Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T23:11:59.612Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Internal barriers to efficiency: why disinvestments are so difficult. Identifying and addressing internal barriers to disinvestment of health technologies

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2021

Bjørn Hofmann*
Affiliation:
Institute for the Health Sciences, Norwegian University of Science and Technology, Gjovik, Norway Centre of Medical Ethics, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway
*
Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]; [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Although efficiency is a core concept in health economics, its impact on health care practice still is modest. Despite an increased pressure on resource allocation, a widespread use of low-value care is identified. Nonetheless, disinvestments are rare. Why is this so? This is the key question of this paper: why are disinvestments not more prevalent and improving the efficiency of the health care system, given their sound foundation in health economics, their morally important rationale, the significant evidence for a long list of low-value care and available alternatives? Although several external barriers to disinvestments have been identified, this paper looks inside us for mental mechanisms that hamper rational assessment, implementation, use and disinvestment of health technologies. Critically identifying and assessing internal inclinations, such as cognitive biases, affective biases and imperatives, is the first step toward a more rational handling of health technologies. In order to provide accountable and efficient care we must engage in the quest against the figments of our minds; to disinvest in low-value care in order to provide high-value health care.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Efficiency is a core concept in health economics. However, this is not pervasive in practice. For example, health economists are accused of focusing on adoption rather than efficiency when assessing health technologies (Scotland and Bryan, Reference Scotland and Bryan2017). The lack of efficiency is expressed by an increased focus on low-value health services (Parkinson et al., Reference Parkinson, Sermet, Clement, Crausaz, Godman and Garner2015; Brownlee et al., Reference Brownlee, Chalkidou, Doust, Elshaug, Glasziou, Heath, Nagpal, Saini, Srivastava and Chalmers2017; Elshaug et al., Reference Elshaug, Rosenthal, Lavis, Brownlee, Schmidt, Nagpal, Littlejohns, Srivastava, Tunis and Saini2017; Glasziou et al., Reference Glasziou, Straus, Brownlee, Trevena, Dans, Guyatt, Elshaug, Janett and Saini2017; Saini et al., Reference Saini, Brownlee, Elshaug, Glasziou and Heath2017a, Reference Saini, Garcia-Armesto, Klemperer, Paris, Elshaug, Brownlee, Ioannidis and Fisher2017b; Malik et al., Reference Malik, Marti, Darzi and Mossialos2018). Recommendations from NICE (Do-not-do list), Choosing Wisely and from Australia (Elshaug et al., Reference Elshaug, Watt, Mundy and Willis2012) together identify 1350 specific low-value technologies in use (Soril et al., Reference Soril, Seixas, Mitton, Bryan and Clement2018). A series of drivers of poor medical care have been identified (Hollingworth and Chamberlain, Reference Hollingworth and Chamberlain2011; Elshaug et al., Reference Elshaug, Watt, Mundy and Willis2012; Niven et al., Reference Niven, Mrklas, Holodinsky, Straus, Hemmelgarn, Jeffs and Stelfox2015; Scott and Duckett, Reference Scott and Duckett2015; Saini et al., Reference Saini, Brownlee, Elshaug, Glasziou and Heath2017a, Reference Saini, Garcia-Armesto, Klemperer, Paris, Elshaug, Brownlee, Ioannidis and Fisher2017b) and solutions are suggested (Ibargoyen-Roteta et al., Reference Ibargoyen-Roteta, Gutiérrez-Ibarluzea and Asua2010; Garner and Littlejohns, Reference Garner and Littlejohns2011; Schmidt, Reference Schmidt2012; Levinson et al., Reference Levinson, Kallewaard, Bhatia, Wolfson, Shortt and Kerr2015; Pathirana et al., Reference Pathirana, Clark and Moynihan2017; Scotland and Bryan, Reference Scotland and Bryan2017; Soril et al., Reference Soril, MacKean, Noseworthy, Leggett and Clement2017; Harris et al., Reference Harris, Allen, Waller and Brooke2017a, Reference Harris, Green, Ramsey, Allen and King2017b).

In particular, disinvestments have been strongly encouraged in order to reduce low-value care and increase efficiency (Ruano-Ravina et al., Reference Ruano-Raviña, Velasco-González, Varela Lema, Cerdá-Mota, Ibargoyen Roteta and Gutiérrez Ibarluzea2007; Hollingworth and Chamberlain, Reference Hollingworth and Chamberlain2011; Elshaug et al., Reference Elshaug, Watt, Mundy and Willis2012; Gliwa and Pearson, Reference Gliwa and Pearson2014; Schwartz et al., Reference Schwartz, Landon, Elshaug, Chernew and McWilliams2014; Selby et al., Reference Selby, Gaspoz, Rodondi, Neuner-Jehle, Perrier, Zeller and Cornuz2015; Gapanenko et al., Reference Gapanenko, Lam, Parker, D'Silva and Johnson2017; Iacobucci, Reference Iacobucci2018; Prusaczyk et al., Reference Prusaczyk, Swindle and Curran2020).

Although assessment supports decisions about adopting technologies, disinvestment decisions require that technologies already in the system undergo reassessment (or assessment if they were not initially subject to an assessment). However, reassessments are rarely reported compared to assessment of new technologies (Soril et al., Reference Soril, Seixas, Mitton, Bryan and Clement2018) and very few results from disinvestments are documented (Polisena et al., Reference Polisena, Clifford, Elshaug, Mitton, Russell and Skidmore2013; Scott and Elshaug, Reference Scott and Elshaug2013; Alderwick et al., Reference Alderwick, Robertson, Appleby, Dunn and Maguire2015; Coronini-Cronberg et al., Reference Coronini-Cronberg, Bixby, Laverty, Wachter and Millett2015; de Vries et al., Reference de Vries, Struijs, Heijink, Hendrikx and Baan2016; Harris et al., Reference Harris, Allen, Waller and Brooke2017a, Reference Harris, Green, Ramsey, Allen and King2017b). Why is this so? This is the key question this paper seeks to address. Although there may be many rational explanations for why reassessments and disinvestments are so rarely reported, this paper addresses some of the less rational mechanisms and barriers. A wide range of barriers (and facilitators/enablers) for disinvestments have been identified (Solomons and Spross, Reference Solomons and Spross2011; Henshall et al., Reference Henshall, Schuller and Mardhani-Bayne2012; van Bodegom-Vos et al., Reference van Bodegom-Vos, Davidoff and Marang-van de Mheen2017; Harris et al., Reference Harris, Allen, Waller and Brooke2017a, Reference Harris, Green, Ramsey, Allen and King2017b; Sauro et al., Reference Sauro, Bagshaw, Niven, Soo, Brundin-Mather, Leigh, Cook and Stelfox2019). However, these are mainly rational or system-level phenomena, such as lack of guidelines, lack of evidence or competency and lack of support (Harris et al., Reference Harris, Allen, Waller and Brooke2017a, Reference Harris, Green, Ramsey, Allen and King2017b). Even if we address all such barriers, there are still some crucial less rational obstacles that effectively can obstruct efficiency in health care, such as affective biases, cognitive biases and imperatives of our imaginations.

Accordingly, this paper will investigate whether there are, strong, ‘internal’ and not fully recognized mechanisms behind the continued use of low-value care. The overall goal is to bring health economics, health technology assessment (HTA), and health policy making consistent with its principles. Hence, although several studies have provided external (system-level) explanations, this study will contribute by looking inside us at cognitive biases, affective biases and imperatives. The goal with revealing the figments of our mind that undermine or hamper reassessment and disinvestment is to increase our attention and direct our actions toward more effective measures to fight the lack of efficiency.

Before analyzing the mechanisms of our mind that hamper disinvestment, let us start with clarifying what is meant by mechanism and disinvestment, the relationship between reassessment and disinvestment and the relationship between the micro-level mechanisms and macro-level decisions.

2. Initial clarifications

In this paper, the term ‘mechanism’ is used as a generic term for a wide range of dispositions, inclinations, biases, tendencies, imperatives and forces that hampers disinvestment.

Disinvestment is defined as ‘withdrawing health resources from any existing health care practices, procedures, technologies or pharmaceuticals that are deemed to deliver little or no health gain for their cost, and thus do not represent efficient health resource allocation’ (Elshaug et al., Reference Elshaug, Hiller and Moss2008) and as activities that ‘remove a TCP [technology and clinical practice] that is unsafe or ineffective, restrict a TCP to more appropriate patient groups, or replace a TCP with an equally safe and effective but more cost-effective option’ (Harris et al., Reference Harris, Allen, Waller and Brooke2017a, Reference Harris, Green, Ramsey, Allen and King2017b). The ‘withdrawal of health resources’ is frequently considered to be negative (despite the fact that what is withdrawn is of little, no, or even negative value). Moreover, the prefix (dis) means ‘apart’, ‘under’, ‘away’ or ‘negative’. Hence, there is a negative connotation related disinvestment.

Disinvestment of low-value care is in accordance with basic principles of efficient use of health resources (Scotland and Bryan, Reference Scotland and Bryan2017). In principle, reassessments and disinvestments can have positive or neutral connotations, for example when identifying scope creep and appropriateness of care (distinguishing high-value and underused procedures from low-value or overused procedures). Nonetheless, the concept tends to be associated with reduction, removal or withdrawal, therefore obtains a negative nuance. Hence, the conception of disinvestment is itself subject to the biases to be discussed below.

Many of the mechanisms that hamper disinvestment also are relevant for reassessment.Footnote 1 Reassessment is also a precondition for identifying low-value care and candidates for disinvestment. Hence, the mechanisms hampering disinvestment also hinder reassessment. However, in order to simplify the reading of the text the paper will use the term ‘disinvestment’ and not ‘reassessment and disinvestment’.

Moreover, the following analysis focuses on mechanisms that appear at the level of individuals and it is not obvious that such mechanisms have system-level effects. However, there are at least three reasons why individual-level mechanisms have system-level effects. First, even micro- and meso-level mechanisms have macro-level implications, not least in terms of alternative costs. Second, many of the described mechanisms are relevant for individuals involved in disinvestment deliberation, including health policy makers. Third, disinvestment decisions have to be performed at the practical (meso- and micro-) level where the effects are most noticeable. Rational and unbiased disinvestment decisions at the macro level will have no real-world effect if they do not take the micro-level effects into account. Moreover, a more detailed analysis of the levels that the various mechanisms work is provided in Hofmann (Reference Hofmann2020) and the levels are indicated in Table 1.

Table 1. Overview of various mechanisms undermining reassessment and disinvestment

3. Mechanisms that hamper disinvestment

There are many ways to classify or group the various inclinations that will be discussed in the following. As the writings of Kahneman and Tversky have been so influential, their (system 1) framework will be applied to describe cognitive biases and affective/emotional biases (Kahneman et al., Reference Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky1982). However, as some of the mechanisms that will be discussed appear to fit well neither with system 1 nor system 2, the concept of ‘imperative’ discussed by Mazarr will be applied (Mazarr, Reference Mazarr2016). An imperative is defined as a ‘specific form of nonconsequentialist judgments [which] involves following, without much analysis or rigorous thought, an intensely felt requirement or obligation that creates a sense that the [agent] ‘must’ take some action’ (Mazarr, Reference Mazarr2016). As biases and imperatives may need different analytical and practical approaches, it makes sense to try to differentiate between them.

Table 1 gives an overview of the groups and specific biases identified in this study.

3.1 Cognitive biases

The Status Quo Bias is described as a cognitive bias with an irrational preference for one option only because it preserves the current state of affairs (Kahneman and Tversky, Reference Kahneman and Tversky2013). This links to what has been called aversion to change (conservativism) making people avoid change (Saposnik et al., Reference Saposnik, Redelmeier, Ruff and Tobler2016). Hence, as far as disinvestments imply changes, they can make people skeptical or resentful.

Another bias is found in our tendency to understand risks and benefits in very unbalanced ways (Slovic and Peters, Reference Slovic and Peters2006; Slovic, Reference Slovic2016). The risks of low-value technologies may be underestimated while the benefits may be overestimated, making disinvestment seem counterintuitive or unnecessary. Hence, when we assess technologies we may not always understand and assess them in an unengaged way (Gigerenzer, Reference Gigerenzer2015).

Another well-known bias is the ‘endowment effect’ according to which we tend to overvalue what we already have got compared to alternatives. In economic terms: ‘the fact that people often demand much more to give up an object than they would be willing to pay to acquire it’ (Kahneman et al., Reference Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler1991). Hence, the technology that we have assessed and implemented, been trained to use, become familiar with, and which partly constitutes our professional identity, tends to be valued higher than other technologies; even if evidence shows that the alternative technology is better. The endowment effect relates to ‘rejection dislike’ and ‘failure embarrassment’ (see below).

Certainly, there are other cognitive biases relevant for reassessment and disinvestment such as the anchoring effect, framing effects and information biases (Saposnik et al., Reference Saposnik, Redelmeier, Ruff and Tobler2016) (see Table 1). Common to all these (and several other) biases is that they tend to buttress positive views and use of a given technology, hampering disinvestment.

3.2 Affective biases

In addition to these cognitive biases, other biases are frequently classified as affective, as emotional factors that tend to distort cognition and decision making. One example is the ‘loss aversion’, according to which we feel uncomfortable with losing what we have, or in economic terms ‘the disutility of giving up an object is greater that the utility associated with acquiring it’ (Kahneman et al., Reference Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler1991). This is exactly what we may fear is happening when we reassess or disinvest in (health) technology. By disinvestment, we think we lose something, e.g. because we attribute unreasonable value to what we have. This also relates to the endowment effect (above).

Other related psychological effects are ‘anticipated decision regret’ (Tymstra, Reference Tymstra1989) and ‘better safe than sorry’. For example, the fear of doing too little may be greater than the fear of doing too much – the fear of ignoring dominates the fear of exaggerating (aversion asymmetry). This effect may enhance the fear of reducing, taking something away or disinvesting. It is also related to defensive medicine and what has been called the ‘popularity paradox’ (Raffle and Gray, Reference Raffle and Muir Gray2007; Welch and Black, Reference Welch and Black2010). ‘Aversion to risk’ and ‘aversion to ambiguity’ (Saposnik et al., Reference Saposnik, Redelmeier, Ruff and Tobler2016) may also be at play whenever it feels risky to reassess or disinvest. The key point for these types of biases is an emotional fear of not being sure, doing too little and not being professionally proficient.

A related bias has been called ‘rejection dislike’ and stems from the fact that no one likes being rejected or to reject others. The same goes for the emotional distress with taking something away (taking away dislike). Disinvesting in specific technologies may mean that some services previously provided may have to be removed. Hence, some patients cannot get what they previously have been offered, and despite the fact that it is of low value, it feels bad to take it away and thereby rejecting people (or to lose it). This may therefore explain the resistance to reassessment and disinvestment.

Correspondingly, no one likes to admit having behaved foolishly. Disinvesting (and sometimes also reassessing) a technology implies that we have provided patients with low-value care, which is not compatible with the professional integrity and self-conception of many health professionals (or policy makers). This may be called the ‘failure embarrassment effect’, and can be one of many reasons why clinicians, health managers, as well as health decision makers are modestly enthusiastic for disinvestment.

Hence, as far as disinvestment is associated with loosing, rejecting, taking away or having behaved foolishly, we tend to be inclined to avoid such situations. This can help us to explain our moderate enthusiasm for reassessment and disinvestment, but also how we should avoid such aspects in order to facilitate reassessment and disinvestment.

3.3 Imperatives

One important imperative is the imperative of possibility (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2002a, Reference Hofmann2002b, Reference Hofmann2002c): because something is possible, it ought to be implemented, or as they say in radiology: ‘we scan because we can’. This is closely related to Roemer's law: ‘A built bed is a filled bed’ (Shain and Roemer, Reference Shain and Roemer1959). The imperative of possibility is related to another imperative, which expressed by the traditional medical phrase ut aliquid fiat (that something must happen), i.e. that there is an obligation to act, and that action is better than inaction. Technology is associated with actionability and reducing readiness to action can be conceived of as plummeting professional stamina. This phenomenon can be connected to the tendency to use technology as a placebo (Einvik et al., Reference Einvik, Tjomsland, Kvernebo, Stavnes and Ekeberg2002; Saririan and Eisenberg, Reference Saririan and Eisenberg2003; Harris, Reference Harris2016). For example, diagnostic technology that is developed to detect somatic disease is used to treat mental conditions (anxiety) or to ascertain health (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2002a, Reference Hofmann2002b, Reference Hofmann2002c, Reference Hofmann2006). This sometimes is called ‘technology creep’ (Gelijns and Halm, Reference Gelijns and Halm1991; Hobson, Reference Hobson2009). As the placebo-effect of technology is high its overall effect may be considered to be significant even if documented (placebo-controlled) effect may be small (Howard et al., Reference Howard, Wessely, Leese, Page, McCrone, Husain, Tong and Dowson2005). This may explain the use of a wide range of low-value care, including several kinds of surgery (Harris, Reference Harris2016) and the opposition to disinvestment.

This relates to the imperative of progress (sometimes also called progress bias), according to which we have a strong cognitive propensity to progress and development (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2019a, Reference Hofmann2019b). Initially, one could come to think that experience and belief in progress would promote change, leaving old technologies obsolete when embracing new ones. However, there tends to be an accumulative aspect of the imperative of progress. Implicitly, we tend to think that science in general and medicine in particular progresses by adding new technologies, not by reducing or removing old ones. Expansion and addition are part and parcel of progress.

Furthermore, the imperative of progress can be connected to technology-related tendencies, such as strong beliefs in positive outcome of advanced technologies (Anton and Jones, Reference Anton and Jones2017; Greenhalgh et al., Reference Greenhalgh, Wherton, Papoutsi, Lynch, Hughes, A'Court, Hinder, Fahy, Procter and Shaw2017) and what has been described as a technology ‘adoption addiction’ (Scotland and Bryan, Reference Scotland and Bryan2017) and the ‘denial of the need for disinvestment’ (Bryan et al., Reference Bryan, Mitton and Donaldson2014). It can also be related to the tendency to use technology for other purposes than intended without documentation of outcomes. Again, diagnostic imaging is a good example, where diagnostic technology is used therapeutically to treat fear and health anxiety, and sometimes to treat mental conditions in physicians (litigation anxiety).

Relatedly, we tend to think that advanced systems and technologies are better than simple ones, a phenomenon that can be called ‘imperative of complexity’ (sometimes also called ‘complexity bias’). A great number of technologies identified as low-value care are advanced or hi-tech, and it apparently counters our intuition that these advanced technologies could be ineffective, inefficient or even harmful. On the contrary, lo-tech or what has been called ‘reverse innovation’ (adapting simple but efficient solutions from low- or middle-income countries) has very little traction.

Yet, another connected imperative is the imperative of extension (sometimes also called extension bias). According to the imperative of extension more is better than little (Rank, Reference Rank2008). This can be observed in a variety of fields, e.g. ‘more tests are better than few’. Reassessing (with the prospect of reducing) and disinvesting in technologies certainly breaks with basic intuitions that more is good.

The imperatives of progress and extension can be observed in the use and management of medical technologies in everyday clinical practice, for example in what has been called double (multiple) replacement (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2019a, Reference Hofmann2019b): an ultrasound machine is ‘replaced’ because it ‘provides low quality images’, ‘is dangerous’ or ‘outdated’. However, when the replacement arrives, the old machine is kept as a reserve. After a while, the discarded machine enters the daily practice again, for example due to high demand. After some time, it is argued again that it is ‘provides low quality images,’, ‘is dangerous’ or ‘outdated’ and needs replacement again (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2002a, Reference Hofmann2002b, Reference Hofmann2002c). Accordingly, disinvestment counters these types of ingrained practice partly driven by imperatives.

Furthermore, there are a series of positive cognitive feedback loops in the assessment and handling of medical technologies. For example, increasing the accuracy of diagnostic tests may lead to the detection of milder cases, and treating milder cases will increase the success rate (Black and Welch, Reference Black and Welch1993; Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2006; Welch et al., Reference Welch, Schwartz and Woloshin2011). Any measures that counter this experience of success appear counterintuitive, ‘irrational’, and regressive.

Diseases and technologies are also well known to have different status and prestige. In particular, diseases and specialties where advanced technology is applied have higher prestige than those where such technologies are not applied (Album and Westin, Reference Album and Westin2008; Album et al., Reference Album, Johannessen and Rasmussen2017). This may be because technology is related to innovation, progress, action, control and optimism (Fredriksen, Reference Fredriksen2006; Haas et al., Reference Haas, Hall, Viney and Gallego2012; Greenhalgh, Reference Greenhalgh2013; Strand et al., Reference Strand, Saltelli, Giampietro, Rommetveit and Funtowicz2016). This in turn may spur certain obligations (imperatives) to contribute to the progress of the field.

One imperative that also can counter disinvestment is what has been called the imperative of knowledge. In the field of diagnostics this is expressed as ‘to know is better than not to know’ despite the fact that many diagnostic tests have many false positives, incidental findings and overdiagnosis, so that the risks outrun the benefits. Nonetheless, we want to know, and tend to think that early detection is better than late (Hofmann and Skolbekken, Reference Hofmann and Skolbekken2017).

Another example is what has been called ‘white elephants’,Footnote 2 i.e. technologies that are acquired in order to attract skillful professionals, to keep individual professionals satisfied or to entice patients, but where the technology may not add value (or be of low value) to patients' outcomes (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann1998).

This relates to what has been called the ‘boys and toys effect’ where technologies, such as surgery robots, have been implemented not because of their effectiveness or efficiency, but because of their attractiveness to professionals and patients (Abrishami et al., Reference Abrishami, Boer and Horstman2014). The extensive use of Swan-Ganz catheters may be another example (Chatterjee, Reference Chatterjee2009). This mechanism can be related to the fact that the requirements for documented effectiveness and efficiency has been different for devices than for drugs (Wilmshurst, Reference Wilmshurst2011).

Hence, we may become reluctant to counter such imperatives, e.g. disinvesting and disposing of technologies that are associated with progress, action, knowledge, control and prestige. Thus, such tendencies are less immediate than biases (system 1) but less reflective than system 2 thinking (being non-consequentialist), and have therefore been classified as imperatives (Mazarr, Reference Mazarr2016).

In sum, there are cognitive biases, affective biases and imperatives that undermine or obstruct efficiency in health care. Table 1 gives an overview of the mechanisms that have been discussed in this paper and which level it involves.

4. Implications: what do biases and imperatives do?

The identified mechanisms can hamper or undermine disinvestment and thereby efficiency in health care. They can therefore help to explain why there are so few attempts and negligible outcomes from disinvestment, despite its excellent rationale, available evidence, accessible frameworks and available guidance. It also explains why identified low-value care still seems abundant, despite high pressure on resources and clear requirements of efficiency.

Another implication is skewed or unwarranted priority setting. The identified inclinations, i.e. the cognitive biases, affective biases and imperatives, represent a kind of implicit rationing resulting in effective and efficient technologies not being implemented or applied (due to opportunity cost) (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2020).

What about distrust and disillusion, frequently following from unaccountable health care? Does the inefficient health service provision following from biases and imperatives result in disillusion or distrust? No. Inefficient care resulting from lack of disinvestment hardly fosters distrust in care. On the contrary, disinvestment can frustrate health professionals and ‘denying patients care’ can harm the patient–physician relationship as well as trust in the health care system. Accordingly, ordinary self-correcting mechanisms do not work.

One important implication is that HTA bodies, guideline developers and health policy makers need to take biases and imperatives into account when they develop and apply their strategies to change health care toward more efficient and just health services provision.

5. What can we do?

How then, should we overcome these barriers to disinvestment as they are internal and irrational mechanisms and not external system-level barriers (rational or interest-driven)?

The first lesson learnt from the analysis is that many of the mechanisms are hidden and not acknowledged. Several of the biases are related to the fast and intuitive system 1, which is hard to access and alter. The best we can do is to engage the more reflective system 2 (Kahneman and Tversky, Reference Kahneman and Tversky1977; Kahneman and Tversky, Reference Kahneman and Tversky1996; Saposnik et al., Reference Saposnik, Redelmeier, Ruff and Tobler2016). This is slower and more resource demanding and also explains why many of the system level facilitators may not be very effective for biases and imperatives.

A first step would be to make explicit the implicit and make covert mechanisms overt. Engaging professionals in explaining why they provide low-value care and patients why they demand it can be but one way to do so. In this process, it may be important to inform openly about why a technology is considered for disinvestment.

Demonstrating the low value compared to relevant alternatives of higher value, can be helpful.

In order to avoid loss aversion, the endowment effect, and other biases it can be fruitful to explain and underscore the (potential) gain with disinvestment. Estimate and report the opportunity cost of low-value care and alternative high-value care can thus be helpful.

Moreover, asking specific questions targeting the various mechanisms may be fruitful. For example, do the fears to doing too little dominate over the fears of doing too much?

Another strategy is to appeal to professional integrity as well to basic ethical principles, such as non-maleficence. The world-expanding ChoosingWisely campaign is but one example of how this can work. Moreover, rejecting and removing a technology is only bad if the technology is of real value to the patient(s). Educating professionals, health managers, policy makers and patients in critical thinking may be important. Hence, involving them in disinvestment processes may be wise (Daniels, Reference Daniels2016).

Imperatives as well as professional norms, and values are ingrained and frequently discussed explicitly. There may be few forums or opportunities to address them. Hence, to initiate, stimulate and engaging professionals to reflect on their imperatives when they are deliberating on health technologies may be fruitful. For example, one can ask professionals to explain how they are addressing the identified imperatives. One can also scrutinize to what extent the condition, the profession(s), specialty, patient group or the technology has prestige or symbolic value, which gives it unwarranted attention, use or priority.

Correspondingly, professionals can be engaged in reflection on how they think the mechanisms influence their professional integrity and standing, and how they could be adjusted. Moreover, as professional norms and values are conveyed and formed most efficiently by opinion leaders, it appears important to target and engage them.

The barriers to disinvestment are oftentimes ingrained behaviors not identified or discussed openly. Hence, explicitly to address the mechanisms may be revealing and influence attitudes and behavior.

Figure 1 shows a flowchart that may be useful for the very first step of addressing biases and imperatives. The next step will be to target and tailor approaches to the disinvestment of specific technologies. There exists a plethora of frameworks of interventions for behavioral change, all with their pros and cons (Michie et al., Reference Michie, Van Stralen and West2011). Gladly, the literature provides theoretical constructs (Michie et al., Reference Michie, Johnston, Abraham, Lawton, Parker and Walker2005) and practical guidance (Michie et al., Reference Michie, Van Stralen and West2011).

Figure 1. Flowchart of questions with respect to addressing reassessment and disinvestment.

6. Discussion

There are more than 150 biases identified in a number of fields in the literature (Wright and Bragge, Reference Wright and Bragge2017). Even though, not all of these may be relevant for handling health technologies, several significant mechanisms have not been mentioned specifically. For example, social pressures (bandwagoning) frequently studied in human relations may be relevant (Cantarelli et al., Reference Cantarelli, Belle and Belardinelli2020). The same goes for context errors that are well known from clinical decision making, e.g. when the physician is not able to see the context of the patient's condition and makes erroneous diagnostic or therapeutic judgments (Wright and Bragge, Reference Wright and Bragge2017). Other psychological effects may also obstruct health economics' objective of efficient care, such as singularity effect and taboo-tradeoffs (Tinghög and Västfjäll, Reference Tinghög and Västfjäll2018). Abstract measures of efficiency lose their relevance in the face of one suffering person or when trading off peoples' lives against consumption.

However, the point here has not been to provide an exhaustive list of biases, but to attend to biases where examples indicate that they hamper disinvestment. Correspondingly, the goal has not been to go into the diverse and detailed debates on the classification and relationship between human cognitive, conceptual and affective biases (or imperatives), but rather to point to some mechanisms that appear to be relevant for explaining and handling the apparently irrational rejection of disinvestment. There may be many ways of classifying the various human inclinations. As indicated earlier, the classification here follows classification in psychology and behavioral economics as that may give some indications of how to address the biases.

Similarly, the mechanisms that have been described can be classified in many ways. For example, imperatives may be classified, analyzed and explained in a wide range of other ways, e.g. as inertia (Okonofua et al., Reference Okonofua, Simpson, Jesri, Rehman, Durkalski and Egan2006; Cooke et al., Reference Cooke, Sidel, Belletti and Fuhlbrigge2012; Reach et al., Reference Reach, Pechtner, Gentilella, Corcos and Ceriello2017; Saposnik and Montalban, Reference Saposnik and Montalban2018), human deficiencies (Cassell, Reference Cassell1993) or more specific forms of technological imperatives (Wolf and Berle, Reference Wolf and Berle1981; Mandell, Reference Mandell1983; Barger-Lux and Heaney, Reference Barger-Lux and Heaney1986; Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2002a, Reference Hofmann2002b, Reference Hofmann2002c). Correspondingly, the loss aversion effect here classified as an affective bias may well be classified as a cognitive bias. This is perfectly fine, as the point has not been to provide a perfect typology or nomenclature, but to focus on the mechanisms in order to increase awareness of phenomena that hamper reassessment and justified disinvestment.

As clarified in the Introduction, other barriers and obstacles than those identified and analyzed here have been identified in the literature, e.g. system-level barriers and that large-scale changes are required even to make small disinvestments in low-value care (Willson, Reference Willson2015). The reason for this is that low-value care frequently affects large parts of the system (pervasiveness), that new or alternative models are different from current ways of thinking and doing (depth), and that a change has to be spread across geographical boundaries, organizations or distinct groups of people (size) (Willson, Reference Willson2015). The focus of this study has been to add to the existing literature on the external system-level barriers by reviewing internal individual level obstacles. However, although biases and imperatives are ‘internal’ in actors, they are active in all stakeholders, and are based on social interaction, i.e. they are intersubjective. Moreover, there are connections between internal and external factors. For instance, industry is benefiting from and promoting biases, such as the imperative of progress. Moreover, biases and imperatives are related to interests and drivers. The closer analysis of the connection between the internal biases and external aspects and agents is the topic for another paper.

It is also worth noting that the health care system may have many other goals than efficiency, e.g. that individuals are cared for and maintaining trust. This is perfectly fine. This paper has only presupposed that efficiency is one of the goals warranted by the ethical principle of justice.

Moreover, there are many types of disinvestments (Daniels et al., Reference Daniels, Williams, Robinson and Spence2013). To investigate which type of mechanism is more efficient in undermining specific types of disinvestment is beyond the scope of this study. This should be considered to be the first step to address the inner barriers to reassessment and disinvestment. Similarly, disinvestments come in many forms, e.g. in ways that are not documented or evidence-based. Services are closed and activities terminated. However, such types of disinvestments have not been the topic of this paper.

Correspondingly, this study is not comprehensive with respect to covering measures to bar or reduce the mechanisms that hamper warranted disinvestment. Obvious measures such as highlighting the positive aspect of (a) gaining knowledge of the benefits of a technology (through reassessment) and (b) the positive aspects of reducing low-value care in order to promote high-value care have only been alluded to. Specific suggestions to reduce cognitive biases exist within special fields, such as decision support to reduce diagnostic errors (Newman-Toker and Pronovost, Reference Newman-Toker and Pronovost2009; Lee et al., Reference Lee, Nagy, Weaver and Newman-Toker2013; McDonald et al., Reference McDonald, Matesic, Contopoulos-Ioannidis, Lonhart, Schmidt, Pineda and Ioannidis2013) and interventions to improve clinical reasoning and decision-making skills (Graber et al., Reference Graber, Kissam, Payne, Meyer, Sorensen, Lenfestey, Tant, Henriksen, LaBresh and Singh2012). Advice on de-biasing health decisions in the clinical setting are available (Wilson and Brekke, Reference Wilson and Brekke1994; Croskerry et al., Reference Croskerry, Singhal and Mamede2013a, Reference Croskerry, Singhal and Mamede2013b), and several of these may be relevant for the health policy context, such as ‘stopping rules’, checklists and ‘cognitive forcing strategies’. All measures need to be carefully analyzed. Specifically, they need to be assessed with respect to biases and imperatives. Again, this study is the first step, pointing to basic measures to address the identified and inherent barriers to disinvestment.

One basic philosophical question emerges from the results of this study: do the biases and imperatives distorting rational disinvestment promote paternalism or libertarian paternalism (nudging)? This crucial question is beyond the scope of the current study. First, because it requires clarification of a series of empirical premises, e.g. how prevalent and intractable biases and imperatives are. Second, because it is the topic of a study (program) in itself.

Moreover, the study has focused on disinvestment. Other and related concepts could have been studied as well, such as reduced use, removal, decommissioning, withdrawal and rejection of technology as well as obsolete, outmoded or superseded technologies. The relationship between these and disinvestment are certainly of great interest, but beyond the scope of this study. As pointed out in the Introduction, most of the mechanisms discussed for disinvestment are relevant for reassessment. A more detailed analysis of the relevance of the various types of biases and imperatives would be a next step in the study of internal factors hampering efficient health care.

Another important issue that is not covered here is the fact that the mechanisms can be placed within specific theoretical frameworks. For example, many of the mechanisms can be elaborated from conceptual-metaphorical theory (Lakoff and Johnson, Reference Lakoff and Johnson1999), which may have implications on how we may address them. Again, theoretical framing is beyond the scope of this study, despite being interesting and important.

The preliminary measures are not to replace other suggestions for increasing efficiency (Ibargoyen-Roteta et al., Reference Ibargoyen-Roteta, Gutiérrez-Ibarluzea and Asua2010; Garner and Littlejohns, Reference Garner and Littlejohns2011; Schmidt, Reference Schmidt2012; Levinson et al., Reference Levinson, Kallewaard, Bhatia, Wolfson, Shortt and Kerr2015; Pathirana et al., Reference Pathirana, Clark and Moynihan2017; Soril et al., Reference Soril, MacKean, Noseworthy, Leggett and Clement2017; Harris et al., Reference Harris, Allen, Waller and Brooke2017a, Reference Harris, Green, Ramsey, Allen and King2017b) but rather to supplement and enhance the effectiveness of already existing suggestions.

7. The Mae West Hypothesis

This study has identified three classes of mechanisms that undermine or hamper disinvestment and reassessment: cognitive biases, affective biases and imperatives. The flowchart provides questions to ask and specific actions. The overall goal is to bring technology management on par with basic principles in health economics and in health care in general and to contribute to a more rational handling of technology in health care. At present, we tend to be subject what may be called ‘the Mae West Hypothesis (MWH)’, i.e. the belief that too much technology is a good thing. May West allegedly claimed that ‘Too much of a good thing is wonderful’ (Johnson, Reference Johnson1982; Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2010). However, with a significant extension of low-value care, the MWH is false, and given a potentially high opportunity cost of low-value care, it is dangerous.

8. Conclusion

The DIS – in disinvestment (and the RE – in reassessment) enhances the negative connotations due to internal mechanisms, such as cognitive biases, affective biases and imperatives. They tend to undermine basic principles in economics and priority setting and, therefore, should be conquered.

In order to do so, we must shrewdly identify, critically assess and bravely handle the inclinations of our mind. In particular, we must abandon the belief that too much of a good thing is wonderful. Hence, to provide accountable and efficient care we must engage in the quest against the figments of our minds. We must reassess and disinvest in order to exchange low-value care with high-value health care.

Acknowledgement

I am most thankful for the wise comments and constructive suggestions from anonymous reviewers.

Conflict of interest

I certify that there is no conflict of interest in relation to this manuscript, and there are no financial arrangements or arrangements with respect to the content of this manuscript with any companies or organizations. The work is funded by ordinary university salary.

Footnotes

1 Reassessment is defined as ‘a structured, evidence-based assessment of the clinical, social, ethical and economic effects of a technology currently used in the healthcare system to inform optimal use of an existing technology in comparison with its alternatives’ (Noseworthy and Clement, Reference Noseworthy and Clement2012: 201). Although reassessment can result in increased as well as decreased uptake and use of a given health technology, and despite the fact that this has been repeatedly emphasized by experts in the field (Noseworthy and Clement, Reference Noseworthy and Clement2012: 201–202; MacKean et al., Reference MacKean, Noseworthy, Elshaug, Leggett, Littlejohns, Berezanski and Clement2013), there seems to be a strong presumption that reassessment is related to reduced use, removal, rationing and decommissioning (Noseworthy and Clement, Reference Noseworthy and Clement2012: 201–202; Soril et al., Reference Soril, MacKean, Noseworthy, Leggett and Clement2017). Hence, reassessment also has a connotation of negative psychological value – of taking away.

2 The term ‘white elephants’ stems from South-East Asia, where white elephants were considered to be holy, and thus neither could work nor be killed.

References

Abrishami, P, Boer, A and Horstman, K (2014) Understanding the adoption dynamics of medical innovations: affordances of the da Vinci robot in the Netherlands. Social Science & Medicine (1982) 117, 125133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Album, D and Westin, S (2008) Do diseases have a prestige hierarchy? A survey among physicians and medical students. Social Science & Medicine (1982) 66, 182188.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Album, D, Johannessen, LE and Rasmussen, EB (2017) Stability and change in disease prestige: a comparative analysis of three surveys spanning a quarter of a century. Social Science & Medicine (1982) 180, 4551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alderwick, H, Robertson, R, Appleby, J, Dunn, P and Maguire, D (2015) ‘Better Value in the NHS.’ The Role of Changes in Clinical Practice. London: Kings Fund.Google Scholar
Anton, MT and Jones, DJ (2017) Adoption of technology-enhanced treatments: conceptual and practical considerations. Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice 24, 223240.Google ScholarPubMed
Barger-Lux, MJ and Heaney, RP (1986) For better and worse: the technological imperative in health care. Social Science & Medicine (1982) 22, 13131320.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Black, WC and Welch, HG (1993) Advances in diagnostic imaging and overestimations of disease prevalence and the benefits of therapy. New England Journal of Medicine 328, 12371243.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brownlee, S, Chalkidou, K, Doust, J, Elshaug, AG, Glasziou, P, Heath, I, Nagpal, S, Saini, V, Srivastava, D and Chalmers, K (2017) Evidence for overuse of medical services around the world. Lancet 390, 156168.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bryan, S, Mitton, C and Donaldson, C (2014) Breaking the addiction to technology adoption. Health Economics 23, 379383.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cantarelli, P, Belle, N and Belardinelli, P (2020) Behavioral public HR: experimental evidence on cognitive biases and debiasing interventions. Review of Public Personnel Administration 40, 5681.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassell, E (1993) The Sourcer's broom. Medicine's Rampant technology. The Hastings Center Report 23, 3239.10.2307/3562922CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chatterjee, K (2009) The Swan-Ganz catheters: past, present, and future. Circulation 119, 147152.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cooke, CE, Sidel, M, Belletti, DA and Fuhlbrigge, AL (2012) Clinical inertia in the management of chronic obstructive pulmonary disease. COPD 9, 7380.10.3109/15412555.2011.631957CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Coronini-Cronberg, S, Bixby, H, Laverty, AA, Wachter, RM and Millett, C (2015) English National health service's savings plan may have helped reduce the use of three ‘low-value’ procedures. Health Affairs 34, 381389.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Croskerry, P, Singhal, G and Mamede, S (2013a) Cognitive debiasing 1: origins of bias and theory of debiasing. BMJ Quality & Safety 22, ii65ii72.10.1136/bmjqs-2012-001713CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Croskerry, P, Singhal, G and Mamede, S (2013b) Cognitive debiasing 2: impediments to and strategies for change. BMJ Quality & Safety 22(suppl. 2), ii65ii72.10.1136/bmjqs-2012-001713CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daniels, T. A. (2016). To what extent should the public be involved in health disinvestment decision making: a mixed methods investigation into the views of health professionals in the English NHS, University of Birmingham.Google Scholar
Daniels, T, Williams, I, Robinson, S and Spence, K (2013) Tackling disinvestment in health care services. The views of resource allocators in the English NHS. Journal of Health Organization and Management 27, 762780.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
de Vries, EF, Struijs, JN, Heijink, R, Hendrikx, RJ and Baan, CA (2016) Are low-value care measures up to the task? A systematic review of the literature. BMC Health Services Research 16, 405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Einvik, G, Tjomsland, O, Kvernebo, K, Stavnes, S and Ekeberg, F (2002) Preoperativ forventning og klinisk effekt ved transmyokardial laserbehandling mot angina pectoris. Tidsskr Nor Lægeforen 122, 21022104.Google Scholar
Elshaug, AG, Hiller, JE and Moss, JR (2008) Exploring policy-makers’ perspectives on disinvestment from ineffective healthcare practices. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 24, 19.10.1017/S0266462307080014CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elshaug, AG, Watt, AM, Mundy, L and Willis, CD (2012) Over 150 potentially low-value health care practices: an Australian study. Medical Journal of Australia 197, 556560.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elshaug, AG, Rosenthal, MB, Lavis, JN, Brownlee, S, Schmidt, H, Nagpal, S, Littlejohns, P, Srivastava, D, Tunis, S and Saini, V (2017) Levers for addressing medical underuse and overuse: achieving high-value health care. Lancet 390, 191202.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fredriksen, S (2006) Tragedy, Utopia and medical progress. Journal of Medical Ethics 32, 450453.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gapanenko, K, Lam, D, Parker, M, D'Silva, J and Johnson, T (2017) Unnecessary care in Canada. Healthcare Quarterly 20, 10.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Garner, S and Littlejohns, P (2011) Disinvestment from low value clinical interventions: NICEly done? BMJ 343, d4519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelijns, AC and Halm, EA (1991) The Diffusion of New Technology: Costs and Benefits to Health Care. Washington, DC. National Academies Press. ISBN-10: 0-309-04491-X.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G (2015) Calculated Risks: How to Know When Numbers Deceive you. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Glasziou, P, Straus, S, Brownlee, S, Trevena, L, Dans, L, Guyatt, G, Elshaug, AG, Janett, R and Saini, V (2017) Evidence for underuse of effective medical services around the world. Lancet 390, 169177.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gliwa, C and Pearson, SD (2014) Evidentiary rationales for the choosing wisely top 5 lists. JAMA 311, 14431444.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Graber, ML, Kissam, S, Payne, VL, Meyer, AN, Sorensen, A, Lenfestey, N, Tant, E, Henriksen, K, LaBresh, K and Singh, H (2012) Cognitive interventions to reduce diagnostic error: a narrative review. BMJ Quality & Safety 21, 535557. doi: 10.1136/bmjqs-2011-000149CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greenhalgh, T (2013) Five biases of new technologies. The British Journal of General Practice 63, 425.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greenhalgh, T, Wherton, J, Papoutsi, C, Lynch, J, Hughes, G, A'Court, C, Hinder, S, Fahy, N, Procter, R and Shaw, S (2017) Beyond adoption: a New framework for theorizing and evaluating nonadoption, abandonment, and challenges to the scale-up, spread, and sustainability of health and care technologies. Journal of Medical Internet Research 19, e367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haas, M, Hall, J, Viney, R and Gallego, G (2012) Breaking up is hard to do: why disinvestment in medical technology is harder than investment. Australian Health Review 36, 148152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, IA (2016) Surgery, the Ultimate Placebo: A Surgeon Cuts Through the Evidence. Sydney: University of New South Wales Press.Google Scholar
Harris, C, Allen, K, Waller, C and Brooke, V (2017a) Sustainability in health care by allocating resources effectively (SHARE) 3: examining how resource allocation decisions are made, implemented and evaluated in a local healthcare setting. BMC Health Services Research 17, 340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, C, Green, S, Ramsey, W, Allen, K and King, R (2017b) Sustainability in health care by allocating resources effectively (SHARE) 9: conceptualising disinvestment in the local healthcare setting. BMC Health Services Research 17, 633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henshall, C, Schuller, T and Mardhani-Bayne, L (2012) Using health technology assessment to support optimal use of technologies in current practice: the challenge of ‘disinvestment’. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 28, 203210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobson, K (2009) Cost of medicine: are high-tech medical devices and treatments always worth it. US News World Rep.Google Scholar
Hofmann, B (1998) Black boxes and white elephants [in Norwegian]. Tidsskrift for Helse Medisinsk Teknikk 5, 3032.Google Scholar
Hofmann, B (2002a) Is there a technological imperative in health care? International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 18, 675689.10.1017/S0266462302000491CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofmann, B (2002b) On the ethics of medical technology [in Norwegian]. HMT – Helsetjenesten Medisinsk Teknikk : Helse, Medisin, Teknikk 9, 2831.Google Scholar
Hofmann, B (2002c) The Technological Invention of Disease – on Disease, Technology and Values. Oslo: University of Oslo.Google Scholar
Hofmann, B (2006) When means become ends: technology producing values. Seminar.net: Media, Technology and Lifelong Learning 2. http://www.seminar.net/current-issue/when-means-become-ends-technology-producing-values.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofmann, B (2010) Too much of a good thing is wonderful? A conceptual analysis of excessive examinations and diagnostic futility in diagnostic radiology. Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy 13, 139148.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hofmann, B (2019a) Progress bias versus status quo bias in the ethics of emerging science and technology. Bioethics: Online Early view.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofmann, B (2019b) Biases and imperatives in handling medical technology. Health Policy and Technology 8, 377385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofmann, B (2020) Biases distorting priority setting. Health Policy 124, 5260.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hofmann, B and Skolbekken, JA (2017) Surge in publications on early detection. BMJ 357, j2102.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hollingworth, W and Chamberlain, C (2011) NICE Recommendations for disinvestment. BMJ 343, d5772.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Howard, L, Wessely, S, Leese, M, Page, L, McCrone, P, Husain, K, Tong, J and Dowson, A (2005) Are investigations anxiolytic or anxiogenic? A randomised controlled trial of neuroimaging to provide reassurance in chronic daily headache. Journal of Neurology Neurosurgery & Psychiatry 76, 15581564.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Iacobucci, G (2018) NHS Proposes to stop funding 17 ‘unnecessary’ procedures. BMJ 362.Google ScholarPubMed
Ibargoyen-Roteta, N, Gutiérrez-Ibarluzea, I and Asua, J (2010) Guiding the process of health technology disinvestment. Health Policy 98, 218226.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Johnson, GL (1982) An opportunity cost view of fixed asset theory and the overproduction trap: comment. The American Journal of Agricultural Economics 64, 773775.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D and Tversky, A (1977) Intuitive Prediction: Biases and Corrective Procedures. Mclean VA: Decisions and Designs Inc.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D and Tversky, A (1996) On the reality of cognitive illusions. Psychological Review 103, 582591.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahneman, D and Tversky, A (2013) Choices, Values, and Frames, Handbook of the Fundamentals of Financial Decision Making: Part I. Singapore: World Scientific 269278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D, Slovic, P and Tversky, A (1982) Judgement under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. New York, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D, Knetsch, JL and Thaler, RH (1991) Anomalies: the endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. The Journal of Economic Perspectives 5, 193206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G and Johnson, M (1999) Philosophy in the Flesh. New York: Basic books.Google Scholar
Lee, CS, Nagy, PG, Weaver, SJ and Newman-Toker, DE (2013) Cognitive and system factors contributing to diagnostic errors in radiology. American Journal of Roentgenology 201, 611617.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levinson, W, Kallewaard, M, Bhatia, RS, Wolfson, D, Shortt, S and Kerr, EA (2015) ‘Choosing wisely’: a growing international campaign. BMJ Quality & Safety 24, 167174.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
MacKean, G, Noseworthy, T, Elshaug, AG, Leggett, L, Littlejohns, P, Berezanski, J and Clement, F (2013) Health technology reassessment: the art of the possible. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 29, 418423.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Malik, H, Marti, J, Darzi, A and Mossialos, E (2018) Savings from reducing low-value general surgical interventions. British Journal of Surgery 105, 1325.10.1002/bjs.10719CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mandell, HN (1983) Technological imperative. Or, when your tool is a hammer, everything looks like a nail. Postgraduate Medicine 74, 2426.Google ScholarPubMed
Mazarr, MJ (2016) Rethinking Risk in National Security: Lessons of the Financial Crisis for Risk Management. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDonald, KM, Matesic, B, Contopoulos-Ioannidis, DG, Lonhart, J, Schmidt, E, Pineda, N and Ioannidis, JP (2013) Patient safety strategies targeted at diagnostic errors: a systematic review. Annals of Internal Medicine 158(5_Part_2), 381389.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Michie, S, Johnston, M, Abraham, C, Lawton, R, Parker, D and Walker, A (2005) Making psychological theory useful for implementing evidence based practice: a consensus approach. BMJ Quality & Safety 14, 2633.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Michie, S, Van Stralen, MM and West, R (2011) The behaviour change wheel: a new method for characterising and designing behaviour change interventions. Implementation Science 6, 42.10.1186/1748-5908-6-42CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Newman-Toker, DE and Pronovost, PJ (2009) Diagnostic errors – the next frontier for patient safety. JAMA 301, 10601062.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Niven, DJ, Mrklas, KJ, Holodinsky, JK, Straus, SE, Hemmelgarn, BR, Jeffs, LP and Stelfox, HT (2015) Towards understanding the de-adoption of low-value clinical practices: a scoping review. BMC Medicine 13, 255.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Noseworthy, T and Clement, F (2012) Health technology reassessment: scope, methodology, & language. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 28, 201202.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Okonofua, EC, Simpson, KN, Jesri, A, Rehman, SU, Durkalski, VL and Egan, BM (2006) Therapeutic inertia is an impediment to achieving the healthy people 2010 blood pressure control goals. Hypertension 47, 345351.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Parkinson, B, Sermet, C, Clement, F, Crausaz, S, Godman, B and Garner, S (2015) Disinvestment and value-based purchasing strategies for pharmaceuticals: an international review. Pharmacoeconomics 33, 905924.10.1007/s40273-015-0293-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pathirana, T, Clark, J and Moynihan, R (2017) Mapping the drivers of overdiagnosis to potential solutions. BMJ 358, j3879.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Polisena, J, Clifford, T, Elshaug, AG, Mitton, C, Russell, E and Skidmore, B (2013) Case studies that illustrate disinvestment and resource allocation decision-making processes in health care: a systematic review. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 29, 174184.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Prusaczyk, B, Swindle, T and Curran, G (2020) Defining and conceptualizing outcomes for de-implementation: key distinctions from implementation outcomes. Implementation Science Communications 1, 43.10.1186/s43058-020-00035-3CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Raffle, A and Muir Gray, J (2007) Screening: Evidence and Practice. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rank, B (2008) Executive physicals – bad medicine on three counts. New England Journal of Medicine 359, 14241425.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reach, G, Pechtner, V, Gentilella, R, Corcos, A and Ceriello, A (2017) Clinical inertia and its impact on treatment intensification in people with type 2 diabetes mellitus. Diabetes & Metabolism 43, 503511. doi: 10.1016/j.diabet.2017.06.003.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ruano-Raviña, A, Velasco-González, M, Varela Lema, L, Cerdá-Mota, T, Ibargoyen Roteta, N and Gutiérrez Ibarluzea, I (2007) Identification, prioritisation and assessment of obsolete health technologies. A methodological guideline. HTA Reports: avalia-t Madrid, Ministry of Science & Innovation.Google Scholar
Saini, V, Brownlee, S, Elshaug, AG, Glasziou, P and Heath, I (2017a) Addressing overuse and underuse around the world. Lancet 390, 105107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saini, V, Garcia-Armesto, S, Klemperer, D, Paris, V, Elshaug, AG, Brownlee, S, Ioannidis, JP and Fisher, ES (2017b) Drivers of poor medical care. Lancet 390, 178190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saposnik, G and Montalban, X (2018) Therapeutic inertia in the new landscape of multiple sclerosis care. Frontiers in Neurology 9, 174.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Saposnik, G, Redelmeier, D, Ruff, CC and Tobler, PN (2016) Cognitive biases associated with medical decisions: a systematic review. BMC Medical Informatics and Decision Making 16, 138.10.1186/s12911-016-0377-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Saririan, M and Eisenberg, M (2003) Myocardial laser revascularization for the treatment of end-stage coronary artery disease. American Journal of Cardiology 41, 173183.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sauro, K, Bagshaw, SM, Niven, D, Soo, A, Brundin-Mather, R, Leigh, JP, Cook, DJ and Stelfox, HT (2019) Barriers and facilitators to adopting high value practices and de-adopting low value practices in Canadian intensive care units: a multimethod study. BMJ Open 9, e024159.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schmidt, DE (2012) The development of a disinvestment framework to guide resource allocation decisions in health service delivery organizations. University of British Columbia.Google Scholar
Schwartz, AL, Landon, BE, Elshaug, AG, Chernew, ME and McWilliams, JM (2014) Measuring low-value care in Medicare. JAMA Internal Medicine 174, 10671076.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scotland, G and Bryan, S (2017) Why do health economists promote technology adoption rather than the search for efficiency? A proposal for a change in our approach to economic evaluation in health care. Medical Decision Making 37, 139147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott, IA and Duckett, SJ (2015) In search of professional consensus in defining and reducing low-value care. Medical Journal of Australia 203, 179181.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scott, I and Elshaug, A (2013) Foregoing low-value care: how much evidence is needed to change beliefs? Internal Medicine Journal 43, 107109.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Selby, K, Gaspoz, J-M, Rodondi, N, Neuner-Jehle, S, Perrier, A, Zeller, A and Cornuz, J (2015) Creating a list of low-value health care activities in Swiss primary care. JAMA Internal Medicine 175, 640642.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shain, M and Roemer, MI (1959) Hospital costs relate to the supply of beds. Journal of Occupational and Environmental Medicine 1, 518.Google Scholar
Slovic, P (2016) The Perception of Risk. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slovic, P and Peters, E (2006) Risk perception and affect. Current Directions in Psychological Science 15, 322325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomons, NM and Spross, JA (2011) Evidence-based practice barriers and facilitators from a continuous quality improvement perspective: an integrative review. Journal of Nursing Management 19, 109120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soril, LJ, MacKean, G, Noseworthy, TW, Leggett, LE and Clement, FM (2017) Achieving optimal technology use: a proposed model for health technology reassessment. Sage Open Medicine 5, 2050312117704861.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Soril, LJJ, Seixas, BV, Mitton, C, Bryan, S and Clement, FM (2018) Moving low value care lists into action: prioritizing candidate health technologies for reassessment using administrative data. BMC Health Services Research 18, 640.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Strand, R, Saltelli, A, Giampietro, M, Rommetveit, K and Funtowicz, S (2016) New narratives for innovation. Journal of Cleaner Production 197, 18491853.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tinghög, G and Västfjäll, D (2018) Why People Hate Health Economics – Two Psychological Explanations, Linköping University, Division of Economics, Department of Management and Engineering.Google Scholar
Tymstra, T (1989) The imperative character of medical technology and the meaning of ‘anticipated decision regret’. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 5, 207213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Bodegom-Vos, L, Davidoff, F and Marang-van de Mheen, PJ (2017) Implementation and de-implementation: two sides of the same coin? BMJ Quality & Safety 26, 495501.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Welch, HG and Black, WC (2010) Overdiagnosis in cancer. Journal of the National Cancer Institute 102, 605613.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Welch, HG, Schwartz, L and Woloshin, S (2011) Overdiagnosed: Making People Sick in the Pursuit of Health. Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Willson, A (2015) The problem with eliminating ‘low-value care’. BMJ Quality & Safety 24, 611614.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilmshurst, P (2011) The regulation of medical devices. Unsatisfactory, unscientific, and in need of a major overhaul. BMJ 342, d2822.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, TD and Brekke, N (1994) Mental contamination and mental correction: unwanted influences on judgments and evaluations. Psychological Bulletin 116, 117.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wolf, S and Berle, B (1981) The Technological Imperative in Medicine. New York: Plenum Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, B and Bragge, P (2017) What strategies to review diagnoses are feasible and sustainable in Emergency Departments?. Melbourne, Australia: Behaviour Works Australia, Monash University. ISSN: 2208-6080.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Overview of various mechanisms undermining reassessment and disinvestment

Figure 1

Figure 1. Flowchart of questions with respect to addressing reassessment and disinvestment.