Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T23:00:47.677Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bodily Integrity and Conceptions of Subjectivity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2020

Abstract

This paper examines two different ways of understanding the concept of bodily integrity and their political implications. In Drucilla Cornell's use of the concept, the body cannot be separated from the mind. Protecting bodily integrity means protecting possibilities of imagining the self as whole. Martha Nussbaum's theorizing is based on a liberal way of conceptualizing subjectivity, in which the mind and the body are separate, and bodily integrity is used to refer to physical inviolability.

Type
Original Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2009 by Mervi Patosalmi

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alcoff, Linda Martín. 2004. Book reviews: Just cause: Freedom, identity, and rights, by Drucilla Cornell. Hypatia 19 (3): 225–28.Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla. 1995. Subjectivity, historiography, and politics: Reflections on the “feminism/postmodernism exchange. In Feminist contentions: A philosophical exchange, Benhabib, Seyla, Butler, Judith, Cornell, Drucilla, and Fraser, Nancy. New York: Routledge, pp. 105125.Google Scholar
Bloodworth, Andrew. 2006. Nussbaum's “capabilities approach.” Nursing Philosophy 7:5860.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butler, Judith. 1995. For a careful reading. In Feminist contentions: A philosophical exchange, Benhabib, Seyla, Butler, Judith, Cornell, Drucilla, and Fraser, NancyRoutledge, pp. 127143.Google Scholar
Chambers, Clare. 2004. Are breast implants better than female genital mutilation? Autonomy, gender equality, and Nussbaum's political liberalism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 7 (4): 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornell, Drucilla. 1995. The imaginary domain: Abortion, pornography and sexual harassment. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Cornell, Drucilla. 1998. At the heart of freedom: Feminism, sex, and equality. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornell, Drucilla. 2002. Between women and generations: Legacies of dignity. New York: Palgrave.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornell, Drucilla. 2003. Autonomy re‐imagined. Journal for the Psychoanalysis of Culture and Society 8 (1): 144–49.Google Scholar
Cornell, Drucilla. 2004. Defending ideals: War, democracy, and political struggles. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornell, Drucilla. 2007. The shadow of heterosexuality. Hypatia 22 (1): 229–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Council of Europe. 1950. Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms as amended by Protocol No. 11. http://conventions.coe.int/treaty/en/Treaties/Html/005.htm (accessed March 21, 2007).Google Scholar
The Council of Europe. 1963. Protocol No. 4 to the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, securing certain rights and freedoms other than those already included in the Convention and in the first Protocol thereto as amended by Protocol No. 11.Google Scholar
Deveaux, Monique. 2002. Political morality and culture: What difference do differences make? Social Theory and Practice 28 (3): 503–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, Cécile, and Miller, David. 2003. Justice and culture: Rawls, Sen, Nussbaum and O'Neil. Political Studies Review 1:417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flax, Jane. 2001a. On encountering incommensurability: Martha Nussbaum's Aristotelian practice. In Controversies in feminism, ed. Sterba, James P.Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc, pp. 2546.Google Scholar
Flax, Jane. 2001b. A constructionist despite herself? On capacities and their discontents. In Controversies in feminism, ed. Sterba, James P.Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc, pp. 4757.Google Scholar
Fraser, Nancy. 1995. Pragmatism, feminism and the linguistic turn. In Feminist contentions: A philosophical exchange, Benhabib, Seyla, Butler, Judith, Cornell, Drucilla, and Fraser, Nancy. New York: Routledge, pp. 157171.Google Scholar
Grosz, Elizabeth. 1990. Jacques Lacan: A feminist introduction. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grosz, Elizabeth. 2005. Time travels: Feminism, nature, power. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, Susan. 2002. Freedom and the imaginary. In Visible women: Essays on feminist legal theory and political philosophy, ed. James, Susan and Palmer, Stephanie. Oxford: Hart Publishing, pp. 175195.Google Scholar
McNay, Lois. 2000. Gender and agency: Reconfiguring the subject in feminist and social theory. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.Google Scholar
McNay, Lois. 2003. Agency, anticipation and indeterminacy in feminist theory. Feminist Theory 4 (2): 139–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Naffine, Ngaire 2002. Can women be legal persons? In Visible women: Essays on feminist legal theory and political philosophy, ed. James, Susan and Palmer, Stephanie. Oxford: Hart Publishing, pp. 6990.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C. 1995. Human capabilities: Female human beings. In Women, culture and development: A study of human capabilities, ed. Nussbaum, Martha C. and Glover, Jonathan. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 61104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C. 1998. “Whether from reason or prejudice”: Taking money for bodily services. Journal of Legal Studies 27 (2)(part 2): 693724.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C. 2000. Women and human development: The capabilities approach. Cambridge, UK: The Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C. 2001. In defense of universal values. In Controversies in feminism, ed. Sterba, James P.Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc, pp. 323.Google Scholar
Pateman, Carole. 1988. The sexual contract. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Phillips, Anne. 2001. Review essay: Feminism and liberalism revisited: Has Martha Nussbaum got it right? Constellations 8 (2): 240–66.Google Scholar
Pulkkinen, Tuija 2000. The postmodern and political agency. Jyväskylä, Finland: SoPhi.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid. 2005. The capability approach: A theoretical survey. Journal of Human Development 6 (1): 93114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smyth, Lisa. 2002. Feminism and abortion politics: Choice, right, and reproductive freedom. Women's Studies International Forum 25 (3): 335–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The United Nations. 1948. Universal declarations of human rights. http://www.unhchr.ch/udhr/lang/eng.htm (accessed March 21, 2007).Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan. 1995. Martha C. Nussbaum: Human capabilities, female human beings. In Women, culture and development: A study of human capabilities, ed. Nussbaum, Martha C. and Glover, Jonathan. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 105115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar