Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T05:52:03.188Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The “Unhappy Consciousness” And Conscious Unhappiness: On Adorno's Critique Of Hegel And The Idea Of An Hegelian Critique Of Adorno

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 June 2015

Simon Jarvis*
Affiliation:
University of Newcastle-upon-Tyne
Get access

Abstract

In the early sections of The Difference Between Fichte's and Schelling's System of Philosophy, Hegel offered some advice on how not to write the history of philosophy. In the hands of the collector of philosophical opinions “philosophy is transposed to the plane of information. Information is concerned with alien objects”. But for Hegel a scarcely less inert relation to previous work in philosophy is implied when this work is taken as a series of faltering steps towards the invention of a perfected thought-technique which would spare truth the labour of error. In these circumstances “The preceding philosophical systems would at all times be nothing but practice studies for the big brains”. Research on the Phenomenology of Spirit has occasionally resembled both an aggregation of inert philological objects and a series of intellectual work-outs. But either fate may be preferable to its relegation to the honourable oblivion of Gedankendichtung, “conceptual poetry”. The phrase “Hegel-specialist” has an oxymoronic ring to it; but the separation of faculties which governs this need for experts cannot be wished away. A stuffed replica of the Phenomenology of Spirit, or even a requirement that all philosophers should speak Hegelian, can hardly today provide more than philosophical kitsch. Hegel's philosophical compositions continue mutely to reproach the graceless cerebration sometimes conducted in their name, but they are still worse served by what Hegel referred to as “the conceit that will not argue”. These considerations also apply to the content of interpretations of the Phenomenology itself and of Hegel's thought in general. Some recent readings have emphasized Hegel's Kantian and Fichtean inheritance to the point where it might almost be thought that what is distinctively interesting about Hegel has vanished altogether. But such readings represent a fair response not merely to any idea that Hegel kindly allows us to have back intact the dogmatic metaphysics harshly prohibited by Kant, but also to interpretations which forget that Hegel's critique of epistemology proceeds immanently and epistemologically rather than being shot from a pistol. Discussion of the “unhappy consciousness” might stand as an epitome for these oppositions in Hegel-reception. At one extreme lies Walter Kaufmann's suggestion that “Hegel evidently wanted to get some ideas about medieval Christianity off his chest…”; but deeper and more nuanced readings of the presence of a phenomenology of religious consciousness in this passage are not lacking, above all the monograph by Wahl and Hyppolite's discussion in his commentary.

Type
Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Hegel, G W F, The Difference Between Fichte's and Schelling's System of Philosophy, trans Harris, H S and Cerf, Walter (Albany: SUNY Press, 1977), p 85 Google Scholar.

2 Ibid, p 87.

3 Phenomenology of Spirit, trans Miller, A V (Oxford University Press, 1977), p 41 Google Scholar.

4 See in particular Pippin, Robert B, Hegel's Idealism: the satisfactions of self-consciousness (Cambridge: CUP, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Kaufmann, Walter, Hegel: Reinterpretation, Texts and Commentary (New York: Doubleday, 1966), p 156 Google Scholar; quoted in Flay, Joseph, Hegel's Quest for Certainty (Albany: SUNY Press, 1984), p 313 Google Scholar.

6 Wahl, Jean, Le malheur de la conscience dans la philosophic de Hegel (Paris: PUF, 1951)Google Scholar

7 Hyppolite, Jean, The genesis and structure of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, trans Cherniak, Samuel and Heckman, John (Evanston: Northwestern UP, 1974), pp 190215 Google Scholar.

8 Fink, Eugen, Hegel: Phaenomenologische Interpretationen der Phaenomenologie des Geistes (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1977), pp 179201 Google Scholar.

9 Pippin, , Hegel's Idealism, pp 143-71Google Scholar.

10 Kojève, Alexandre, Introduction a la lecture de Hegel (Paris: Gallimard, 1947), pp 1134, 49-56, 61-76Google Scholar.

11 Garaudy, Roger, La pensée de Hegel (Paris: Bordas, 1966), p 59 Google Scholar.

12 Marcuse, Herbert, Reason and revolution: Hegel and the rise of social theory, 2nd edn, (London: Routledge, 1955), pp 91120 Google Scholar.

13 Lukacs, Georg, The Young Hegel: studies in the relations between dialectics and economics, trans Livingstone, Rodney (London: Merlin Press, 1975), pp 466536 Google Scholar.

14 Adorno, Theodor W, Hegel: Three Studies, trans Nicholsen, Shierry Weber (Cambridge: Mass, MIT Press, 1993)Google Scholar; Negative Dialektik (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1975)Google Scholar; Subject and object” in The Essential Frankfurt School Reader, ed by Arato, Andrew and Gebhardt, Eike (New York: Continuum, 1982), pp 497511 Google Scholar.

15 Rinaldi, Giacomo, A History and Interpretation of the Logic of Hegel (Lewiston, Queenston and Lampeter: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1992), p 315 Google Scholar.

16 Ahlers, Rolf, “The overcoming of critical theory in the Hegelian unity of theory and praxis”, Clio 8 (1) (1978), 7196, p 82Google Scholar.

17 Winfield, Richard Dien, Freedom and Modernity (Albany. SUNY Press, 1991), p 195n.Google Scholar

18 Rose, Gillian, Hegel contra Sociology (London: Athlone, 1981), pp 3133 Google Scholar; see also The Broken Middle (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), pp 810 Google Scholar.

19 As Rose points out: Hegel contra Sociology, p 185.

20 Theunissen, Michael, Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist als theologisch-politischer Traktat (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1970), pp 337 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Negativitaet bei Adorno” in Adorno-Konferenz 1983, ed Friedeburg, Ludwig von and Habermas, Jürgen (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983), pp 4165 Google Scholar; Gesellschaft und Geschichte. Zur Kritik der kritischen Theorie (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1969)Google Scholar.

21 Theunissen, , “Negativität bei Adorno”, pp 5758 Google Scholar.

22 The Difference between Fichte 's and Schelling's System of Philosophy, p 81.

23 Phenomenology, p 141.

24 Ibid., p 141.

25 Phenomenology, trans Miller, , p 487 Google Scholar; Hegel's words are also quoted with reference to Adorno's Hegel-reception by Thyen, Anke, Negative Dialektik und Erfahrung. Zur Rationalität des Nichtindentischen bei Adorno (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1989), p 166 Google Scholar.

26 “…it must be said that nothing is known which is not in experience, or, as it is expressed, that is not felt to be true, not given as an inwardly revealed eternal verity, as something sacred that is believed, or whatever other expressions have just been used.” Phenomenology, p 487.

27 Ibid., pp 8-9.

28 See for example Hegel's, Science of Logic, trans Miller, A V, p 842 Google Scholar.

29 Phenomenology, pp 131-32.

30 Negative Dialektik (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1975) [ND], pp 8283nGoogle Scholar; Negative Dialectics, trans Ashton, E B [Ashton] (London: Routledge, 1973), p 75nGoogle Scholar. Quotations from Negative Dialektik are given in my translation; references to Ashton's version are supplied for convenience.

31 Drei Studien zu Hegel (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1974) [DS], p 58 Google Scholar. Hegel: Three Studies, trans Nicholsen, Shierry Weber (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1993) [H], p 59 Google Scholar. Quotations are from Nicholsen's version.

32 DS, p 14; H, p 7.

33 DS, p 18; H, p 12.

34 DS, pp 10-11; H, p 3. It is interesting that Richard Kroner is here credited with this insight given the frequency with which Kroner is reproached for presenting the history of German idealism as a single straight line.

35 DS, p 34; H, p 30.

36 DS, p 73; H, p 77.

37 DS, p 48; H, p 46.

38 DS, p 80; H, pp 84-85. For striking evidence of the influence of this thesis on Adorno's thinking see ND, p 66; Ashton, pp 56-57.

39 DS, pp 10-11; H, pp 2-3.

40 DS, pp 12-13; H, p 5.

41 Compare Adorno's characterization of experience as the “animating contradiction., of absolute truth”: DS, p 53; H, p 54.

42 DS, pp 33-34; H, pp 29-30.

43 ND, pp 85-86; Ashton, pp 77-78.

44 ND, p 138.

45 See, for example, Zur Metakritik der Erkenntnistheorie (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970)Google Scholar; Against Epistemology, trans Domingo, Willis (Oxford: Blackwell, 1982)Google Scholar.

46 DS, p 13; H, p 6.

47 See, for example. Minima Moralia, trans Jephcott, E F N (London: New Left Books, 1974), p 128 Google Scholar.

48 DS, p 17; H, p 11.

49 DS, p 65; H, p 67.

50 DS, pp 20-21; H, p 15.

51 DS, p 17; H, p 11. It should not be imagined that in naming Hegel's a philosophy of identity Adorno is confusing it with Schelling's early philosophy of identity: cf. DS, p 15; H, p 8.

52 Science of Logic, trans Miller, A V, p 439 Google Scholar.

53 Ibid.

54 Ibid., pp 440-41.

55 ND, p 156; Ashton, p 153

56 ND, pp 37-38; Ashton, p 27.

57 Ruediger Bubner points out the aptness of Friedrich Schlegel's aphorism: “It is equally fatal to spirit to have a system and to have none. It will therefore simply have to decide to combine the two”. Bubner, , “Adornos Negative Dialektik” in Adorno-Konferenz 1983, pp 3565, p 35Google Scholar.

58 ND, p 149; Ashton, p 145.

59 ND, p 10; Ashton, p xx.

60 ND, p 21; Ashton, p 10.

61 DS, p 93; H, p 100; see also ND, p 114-15; Ashton, p 108-9.

62 Hegel's, Logic, trans Wallace, William (Oxford: OUP, 1975), p 31 Google Scholar.

63 DS, p 94; H, p 101.

64 Cf. Hegel's, Philosophy of Mind, trans Wallace, William and Miller, A V (Oxford: OUP, 1971), pp 220-21Google Scholar.

65 ND, p 150; Ashton, p 147.

66 Phenomenology, p 66.

67 Cf Adorno, , Kierkegaard: Construction of the Aesthetic, trans Hullot-Kentor, Robert (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989), p 106 Google Scholar.

68 DS, p 71; H, p 74.

69 DS, p 60; H, p 62.

70 ND, p 241; Ashton, p 243.

71 See for example Aesthetische Theorie, (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1973), p 53 Google Scholar.

72 The sources for this thesis, apart from the obvious debt to Marx, include Sohn-Rethel, Alfred, Intellectual and manual labour, trans Sohn-Rethel, Martin (London: Macmillan, 1979)Google Scholar.

73 ND, p 198; Ashton, p 198.

74 Theunissen, , Hegels Lehre vom absoluten Geist, p 5 Google Scholar.

75 DS, p 23; H, p 18.

76 ND, pp 146-47; Ashton, p 143.

77 Marx, Karl, Early writings trans Livingstone, Rodney and Benton, Gregor, (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1975), pp 385-86Google Scholar.

78 Phaenomenologie des Geistes, ed Hoffmeister, Johannes (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1952), p 48 Google Scholar: “die Anstrengung des Begriffs”, rendered by Miller, , Phenomenology, p 35 Google Scholar, as “the strenuous effort of the Notion”.

79 DS, pp 53-83; H, pp 53-88.

80 DS, pp 13-14; H, p 7.

81 DS, p 26; H, p 21.

82 DS, p 27; H, p 22.

83 DS, pp 28-29; H, pp 23-24. See also ND, pp 179-80; Ashton, pp 177-78.

84 DS, p 58; H, p 59.

85 ND, p 173; Ashton, p 171: Vermittlung is in general variously mistranslated by Ashton as “transmisson” or “indirectness” rather than “mediation”.

86 ND, p 139; Ashton, p 135.

87 ND, p 173; Ashton, p 171.

88 DS, p 31; H, p 26.

89 DS, pp 30-31; H, p 26.

90 ND, pp 187-90; Ashton, pp 186-89 (as “The object not a datum”).

91 Ibid.

92 ND, p 186; Ashton, p 185.

93 ND, p 187; Ashton, p 187.

94 ND, pp 189-90; Ashton, p 189.

95 Adorno, Kierkegaard, p 107.

96 Ibid., p 115.

97 ND, p 24; Ashton, p 13.

98 DS, p 52; H, p 50.

99 Phenomenology, trans Miller, , p 134 Google Scholar.

100 A point which is brought out especially strongly by Liebrucks's reading: Liebrucks, Bruno, Sprache und Bewusstsein, vol 5, Die zweite Revolution der Denkungsart: Hegels Phaenomenologie des Geistes (Frankfurt am Main: Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft, 1970), pp 103-9Google Scholar.

101 “Eine fremde Gabe”: cf Phaenomenologie, p 166; cf Phenomenology, trans Miller, , p 133 Google Scholar.

102 Ibid, pp 165-66; Phenomenology, trans Miller, , pp 135-36Google Scholar.

103 Phenomenology, p 132.

104 Ibid., p 134.

105 DS, pp 30-31; H, p 26.

106 DS, p 31; H, p 26.

107 ND, p 160; Ashton, p 157.

108 ND, p 203; Ashton, p 203.

109 Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans Paton, H J (New York: Harper and Row, 1964), p 102.Google Scholar

110 For an invocation of such a given moment see DS, p 17; H, p 11.

111 ND, pp 178-80; Ashton, pp 176-78.

112 DS, p 32; H, p 28.

113 DS, pp 20-22; H, pp 15-17.

114 Phenomenology, trans Miller, , p 66 Google Scholar.

115 ND, pp 163-64; Ashton, pp 161-62.

116 ND, p 203; Ashton, p 203; cf Hegel, G W F, Philosophy of Mind, trans Wallace, William and Miller, A V. (Oxford: OUP, 1971), pp 1516 Google Scholar.

117 Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans Cumming, John (London: New Left Books, 1979), p 45 Google Scholar: “Aboriginal myth already contains the aspect of deception which triumphs in the fraudulence of Fascism yet imputes the same practice of lies to the Enlightenment”.

118 Cf especially the account of Schein, illusory being: Hegel's Science of Logic, trans Miller, , p 395-99Google Scholar.

118 Cf, for example, Aesthetische Theorie, pp 345-47.

119 ND, p 22; Ashton, pp 10-11.

120 ND, p 149; Ashton, p 145; ND, p 161; Ashton, p 158.

121 Theunissen, , “Negativitaet bei Adorno”, pp 5152 Google Scholar.

122 ND, p 66; Ashton, p 57

123 ND, p 66; Ashton, p 57.