Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T17:26:01.089Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Importance of Disambiguating Adaptive States in Development Theory and Practice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Abstract

This article proposes a way to disambiguate the evaluative states currently identified as “adaptive preferences” in development literature. It provides a brief analysis of Serene Khader's Deliberative Perfectionist Approach, and demonstrates that distinguishing between adaptive states has important implications for the theory and practice of development intervention. Although I support Khader's general approach and consider my project to be complementary, I argue that the term preferences be replaced with four distinct terms: beliefs, choices, desires, and values. Distinguishing among adaptive states can serve to prevent inappropriate intervention and appreciate the costs of transforming inappropriate adaptations. I argue that adaptive values are especially problematic, given how central a person's values are to their sense of meaning and self. Attempts to transform adaptive values are likely to produce internal conflict, resulting in psychological distress and diminished agency. Furthermore, some values (referred to in moral psychology as sacred values) preclude deliberation and comparison given their communal status as infinitely valuable. To deliberate about sacred values is to violate them. The emotional and psychological damage that may result from value transformation is thus likely to be extensive, and must be taken into account when determining whether, and what type of, intervention is justified.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2017 by Hypatia, Inc.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anscombe, G. E. M. 2000. Intention, 2nd edition. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Baber, H. E. 2007. Adaptive preference. Social Theory and Practice 33 (1): 105–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Jonathan, and Leshner, Sarah. 2000. How serious are expressions of protected values? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 6 (3): 183–94.Google ScholarPubMed
Baron, Jonathan, and Spranca, Mark. 1997. Protected values. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 70 (1): 116.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Benson, Paul. 1991. Autonomy and oppressive socialization. Social Theory and Practice 17 (3): 385408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruckner, Donald. 2009. In defense of adaptive preferences. Philosophical Studies 142 (3): 307–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colburn, Ben. 2011. Autonomy and adaptive preferences. Utilitas 23 (1): 5271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1984. Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. 1987. The intentional stance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Elster, Jon. 1983. Sour grapes. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fiske, Alan, and Tetlock, Philip. 1997. Taboo trade‐offs. Political Psychology 18 (2): 255–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. 1981. Representations. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. 1990. A theory of content. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68 (1): 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginges, Jeremy, Atran, Scott, Medin, Douglas, and Shikaki, Khalil. 2007. Sacred bounds on rational resolution of violent political conflict. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 104: 7357–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gowans, Christopher. 1996. Moral theory, moral dilemmas, and moral responsibilities. In Moral dilemmas and moral theory, ed. Mason, H. E.New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Graham, Jesse, and Haidt, Jonathan. 2012. Sacred values and evil adversaries. In The Social Psychology of Morality, ed. Mikulincer, Mario and Shaver, Phillip R.Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.Google Scholar
Khader, Serene. 2011. Adaptive preferences and women's empowerment. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khader, Serene. 2012. Must theorizing about adaptive preferences deny women's agency? Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (4): 302–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khader, Serene. 2013. Identifying adaptive preferences in practice. Journal of Global Ethics 9 (3): 311–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khader, Serene. 2014. Empowerment through self‐subordination? In Poverty, agency, and human rights, ed. T Meyers, Diana. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mandel, David R., and Vartanian, Oshin. 2008. Taboo or tragic: Effect of tradeoff type on moral choice, conflict, and confidence. Mind and Society 7 (2): 215–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marcus, Ruth. 1990. Some revisionary proposals about belief and believing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50: 132–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Narayan, Uma. 2002. Minds of their own. In A mind of one's own, ed. Antony, Louise and Witt, Charlotte. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2000. Women and human development. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rachels, James. 1999. The challenge of cultural relativism. In The elements of moral philosophy, 3rd edition. New York: McGraw Hill, Inc.Google Scholar
Ritov, Ilana, and Baron, Jonathan. 1999. Protected values and omission bias. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 79 (2): 7994.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scanlon, T. 1998. What we owe each other. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1970. Collective choice and social welfare. San Francisco: Holden Day, Inc.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1993. Internal consistency of choice. Econometrica 61 (3): 495521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as freedom. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, Inc.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. 1907. The methods of ethics, 7th edition. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett.Google Scholar
Stoljar, Natalie. 2014. Autonomy and adaptive preference formation. In Autonomy, oppression, and gender, ed. Veltman, Andrea and Piper, Mark. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 1994. Mental reality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Superson, Anita. 2005. Deformed desires and informed desire tests. Hypatia 20 (4): 109–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tanner, Carmen, and Medin, Douglas. 2004. Protected values. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 11 (1): 185–91.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tessman, Lisa. 2015. Moral failure. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tetlock, Philip. 2003. Thinking the unthinkable. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7 (7): 320–24.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tetlock, Philip, Orie Kristel, S., Elson, Beth, and Green, Melanie. 2000. The psychology of the unthinkable. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 78 (5): 853–70.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Von Wright, Georg H. 1963. The logic of preference. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1973a. A critique of utilitarianism. In Utilitarianism, ed. Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, Bernard. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 1973b. Problems of the self. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yount, Kathryn. 2002. Like mother, like daughter? Journal of Health and Social Behavior 43 (September): 336–58.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed