Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T16:07:26.325Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reverberating the Glas: Towards a Deconstructive Account of Particularity in Hegel's Logic of the Concept

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 October 2020

Jakub Mácha*
Affiliation:
Masaryk University, Brno, [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

Understanding Hegel's account of particularity has proven to be anything but straightforward. Two main accounts of particularity have been advanced: the particular as an example or instance and the particular as a subjective perspective on a universal concept. The problem with these accounts is that they reduce particularity either to singularity or to universality. As Derrida's analyses make apparent, the ‘structure of exemplarity’ in Hegel is quite intricate. Hegel uses ‘example’ in three senses: it means (1) ‘instance’, ‘illustration’, or (2) ‘model’, ‘exemplary individual’, ‘paradigm’, or (3) a by-play (a meaning derived from Hegel's neologism beiherspielen, in which Beispiel is understood quasi-etymologically as a ‘by-play’ of accidental moments). A Beispiel in the first sense can be replaced by another instance in a free play (by-play). This play of accidental moments, however, is not entirely free; it generates a series (of replacements) that ultimately leads to an example in the second sense, to an exemplary individual. I argue that particularity can be taken as exemplarity of this kind, oscillating between a singular example and a universal paradigm. Within this by-play, the universal concept, its law, is supposed to be mediated and determined. However, out of the differences between the examples the by-play induces another law, the law of non-mediation, which may, in Derrida's view, actually negate the dialectical movement towards universality. I argue, utilizing Malabou's concept of plasticity, that this disruption may be recovered. This implies that each individual example within a series is a particular determination of the universal. Hence, we can take literally Hegel's claim that the movement of the concept is play.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agamben, G. (2009), The Signature of All Things, trans. D'Insanto, L. and Attel, K.. New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
Critchley, S. (1988), ‘A Commentary Upon Derrida's Reading of Hegel in Glas’, Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 9:2: 632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derrida, J. (1982), Différance’, Margins of Philosophy, trans. Bass, A.. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. (1986), Glas, trans. Leavey, J. Jr. and Rand, R.. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. (1987), The Truth in Painting, trans. Bennington, G. and McLeod, I.. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derrida, J. (1992), ‘Passions: “An Oblique Offering”’, in Wood, D. (ed.), Derrida: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. (2005a), ‘A time for farewells: Heidegger (read by) Hegel (read by) Malabou’, in Malabou, C., The Future of Hegel: Plasticity, Temporality and Dialectic, trans. Cohen, J. D.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. (2005b), On Touching—Jean-Luc Nancy, trans. Irizarry, C.. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. (2006), Specters of Marx, trans. Kamuf, P.. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. (2010), ‘Hostipitality’, in: Acts of Religion, ed. Anidjar, G.. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. and Ferraris, M. (2001), A Taste for the Secret, trans. G. Donis. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. and Roudinesco, E. (2004), For What Tomorrow… (A Dialogue), trans. Fort, J.. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Fišerová, M. (2018a), Dekonstrukce podpisu. Jacques Derrida a opakování neopakovatelného. Prague: Togga.Google Scholar
Fišerová, M. (2018b), ‘Pragmatical Paradox of Signature’, Signata 9: 485504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fišerová, M. (forthcoming), Event of Signature: Jacques Derrida and Repeating of the Unrepeatable. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Liddell, H. and Scott, R. (1940), A Greek-English Lexicon. Oxford: Clarendon Press. <http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/>Google Scholar
Littré, E. (1878), Dictionnaire de la langue française. Paris: Hachette.Google Scholar
Lumsden, S. (2007a), ‘Dialectic and différance. The place of singularity in Hegel and Derrida’, Philosophy & Social Criticism 33:6: 667–90.10.1177/0191453707080580CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lumsden, S. (2007b), ‘Hegel, Derrida and the Subject’, Cosmos and History 3:2–3: 3250.Google Scholar
Mácha, J. (2019), ‘Particularity as Paradigm: A Wittgensteinian Reading of Hegel's Subjective Logic’, in Mácha, J. and Berg, A. (eds.), Wittgenstein and Hegel: Reevaluation of Difference. Berlin: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mácha, J. (2020a), ‘Beispiel/By-play in Hegel's Writings’, in Hrnjez, S. and Nardelli, E. (eds.), Hegel and/in/on Translation, Verifiche XLIX (1–2).Google Scholar
Mácha, J. (2020b), ‘The Logic of Exemplarity’, Law & Literature, DOI: 10.1080/1535685X.2020.1779513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malabou, C. (2000), ‘Deconstructive and/or “plastic” readings of Hegel’, Hegel Bulletin 21:1–2: 132–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malabou, C. (2005), The Future of Hegel: Plasticity, Temporality and Dialectic, trans. During, L.. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2018), Hegel's Realm of Shadows. Logic as Metaphysics in The Science of Logic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redding, P. (2014), ‘The Role of Logic “Commonly So Called” in Hegel's Science of Logic’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22:2: 281301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roller, M. (2015), ‘Between unique and typical: Seneca exempla in a list’, in Lowrie, M. and Lüdemann, S. (eds.), Exemplarity and Singularity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Schlitt, D. M. (2012), Hegel's Trinitarian Claim: A Critical Reflection. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Schülein, J.-G. (2016), Metaphysik und ihre Kritik bei Hegel und Derrida. Hamburg: Meiner.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stekeler-Weithofer, P. (1992), Hegels analytische Philosophie. Die Wissenschaft der Logik als kritische Theorie der Bedeutung. Paderborn: Ferdinand Schöningh.Google Scholar
Stewart, J. (2011), ‘Kierkegaard and Hegel on Faith and Knowledge’, in Houlgate, S. and Baur, M. (eds.), A Companion to Hegel. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Warminski, A. (1987), Readings in Interpretation. Hölderlin, Hegel, Heidegger. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (2006), From Concept to Objectivity: Thinking Through Hegel's Subjective Logic. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (2011), ‘Hegel's Solution to the Mind-Body Problem’, in Houlgate, S. and Baur, M. (eds.), A Companion to Hegel. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Žižek, S. (2012), Less than Nothing: Hegel and the Shadow of Dialectical Materialism. London: Verso.Google Scholar