Published online by Cambridge University Press: 24 February 2017
It is not, of course, for his work as a teacher in the Academy that Plato is remembered most in the history of education but rather for his Utopian plan for education, a plan which had a profound influence on the education of antiquity. This may explain why so little is known of the internal functioning of this famous school.
1. It would be unfair and unhistorical to attribute commercial motives as the principal ones dominating the schools of Aristotle and Isocrates, but it is impossible, especially in the case of Isocrates, to ignore the commercial dimension. This was criticism Isocrates himself had to contend with. See Antidosis, 3–5.Google Scholar
2. Jaeger, Werner, Aristoteles. Grundlegung einer Geschichte seiner Entwicklung (Berlin, 1923), 17–22.Google Scholar
3. On these points, see Marrou, H. I., A History of Education in Antiquity (New York, 1956), 67–8. See also the bibliographical notes, 373.Google Scholar
4. Freeman, Kenneth J., Schools of Hellas (New York, 1922), 230.Google Scholar
5. Epicrates, frg., 287, Kock.Google Scholar
6. Diogenes Laertius, Lives, III, 46; IV, 2.Google Scholar
7. Socrates' lack of interest in natural philosophy has been emphasized by Plato and Aristotle. See Jaeger, Paideia (Oxford, 1947), II, 31.Google Scholar
8. Plato, Laws, VII, 808d.Google Scholar
9. Power, Edward J., Main Currents in the History of Education, (New York, 1962), 59–60.Google Scholar
10. Plato, Republic, II, 376e; VII, 521de.Google Scholar
11. Plato, ibid., II, 377a; III, 392b; X 595a–608b; Laws, VII, 810c-811b.Google Scholar
12. Plato, Republic, III, 410c–412a.Google Scholar
13. Plato, Laws, VII, 794c; 802e; 813b.Google Scholar
14. Plato, Republic, V, 451d–457b; Laws, VII, 804d–805b; 813b.Google Scholar
15. Plato, Republic, II, 528b–530c.Google Scholar
16. From Plato's description of arithmetic we know how it was approached in traditional Greek education. See Republic, VII, 522c, and Laws, VII, 819c.Google Scholar
17. The most prominent was Eudoxes of Cnidus. See Diogenes Laertius, Lives, VIII, 87.Google Scholar
18. Plato, Republic, VII, 514a.Google Scholar
19. Aristotle, Physics, I, 191b.Google Scholar
20. See Power, op. cit., 70.Google Scholar
21. See Jaeger, Paideia, 107.Google Scholar
22. Ibid., 126.Google Scholar
23. For an examination of the relativism and nihilism of Protagorus and Gorgias, see Gomperz, H., Sophistik and Rhetorik (Berlin, 1912), 1–35.Google Scholar
24. Isocrates in Against the Sophists is really advertising his school and tells us how it will alter the conventional sophistic program of teaching.Google Scholar
25. This seems apparent from Isocrates' remarks in ibid., 9–11, and from Plato's general preference for scientific humanism.Google Scholar
26. Aristotle, De Partibus Animalium, I, 639a.Google Scholar
27. Euclid, Elements of Geometry, I, 5.Google Scholar
28. See Marrou, op. cit., 177–181.Google Scholar