flight to objectivity: Essays on Cartesianism and culture. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Browne, Alice 1987. The eighteenth century feminist mind. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.Google Scholar
Deluna, D.N. 1993. Mary Astell: England's first feminist literary critic. Women's Studies 22:231–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Descartes, Rene [1637] 1994. Discourse on the method. The philosophical writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, and Murdoch, Dugald. Volume I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary [1641] 1994. Meditations on first philosophy. The philosophical writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, and Murdoch, Dugald. Volume II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary [1644] 1994. Principles of philosophy. The philosophical writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, and Murdoch, Dugald. Volume I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Astell, Mary [1649] 1994. The passions of the soul. The philosophical writings of Descartes, trans. Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, and Murdoch, Dugald. Volume I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Elshtain, Jean B. 1981. Public man, private woman. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Harth, Erica 1992. Cartesian women: Versions and subversions of rational discourse in the old regime. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, Bridget, ed. 1986. The first English feminist. New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Hinton, R.W.K. 196768. Husbands, fathers, and conquerors. Parts 1 and 2. Political Studies 15 (3): 291300; 16 (1): 55‐67. The Ladies Religion. 1692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Genevive 1984. The man of reason: “Male” and “female” in Western philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John [1689] 1988. John Locke's two treatises of government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John [1693] 1968. Some thoughts concerning education. In The educational writings, ed. Axtell, James L.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John [1695a] 1975. An essay concerning human understanding, ed. Nidditch, Peter. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John 1695b. The reasonableness of Christianity. London . Microfilm.Google Scholar
Masham, Damaris 1696. The discourse concerning the love of God. London . Microfilm.Google Scholar
Locke, John 1705. Occasional thought in reference to a vertuous of Christian life. London . Microfilm.Google Scholar
Messenger, Ann 1986. His and hers: Essays in restoration and eighteenth century literature. Lexington: University Press of Kentucky.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Juliet 1984. Women: The longest revolution. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Norris, John [1697] 1968. An account of reason and faith: In relation to the mysteries of Christianity. In The Cambridge Platonists. ed. Craig, Gerald. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Norton, J.E. 1961. Some uncollected authors XXVII; Mary Astell. Book Collector 10(1): 5860.Google Scholar
O'Donnell, Sheryl 1978. Mr. Locke and the ladies. Studies in Eighteenth Century Culture 8: 151–64.Google Scholar
Locke, John 1984. My idea in your mind: John Locke and Damaris Cudworth Masham. In Mothering the mind, ed. Perry, Ruth and Brownley, Martine. New York: Holmes and Meier.Google Scholar
Pateman, Carole 1988. The sexual contract. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Locke, John 1989. God hath ordained to man a helper: Hobbes, patriarchy, and conjugal right. British Journal of Political Science 19: 445–64.Google Scholar
Perry, Ruth 1986. The celebrated Mary Astell: An early English feminist. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John 1990. Mary Astell and the feminist critique of possessive individuals. Eighteenth Century Studies 23: 447–57.Google Scholar
Rand, Benjamin, ed. 1927. The correspondences of John Locke and Edward Clark. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rogers, Katherine M., ed. 1979. Before their time. New York: Unger.Google Scholar
Locke, John 1982. Feminism in eighteenth century England. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Scaltsas, Patricia Ward. 1990. Women as ends—women as means in the Enlightenment. In Women's rights and the rights of man, ed. Arnaud, A. J. and Kingdom, E.Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.Google Scholar
Schouls, Peter A. 1989. Descartes and the Enlightenment. Kingston, Ont: McGill‐Queen's University Press.Google Scholar
Shanley, Mary Lyndon 1979. Marriage contract and social contract in seventeenth century English political thought. Western Political Quarterly 32: 7991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siskin, Charles 1994. Gender, sublimity, culture: Reauthorizing disciplinary desire. Eighteenth Century Studies 28: 3750.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Hilda L 1982. Reason's disciples. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Florence 1916. Mary Astell. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Springborg, Patricia 1995. Mary Astell (1666‐1731): Critic of Locke. American Political Science Review 89 (3): 621–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John 1996. Mary Astell (1666‐1731), political writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Squadrito, Kathleen M. 1987. Mary Astell's critique of Locke's view of thinking matter. Journal of the History of Philosophy 25:433–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stern, Karl 1965. The flight from woman. New York: Noonday.Google Scholar
Tuana, Nancy 1992. Women and the history of philosophy. New York: Paragon House.Google Scholar
Wilson, Margaret D. 1979. Superadded properties: The limits of mechanism in Locke. American Philosophical Quarterly 16:143150.Google Scholar