Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T00:16:51.588Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How biological is human history? Kant's use of biological concepts and its implications for history as moral anthropology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2013

Liesbet Vanhaute*
Affiliation:
University of Antwerp, [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

This article concerns a specific shift in Kant's use of biological concepts in his theory of history. As I argue in the first section, biological concepts play an important role in Kant's early theory of history. However, in the Critique of the Power of Judgement, Kant explicitly separates history from biology: history and biology become fundamentally different forms of teleological explanation. In the second section, I examine Kant's reasons for the separation of history from biology. I conclude with a discussion of the moral implications of this modification in his historical writings.

Kant's main concern in his philosophy of history is the intelligibility of history. How should history be understood, given the fact that it appears to be a mere amalgam of contingent human actions?

The reason why historical facts are so confusing and unsystematic is that human behaviour is not fully determined by any particular factor. It is underdetermined by animal instinct, but it is not completely guided by principles of reason either. To address this randomness, philosophers of history must actively search for coherent structures. They must look for concepts and assumptions that help them to grasp the phenomena in a systematic way. Kant suggests that assuming a predisposition which unfolds throughout history is inevitable in this regard. A predisposition is understood as a natural tendency of the human species, which is initially hidden but manifests itself gradually and continually.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, H. (1990), Kant's Theory of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beishart, C. (2009), ‘Kant's Characterization of Natural Ends’ in Heidemann, D., (ed.), Kant-Yearbook: Teleology. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Cohen, A. (2009), Kant and the Human Sciences: Biology, Anthropology and History. New York: Pallgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, A. (2006), ‘Kant on Epigenesis, Monogenesis and Human Nature: The Biological Premises of Anthropology’, Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences 37(4), 675693.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Guyer, P. (2003), ‘Kant's Principles of Reflecting Judgement’ in Guyer, P., (ed.), Kant's Critique of the Power of Judgement, Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1789), Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, trans. Louden, R. in Louden, R., and Zöller, G. (eds.), Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1790), Critique of the Power of Judgement, trans. Guyer, P., and Matthews, E.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1785), Determination of the Concept of a Human Race, trans. Wilson, H. and Zöller, G. in Louden, R. and Zöller, G. (eds.), Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1785), Groundwork of The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Gregor, M. in Gregor, M. and Wood, A. (eds.), Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1784), Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim, trans. Wood, A in Louden, R. and Zöller, G. (eds), Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1755), Of the Different Races of Human Beings, trans. Wilson, H. and Zöller, G. in Louden, R. and Zöller, G. (eds), Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1788), On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy, trans. Zöller, G. in Louden, R. and Zöller, G. (eds), Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1793), Religion within the Boundaries of mere Reason, trans. di Giovanni, G. in di Giovanni, G. and Wood, A. (eds.), Religion and Rational Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1785), Review of J.G. Herder's Ideas for the Philosophy of History of Humanity, trans. Wood, Allen in Louden, R. and Zöller, G. (eds.), Anthropology, History, and Education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1797), The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Gregor, M. in Gregor, M. and Wood, A. (eds.), Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
Kleingeld, P. (1999), ‘Kant, history & the idea of moral development’ in History of Philosophy Quarterly 16:5980.Google Scholar
Wilson, H. (2006), Kant's Pragmatic Anthropology. Its Origin, Meaning and Critical Significance. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Ypi, L. (2010), ‘ Natura Daedala Rerum? On the Justification of Historical Progress in Kant's Guarantee of Perpetual Peace ’ in Kantian Review 14, 2:118148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zammito, J. (1992), Genesis of Kant's Critique of Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar