Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-21T23:32:55.885Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Genomics and insurance in the United Kingdom: increasing complexity and emerging challenges

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 May 2024

Padraig Dixon*
Affiliation:
Nuffield Department of Primary Care Health Sciences, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK Centre for Personalised Medicine, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK
Rachel H. Horton
Affiliation:
Centre for Personalised Medicine, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK Clinical Ethics, Law and Society research group, Wellcome Centre for Human Genetics, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK
William G. Newman
Affiliation:
Evolution, Infection and Genomics, School of Biological Sciences, University of Manchester, Manchester, UK Manchester Centre for Genomic Medicine, Manchester University NHS Foundation Trust, Manchester, UK
John H. McDermott
Affiliation:
Evolution, Infection and Genomics, School of Biological Sciences, University of Manchester, Manchester, UK Manchester Centre for Genomic Medicine, Manchester University NHS Foundation Trust, Manchester, UK
Anneke Lucassen
Affiliation:
Centre for Personalised Medicine, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK Clinical Ethics, Law and Society research group, Wellcome Centre for Human Genetics, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK
*
Corresponding author: Padraig Dixon; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article identifies issues relating to the use of genetics and genomics in risk-rated insurance that may challenge existing regulatory models in the UK and elsewhere. We discuss three core issues: (1) As genomic testing advances, and results are increasingly relevant to guide healthcare across an individual's lifetime, the distinction between diagnostic and predictive testing that the current UK insurance code relies on becomes increasingly blurred. (2) The emerging category of pharmacogenetic tests that are predictive only in the context of a specific prescribing moment. (3) The increasing availability and affordability of polygenic scores that are neither clearly diagnostic nor highly predictive, but which nonetheless might have incremental value for risk-rated insurance underwriting beyond conventional factors. We suggest a deliberative approach is required to establish when and how genetic information can be used in risk-rated insurance.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

This article identifies emerging issues relating to the use of genomics and geneticsFootnote 1 in insurance. These issues relate to clinical, research, technological and economic developments that may disrupt prevailing regulatory models intended to support the efficient and equitable provision of insurance. Our focus is on the specific regulatory context of the United Kingdom, but the general issues we raise will apply to varying extents in other jurisdictions.

Diagnostic tests for genetic conditions began to be used by the UK insurance industry to inform offers of cover in the 1990s, in light of which a ‘Genetic Testing Code of Practice’ was introduced by the Association of British Insurers (ABI) in December 1997 (House of Commons Science and Technology Committee, 2001). A version of this agreement has existed in various forms ever since and has been subject to amendments over time (Department of Halth and Social Care, 2022). The current version of the Code, a voluntary agreement between the UK government and the ABI, refers to two types of genetic test.

Diagnostic genetic tests are defined as those that confirm or rule out a diagnosis. Predictive genetic tests assess future disease risk. These tests were first offered in the context of a previously identified familial ‘genetic disorder’ to see whether an individual might develop the condition in the future. They were therefore typically only offered to people with a personal or family history that strongly suggested a genetic condition. In this scenario, if a potentially concerning variant was identified there was a much higher probability of it being medically relevant, permitting greater confidence in diagnosis.

The Code applies to life, critical illness, and income protection insurance, although we consider issues affecting other forms of insurance below in the context of emerging challenges that may go beyond the current version of the Code, or which may arise in other countries. The Code embodies two core principles. The first prohibits insurers from requiring or pressuring applicants for insurance policies to take either type of genetic test. The second relates to predictive tests. While the Code permits consideration by insurers of diagnostic genetic test results, predictive tests results may be considered only if the test is specifically named in the Code and if the financial sum to be assured exceeds limits defined in the Code. Only one such test currently meets these criteria, which is a predictive genetic test for Huntington's disease in relation to applications for life insurance cover over £500,000. The Code does not prevent the use of family history for a disease or trait. Strongly heritable conditions will sometimes have a family history and insurers can and do use this information as an indirect genetic test of disease risk.

A long-standing concern (Holmes, Reference Holmes1996; Daniels, Reference Daniels and Rothstein2004; Ossa and Towse, Reference Ossa and Towse2004; Prince, Reference Prince2018, Reference Prince2017; Rothstein, Reference Rothstein2018; Joly et al., Reference Joly, Dalpé, Dupras, Bévière-Boyer, De Paor, Dove, Moreno, Ho, Ho and Cathaoir2020a, Reference Joly, Dupras, Pinkesz, Tovino and Rothstein2020b; Prince et al., Reference Prince, Uhlmann, Suter and Scherer2021; Tiller et al., Reference Tiller, Bakshi, Brotchie, Green, Winship and Lacaze2023) that motivated the original version of the code and its subsequent iterations has been the possibility of genetic discrimination, which could involve the denial of insurance, restrictions to coverage or substantially higher premiums to those with particular genetic profiles (Harper, Reference Harper1992; Holmes, Reference Holmes1996; Maxwell et al., Reference Maxwell, Russell, Wu, Sharapova, Banthorpe, O'Reilly and Lewis2021). This could lead to individuals refusing to take genetic tests that were otherwise indicated for fear that their results (or the mere fact of taking the test) could result in exclusion or unfavourable terms when seeking insurance. On the other side of the market, prohibitions or limitations on the ability of insurers to use genetic information in risk-based pricing could threaten their commercial viability or lead to the withdrawal of particular insurance products (Born Reference Born2019).

These types of concern were, in some cases, motivated by an expectation that most genetic tests would be highly predictive, leading to this testing being potentially discriminating (Macdonald and Yu, Reference Macdonald and Yu2011). However, although many genetic traits are highly penetrant, a large proportion are not, meaning that testing for these genetic variants in unaffected individuals may not be as predictive as once imagined. To date, evidence from annual reports on the operation of the Code (ABI, 2022) suggests genetic information on insurance been limited in all but a few cases. However, these reports cannot determine how many people have elected not to declare genetic risks (when they are not obliged to do so), and therefore do not necessarily fully reflect the impact of these arrangements on insurance decisions. In any event, advances in technology that enable the identification of more subtle genetic contributions to disease susceptibility, longevity and drug responses may merit new forms of oversight to support the interests of both insurers and their policyholders (Roberts et al., Reference Roberts, Dolinoy and Tarini2014; Peter et al., Reference Peter, Richter and Thistle2017; Rothstein, Reference Rothstein2018; Born Reference Born2019; Conley, Reference Conley2019; Tiller et al., Reference Tiller, Morris, Rice, Barter, Riaz, Keogh, Delatycki, Otlowski and Lacaze2020; Rodriguez-Rincon et al., Reference Rodriguez-Rincon, Parkinson, Hocking, Evans, Hudson and Morley2022).

We describe three developments that may increase the salience of genetic data for insurance. The first issue relates to a blurring of the distinction between diagnostic and predictive genetic tests, the second to similar issues in the context of pharmacogenetics, and the third to the prediction of healthcare costs, mortality, and related phenotypes. We discuss these three issues below after first briefly reviewing the principles of insurance in the context of actuarial fairness and wider considerations (beyond actuarial fairness) that may have a bearing on how genetic tests might be used in insurance.

2. Insurance, actuarial fairness and wider considerations regarding genomics

Insurance protects against losses associated with unpredictable events. While an event may be probable (such as some form of prolonged ill health) or certain (death), its timing and consequences are likely to be unpredictable. Faced with uncertainty about the timing, scope and extent of these events, individuals derive value from pooling risks with others in the population. Within a risk pool, the majority of individuals who do not make claims contribute to meet the cost of the minority who do make claims. Our discussion of insurance in this paper refers throughout to risk-rated insurance, as opposed to, for example, community-rated insurance which is a method of determining insurance premiums based on the overall risk profile of a community or group rather than on individual characteristics.

The premium and terms of risk-rated insurance contracts reflect the risk that a prospective customer may experience an event that gives rise to a claim, as well as the costs borne by the insurer in providing cover. Higher assessed risk generally results in higher premiums to be paid by customers, and/or more restrictive contract terms. The converse will generally be true for lower assessed risk. From an actuarial perspective, a fair insurance contract is one that accurately prices risk. Systematic mispricing of insurance by a single provider, in the sense of overcharging or undercharging certain groups given the risks and therefore the costs associated with each group, will result in a competitive disadvantage and will not be sustainable.

If genetic factors, broadly defined, influence the risk of insurable events, then their use in insurance underwriting will contribute to actuarial fairness in the pricing of risk, and the efficient operation of the insurance market as a whole. Reliance on actuarial fairness ‘expresses the moral judgment that fair underwriting practices must reflect the division of people according to actuarially accurate determination of their risks’ (Daniels, Reference Daniels and Rothstein2004). Wider considerations in relation to the use of genetics in insurance beyond actuarial concerns may involve access to insurance by different groups, the cost and quality of insurance, and privacy issues. These wider considerations motivate the existence of the Code, as well as other international examples that treat genetic information differently to other rating factors used in insurance underwriting.

These international examples include the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act (GINA) in the United States (Bélisle-Pipon et al., Reference Bélisle-Pipon, Vayena, Green and Glenn Cohen2019), which prohibits the use of genetic information in determining the offer of health insurance, but not necessarily other forms of insurance including life insurance. The Genetic Non-Discrimination Act (Bombard and Heim-Myers, Reference Bombard and Heim-Myers2018; Bélisle-Pipon et al., Reference Bélisle-Pipon, Vayena, Green and Glenn Cohen2019; Supreme Court of Canada, 2020) in Canada prohibits requesting disclosure of the results of genetic tests or being forced to take such tests in order to obtain access to goods and services including insurance. The Australian life insurance industry introduced a partial, self-regulated ban on the use of genetic results in 2019, and debates continue on whether this moratorium is fit for purpose (Tiller et al., Reference Tiller, Bakshi, Dowling, Keogh, McInerney-Leo, Barlow-Stewart, Boughtwood, Gleeson, Delatycki and Winship2024; Tiller and Lacaze, Reference Tiller and Lacaze2023).

As we assess emerging challenges posed by genomics to insurance, and specifically in the regulatory context of the United Kingdom, we consider challenges both to the process of underwriting (‘how much risk is attributable to a particular person?’), to these wider considerations that may give rise to departures from actuarial fairness in offers of insurance, and finally to the operation of the insurance market itself. We examine these challenges under three primary themes, as follows.

The first relates to the fact that, as genetic testing routinely encompasses ever greater portions of the genome, the distinction in the Code between diagnostic and predictive genetic testing becomes blurred. A ‘typical’ person has around 100,000 rare variants in their genome (Auton et al., Reference Auton, Abecasis, Altshuler, Durbin, Abecasis, Bentley, Chakravarti, Clark, Donnelly, Eichler, Flicek, Gabriel, Gibbs, Green, Hurles, Knoppers, Korbel, Lander, Lee, Lehrach, Mardis, Marth, McVean, Nickerson, Schmidt, Sherry, Wang, Wilson, Gibbs, Boerwinkle, Doddapaneni, Han, Korchina, Kovar, Lee, Muzny, Reid, Zhu, Wang, Chang, Feng, Fang, Guo, Jian, Jiang, Jin, Lan, Li, Li, Li, Liu, Liu, Lu, Ma, Tang, Wang, Wang, Wu, Wu, Xu, Yin, Zhang, Zhang, Zhao, Zhao, Zheng, Lander, Altshuler, Gabriel, Gupta, Gharani, Toji, Gerry, Resch, Flicek, Barker, Clarke, Gil, Hunt, Kelman, Kulesha, Leinonen, McLaren, Radhakrishnan, Roa, Smirnov, Smith, Streeter, Thormann, Toneva, Vaughan, Zheng-Bradley, Bentley, Grocock, Humphray, James, Kingsbury, Lehrach, Sudbrak, Albrecht, Amstislavskiy, Borodina, Lienhard, Mertes, Sultan, Timmermann, Yaspo, Mardis, Wilson, Fulton, Fulton, Sherry, Ananiev, Belaia, Beloslyudtsev, Bouk, Chen, Church, Cohen, Cook, Garner, Hefferon, Kimelman, Liu, Lopez, Meric, O'Sullivan, Ostapchuk, Phan, Ponomarov, Schneider, Shekhtman, Sirotkin, Slotta, Zhang, McVean, Durbin, Balasubramaniam, Burton, Danecek, Keane, Kolb-Kokocinski, McCarthy, Stalker, Quail, Schmidt, Davies, Gollub, Webster, Wong, Zhan, Auton, Campbell, Kong, Marcketta, Gibbs, Yu, Antunes, Bainbridge, Muzny, Sabo, Huang, Wang, Coin, Fang, Guo, Jin, Li, Li, Li, Li, Lin, Liu, Luo, Shao, Xie, Ye, Yu, Zhang, Zheng, Zhu, Alkan, Dal, Kahveci, Marth, Garrison, Kural, Lee, Leong, Stromberg, Ward, Wu, Zhang, Daly, DePristo, Handsaker, Altshuler, Banks, Bhatia, del Angel, Gabriel, Genovese, Gupta, Li, Kashin, Lander, McCarroll, Nemesh, Poplin, Yoon, Lihm, Makarov, Clark, Gottipati, Keinan, Rodriguez-Flores, Korbel, Rausch, Fritz, Stütz, Flicek, Beal, Clarke, Datta, Herrero, McLaren, Ritchie, Smith, Zerbino, Zheng-Bradley, Sabeti, Shlyakhter, Schaffner, Vitti, Cooper, Ball, Stenson, Bentley, Barnes, Bauer, Keira Cheetham, Cox, Eberle, Humphray, Kahn, Murray, Peden, Shaw, Kenny, Batzer, Konkel, Walker, MacArthur, Lek, Sudbrak, Amstislavskiy, Herwig, Mardis, Ding, Koboldt, Larson, Ye and Gravel2015) – some of these may help diagnose a condition already known about, others may predict disease (with varying degrees of accuracy) and yet others be entirely uncertain as to what their effects may be. This blurs the distinction alluded to in the Code. This blurring may also increase the challenges of underwriting (given uncertainty associated with the interpretation of results), with wider considerations relating to the equitable processing of this information, and with the wider operation of the market (given the resources necessary to process increasing volumes of genetic data).

The second area relates to pharmacogenetics, which is the study of how genetic variation can affect an individual's response to medicines. However, predictions of response at an individual level are imperfect, the medicine in question may never be required, and identification of the risk of serious adverse events could increase the cost of future healthcare and therefore potentially the costs of insurance (if no effective alternative treatments are available) or reduce these costs (if treatment is more effective when informed by pharmacogenetics). Again, pharmacogenetics seems likely to blur the diagnostic/predictive distinction at the centre of the Code, and will likely have implications for underwriting and for equitable access to insurance.

The third area relates to predicting costs, mortality and related phenotypes from genotype, especially in the context of increasing availability and affordability of composite indices of disease liability such as ‘polygenic scores’ that measure a component of risk for common disease. These tests may be neither clearly diagnostic nor highly predictive, and the contribution of a polygenic score to absolute risk may be very small. Nonetheless, polygenic scores could add some value to underwriting beyond conventional factors, which, absent other considerations, would result in better pricing of risk. However, it is these other considerations that merit a wider debate on appropriate uses of this type of information. There may also be market-wide impacts under differential access to this information.

We explore each of these topics in more detail in the following sections.

3. The blurring of the distinction between diagnostic and predictive tests

The cost of genetic testing continues to fall, and the volume of data that such testing produces continues to increase (Horton and Lucassen, Reference Horton and Lucassen2019). Whilst in the past only certain variants were analysed based on a clinical suspicion of their presence, ‘genome first’ approaches facilitated by technological advances identify many more variants that may have implications for the individual concerned, and interpreting their significance can be very challenging. To place the scale of variation in context, there are on average 4–5 million differences between the reference human genome and any typical human genome (Auton et al., Reference Auton, Abecasis, Altshuler, Durbin, Abecasis, Bentley, Chakravarti, Clark, Donnelly, Eichler, Flicek, Gabriel, Gibbs, Green, Hurles, Knoppers, Korbel, Lander, Lee, Lehrach, Mardis, Marth, McVean, Nickerson, Schmidt, Sherry, Wang, Wilson, Gibbs, Boerwinkle, Doddapaneni, Han, Korchina, Kovar, Lee, Muzny, Reid, Zhu, Wang, Chang, Feng, Fang, Guo, Jian, Jiang, Jin, Lan, Li, Li, Li, Liu, Liu, Lu, Ma, Tang, Wang, Wang, Wu, Wu, Xu, Yin, Zhang, Zhang, Zhao, Zhao, Zheng, Lander, Altshuler, Gabriel, Gupta, Gharani, Toji, Gerry, Resch, Flicek, Barker, Clarke, Gil, Hunt, Kelman, Kulesha, Leinonen, McLaren, Radhakrishnan, Roa, Smirnov, Smith, Streeter, Thormann, Toneva, Vaughan, Zheng-Bradley, Bentley, Grocock, Humphray, James, Kingsbury, Lehrach, Sudbrak, Albrecht, Amstislavskiy, Borodina, Lienhard, Mertes, Sultan, Timmermann, Yaspo, Mardis, Wilson, Fulton, Fulton, Sherry, Ananiev, Belaia, Beloslyudtsev, Bouk, Chen, Church, Cohen, Cook, Garner, Hefferon, Kimelman, Liu, Lopez, Meric, O'Sullivan, Ostapchuk, Phan, Ponomarov, Schneider, Shekhtman, Sirotkin, Slotta, Zhang, McVean, Durbin, Balasubramaniam, Burton, Danecek, Keane, Kolb-Kokocinski, McCarthy, Stalker, Quail, Schmidt, Davies, Gollub, Webster, Wong, Zhan, Auton, Campbell, Kong, Marcketta, Gibbs, Yu, Antunes, Bainbridge, Muzny, Sabo, Huang, Wang, Coin, Fang, Guo, Jin, Li, Li, Li, Li, Lin, Liu, Luo, Shao, Xie, Ye, Yu, Zhang, Zheng, Zhu, Alkan, Dal, Kahveci, Marth, Garrison, Kural, Lee, Leong, Stromberg, Ward, Wu, Zhang, Daly, DePristo, Handsaker, Altshuler, Banks, Bhatia, del Angel, Gabriel, Genovese, Gupta, Li, Kashin, Lander, McCarroll, Nemesh, Poplin, Yoon, Lihm, Makarov, Clark, Gottipati, Keinan, Rodriguez-Flores, Korbel, Rausch, Fritz, Stütz, Flicek, Beal, Clarke, Datta, Herrero, McLaren, Ritchie, Smith, Zerbino, Zheng-Bradley, Sabeti, Shlyakhter, Schaffner, Vitti, Cooper, Ball, Stenson, Bentley, Barnes, Bauer, Keira Cheetham, Cox, Eberle, Humphray, Kahn, Murray, Peden, Shaw, Kenny, Batzer, Konkel, Walker, MacArthur, Lek, Sudbrak, Amstislavskiy, Herwig, Mardis, Ding, Koboldt, Larson, Ye and Gravel2015) – and many of these differences will have minor or unknown medical impact.

Indeed, large numbers of variants that have historically been considered to be pathogenic (i.e. associated with specific health outcomes) have in fact turned out to be common in individuals who do not show the associated phenotype, suggesting that either their original classification was wrong, or that their impact on health is more subtle or context-dependent than previously appreciated.

Beaumont and Wright (Reference Beaumont and Wright2022) illustrated the challenge of interpreting people's genomic data, showing that while large gene panels may maximise diagnostic yield, they are also likely to identify several variants that look hypothetically concerning though are probably benign; most people have at least one rare variant in the coding regions of the genome in panels containing over five hundred disease genes. Even for ‘well-understood’ pathogenic genetic variants, context matters: Jackson et al. (Reference Jackson, Weedon, Harrison, Wood, Ruth, Tyrrell and Wright2022) found that people with cancer-predisposing genetic variants were at significantly less elevated risk of cancer in the absence of a family history. These issues are likely to be amplified by initiatives to undertake whole genome sequencing of all newborn children within a population.

The predictive value of a specific variant identified via genetic testing in the absence of phenotype and positive family history may therefore be low (Horton et al., Reference Horton, Crawford, Freeman, Fenwick, Wright and Lucassen2019; Horton and Lucassen, Reference Horton and Lucassen2019; Horton and Lucassen, Reference Horton and Lucassen2022). As genetic tests become broader, a distinction has emerged between using genetic results for diagnoses (in tandem with other clinical information) and the use of genetic data for other purposes (such as prediction of disease risk) outside of a clear familial or phenotypic context. For example, in the former case, a high degree of confidence might be expected in reaching an overall diagnostic assessment for a particular individual. In the latter, inferences about disease risk are likely to be less meaningful at the level of the individual.

This changing distinction between diagnostic and predictive results may also be influenced in some contexts by prognostic information. For example, in some cases an underlying genetic cause for a clinical diagnosis may change the prognosis associated with a particular condition. For example, knowledge that an individual has congenital long QT syndrome (which is associated with irregular or abnormal heart beats) may change the prognosis associated with the risk of future cardiac arrests (Arthur et al., Reference Arthur, Ahmad and Postema Pieter2022).

There is also increasing interest in (Sud et al., Reference Sud, Horton, Hingorani, Tzoulaki, Turnbull, Houlston and Lucassen2023) aggregated summaries (typically referred to as polygenic risk scores) analysing many points of variation in the genome to estimate liability to disease incidence, disease progression or related outcomes. Does knowledge that an individual has high polygenic risk for a particular condition constitute a genetic ‘result’? Without additional information, knowledge that an individual is in the top decile or even the top percentile of a polygenic distribution for incident disease may indicate only a marginal increase in lifetime risk, and furthermore could miss most cases that occur in people in other centiles.

For example, women in the top 5 per cent of polygenic risk for ovarian cancer have a lifetime risk of 2.1 per cent for developing this condition, compared to a population average risk of 1.6 per cent (Sud et al., Reference Sud, Turnbull and Houlston2021). The overall distribution of the polygenic risk at the population level may be informative for disease aetiology, even if knowledge of an individual's polygenic risk in itself does not contribute much, if anything, to knowledge of ‘which particular individuals will succumb’ (Davey Smith, Reference Smith2011) to the condition of interest. Below, we explore other potential consequences of polygenic scores for insurance in the context of increasing knowledge of the association between genotype and healthcare costs.

These discussions illustrate that the distinction between predictive and diagnostic codes in the Code, based primarily on the presence or absence of symptoms, may be increasingly difficult to defend since this binary distinction may not be especially relevant to the insurance decision. Of note in this regard is that the UK Government opened a consultation in the second half of 2023 on whether (amongst other issues for which evidence was requested) the Code should widen the considerations used to characterise whether a predictive test should be disclosed. The consultation was structured around four questions: (1) How useful is the genetic test for characterising the risk of developing a condition? (2) How many people take the test? (3) What is the impact of the condition in terms of the length and quality of life of people who develop it? (4) What is the potential for reducing the risk of developing the condition and managing its effects if it develops?

We note that these questions highlight a recognition that topics such as penetrance need consideration (since the ‘usefulness’ of a genetic test in characterising disease risk is a function of penetrance) and that this moves away from the symptomatic/asymptomatic distinction that is central to the current Code. For example, highly penetrant risk-increasing BRCA variants are predictive of future risk and may have material consequences for future healthcare costs (of particular interest to a health insurer) and for mortality (of particular interest to a life insurer).

3.1 Insurance industry perspectives

Even if genetic variants found by genomic tests can – in certain contexts – help predict disease, one may argue that no changes to current practices are required. This would be the case if, in fairly assessing risks, insurers recognise that many apparently pathogenic genetic variants may in fact turn out to be clinically insignificant, and as such avoid gross distortions to the pricing of risk. However, the situation may be more complicated than this given the responses that insurers and individuals may have to genetic information. Lacaze et al. (Reference Lacaze, Ryan, Woods, Winship and McNeil2017) note that this depends on the insurer ‘actually understanding’ the genetic concepts involved in influencing risk. Ashcroft (Reference Ashcroft2007) refers to irrational discrimination by insurers arising from ‘false beliefs’ about genetic information. In this case, the identification of a variant, or a combination of variants, may at best lead to mispricing of the associated risk, or at worst an actuarially unjustified refusal to insure an individual. In either case, there would be too little insurance offered at too high a price.

For example, pathogenic variants in MYBPC3 gene increase the risk of developing hypertrophic cardiomyopathy, a disease caused by dysfunction in the cardiac muscles which can lead to arrhythmia and sudden death (Marston et al., Reference Marston, Copeland, Gehmlich, Schlossarek and Carrrier2012). Many people, even within the same family, with the same pathogenic MYBPC3 variant may have no or few symptoms, will never develop hypertrophic cardiomyopathy and are unaware that they have this genotype (Marian and Braunwald, Reference Marian and Braunwald2017). These individuals are at increased risk of developing hypertrophic cardiomyopathy but the genetic test result itself does not mean they have the condition. Nevertheless, some individuals with these variants (and not necessarily expressing the associated phenotype) are reported to have encountered potentially unjustified obstacles when applying for insurance (Christiaans et al., Reference Christiaans, Kok, van Langen, Birnie, Bonsel, Wilde and Smets2010).

These possibilities and concerns are also informed by historical precedents for these practices in relation to new and complex health challenges such as the emergence of HIV. For example, following guidelines issued in 1987 by the Association of British Insurers, applicants for life insurance to almost all UK insurers were asked if they had taken an HIV antibody test (Barton and Roth, Reference Barton and Roth1992). This led to concerns that merely taking the test would lead to insurance being withheld or becoming more expensive, and moreover could lead to serious health consequences by deterring people from HIV testing, leading to increased rates of HIV transmission (Barton and Roth, Reference Barton and Roth1992).

3.2 Consumer perspectives

A further consideration relates to the responses of individuals, and potential excessive insurance against negligible risks associated with variants that could theoretically increase the risk of developing a given phenotype but which ultimately are likely to be clinically insignificant. As McLean and Gannon (Reference McLean, Gannon and Sorrell1998) put it, ‘…the aura of scientific certainty which pervades much of the discourse on genetics may lead the unwary or the ignorant into weighing genetic evidence more heavily in the decision-making scales than is actually merited’.

Viewed from one perspective, this may not require policy intervention if individuals are considered to be the most competent judges of their own self-interest. However, concerns about the consequences of exaggerated expectations regarding the informativeness of genetic tests for future disease risk, such as increased, but unwarranted, demand on primary care, may provide a rationale for intervention. On the other hand, there is evidence that some at-risk individuals refuse or are inclined to refuse genetic testing from fear of discrimination by insurers (Hall and Rich, Reference Hall and Rich2000; Allain et al., Reference Allain, Friedman and Senter2012; Haga et al., Reference Haga, Barry, Mills, Ginsburg, Svetkey, Sullivan and Willard2013; Robinson et al., Reference Robinson, Carroll, Feuerman, Perry, Hoffman-Andrews, Walsh, Christensen, Green and McGuire2016; Wauters and Van Hoyweghen, Reference Wauters and Van Hoyweghen2016).

3.3 Market and system-level perspectives

The resources needed to confirm the consequences for an individual of a particular genetic variant or variants may be considerable, and in some cases there will be no known consequences for an individual's health. These resources, all with competing alternative uses, include patient time, clinical input and potentially also financial consequences for the individual as well as the health system concerned. For example, McGurk et al. (Reference McGurk, Zheng, Henry, Josephs, Edwards, de Marvao, Whiffin, Roberts, Lumbers, O'Regan and Ware2022) considered recommendations for reporting of secondary findings in clinical sequencing following the list of secondary findings noted by the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics that should be sought routinely. One example is the TTN gene; particular variants in this gene predispose to dilated cardiomyopathy (DCM), yet the lifetime risk of DCM for those with this variant is low. Some 8,000 person years of surveillance (amounting to 1,600 cardiovascular magnetic resonance scans under a 5-yearly imaging schedule) in the UK Biobank population (a cohort of middle-aged and early-old age individuals with the approximate age for presentation of DCM) are necessary to prevent one death over the subsequent four years. The yields of one-off and serial evaluation might be expected to be lower in younger individuals.

4. Pharmacogenetics

The complexities in defining which results merit intervention, and when, also arise in the context of pharmacogenetics. Response to medicines varies between individuals, in part, because of genetic variation. If a pharmacogenetic test determines that an individual is less likely to respond to a certain medication, it may be recommended to select an alternative treatment (if available). However, this alternative medicine may, on average in the population, be less effective than the ‘first-line’ therapy. Although this individual is receiving the most suitable treatment for them, it remains an inferior therapeutic strategy compared to what an individual without the pharmacogenetic variant would receive. Alongside the health consequences for the individual concerned, this has implications for potential future treatment costs. Pharmacogenetic testing may predict treatment options to some extent and confer an increased or decreased chance of response to therapy, but such findings are not usually thought of as diagnostic, again highlighting that the diagnostic/predictive classification may be less useful in this setting.

For example, CYP2C19 is an important drug metabolising enzyme (Gaedigk et al., Reference Gaedigk, Sangkuhl, Whirl-Carrillo, Klein and Steven Leeder2017). Genetic variation in the CYP2C19 gene is associated with diminished tolerance, treatment failure, and adverse reactions for many medicines (Botton et al., Reference Botton, Whirl-Carrillo, Del Tredici, Sangkuhl, Cavallari, Agúndez, Duconge, Michael Lee, Woodahl, Claudio-Campos, Daly, Klein, Pratt, Scnott and Gaedigk2021). For instance, CYP2C19 catalyses the activation of clopidogrel, a widely prescribed anti-platelet drug. Individuals with two CYP2C19 loss-of-function alleles (‘poor metabolisers’) will respond less well to clopidogrel compared to the rest of the population (Scott et al., Reference Scott, Sangkuhl, Stein, Hulot, Mega, Roden, Klein, Sabatine, Johnson and Shuldiner2013).

A genetic result showing that an individual carries a loss of function variant in CYP2C19 means that their CYP2C19 enzyme will have reduced activity. As such, CYP2C19 genotyping could be considered diagnostic in nature. However, the negative clinical impact of being a CYP2C19 poor metaboliser is only experienced in certain contexts, such as when the individual is prescribed clopidogrel. In that regard, one could consider the test to be more akin to a predictive test. This blurring between the diagnostic and predictive creates challenges when attempting to consider the insurance implications of a given pharmacogenetic test result.

4.1 Insurance, consumer and market perspectives

We consider that a greater use of pharmacogenetic testing will further blur the distinction between diagnostic and predictive tests. The actuarial implications of pharmacogenetic drug responsiveness will be difficult to assess, not least because prescribing decision for these kinds of medication will arise for some but not all potential patients. Since improved prescribing would very likely improve patient health in aggregate, it is important that any guidance, regulations or legislation support appropriate prescribing.

5. Predicting costs, mortality and related phenotypes from genotype

Genetic rating factors that influence the propensity to incur healthcare costs and that influence mortality will be relevant to the actuarial pricing of health and life insurance products. We consider whether these kinds of rating factors might be feasible, and if so the types of wider considerations that merit scrutiny around their use.

Recent evidence has quantified the heritability of future healthcare costs. Heritability refers the proportion of variance in a phenotype that is attributable to genetic variance in a given population. Lakhani et al. (Reference Lakhani, Tierney, Manrai, Yang, Visscher and Patel2019) used an American health insurance dataset to examine the heritability of monthly healthcare cost amongst 56,396 twin pairs. They estimated that the heritability of average monthly cost was 0.29, meaning that 29 per cent of the variance in average monthly healthcare cost between individuals in that study population was attributable to genetic factors. de Zeeuw et al. (Reference de Zeeuw, Voort, Schoonhoven, Nivard, Emery, Hottenga, Willemsen, Dykstra, Zarrabi, Kartopawiro and Boomsma2021) studied 16,726 participants in the Netherlands Twin Register and estimated similar heritabilities between 0.29 and 0.38. Although debates continue about the extent to which twin studies might over-estimate heritability (Young, Reference Young2019), these estimates for healthcare cost heritability suggest measures of genetic liability to incur healthcare costs are potentially relevant to insurance underwriting.

Mendelian randomisation analyses – the use of common genetic variation indicating liability to particular phenotypes in causal instrumental variable analyses – has demonstrated that genotypes associated with a variety of diseases (Dixon et al., Reference Dixon, Harrison, Hollingworth, Davies and Smith2022a), traits (Dixon et al., Reference Dixon, Hollingworth, Harrison, Davies and Smith2020; Hazewinkel et al., Reference Hazewinkel, Richmond, Wade and Dixon2022; Lee et al., Reference Lee, Jukarainen, Dixon, Davies, Smith, Natarajan and Ganna2022) and behaviours (Dixon et al., Reference Dixon, Sallis, Munafo, Smith and Howe2022b) are also associated with healthcare costs and with closely related outcomes such as rates of inpatient hospital admission (Hazewinkel et al., Reference Hazewinkel, Richmond, Wade and Dixon2022). The use of cost phenotypes will be more consequential in health systems that rely on private healthcare insurance, and are unlikely to have a significant impact in tax-payer funded, universal and free-at-delivery health system such as the NHS in the UK.

However, these types of consideration may be important for life insurance in many countries. In relation to mortality risk, Karlsson Linnér and Koellinger (Reference Karlsson Linnér and Koellinger2022) found that a polygenic score could detect a substantially shorter median lifespan in the top decile of total genetic liability independent of other factors used in conventional insurance underwriting. There are emerging examples (such as Insurance Newsnet, 2023) of life insurers using polygenic risk scores for health conditions (rather than mortality risk per se) as a means of encouraging behavioural change such as improved adherence to medication in light of personal knowledge of a polygenic risk.

5.1 Insurance, consumer and market perspectives

While polygenic risk scores for factors used in insurance underwriting may be neither particularly predictive nor diagnostic, the use of this kind of information could improve the actuarial fairness of assessed risk in offers of insurance. However, wider debates are needed on the normative implications of using genetic information on this way – this is the topic of our next section (‘Toward deliberative processes’). A particular issue that may arise in this context is adverse selection.

Unlike in most other markets, the likelihood of incurring significant cost in the process of providing the service of insurance depends in a fundamental way on the unobservable characteristics of the buyer and the unobservable actions this buyer might take (Cutler and Zeckhauser, Reference Cutler, Zeckhauser, Culyer and Newhouse2000). Adverse selection arises in circumstances where individuals who expect to incur high future health costs differentially prefer more generous or comprehensive insurance plans, and individuals who expect relatively low costs select less comprehensive and less expensive plans (Cutler and Zeckhauser, Reference Cutler and Zeckhauser1998).

One means to overcome adverse selection is to reduce the informational asymmetry between customer and insurer so that the latter can more readily identify risks, and offer contracts priced according to individual risk profiles. This, of course, may conflict with the wider concerns and priorities concerning insurance in the presence of more extensive and richer genetic data than the insurance industry has heretofore encountered.

The magnitude of adverse selection informed by knowledge of polygenic risk in relation to longevity or future healthcare costs remains to be assessed, and may be small in general (MacMinn et al., Reference MacMinn, Brockett and Raeburn2007) or large for some groups (Hoy and Witt, Reference Hoy and Witt2007). Overall, there remains little evidence on whether these concerns are having or will have noticeable impacts on the insurance markets concerned. However, given the emerging developments we describe above, there appears to be a strong case for considering whether new arrangements for oversight are merited.

6. Towards deliberative processes

The foregoing considered issues that were specific to the regulatory regime of the UK (specifically the Code), as well as more general issues that may arise both in the UK and elsewhere. A fundamental issue underlying both the specific and general issues to which these emerging developments in genomics give rise for insurance relates to whether and how genetic information merits distinct treatment as a risk factor for risk-rated insurance. The complexities include the uneven way in which genetic information may be revealed (and potentially disclosed) across types of individual, diseases, risk levels and at points in the life course.

A central task that for any new regulatory response that involves wider considerations than the actuarial pricing of genetic risk will therefore be to identify individuals and groups on whom these costs fall and on whom they ought to fall. We do not take a position on which normative perspectives are necessarily appropriate, but instead outline the parameters in which such a debate may be held.

For example, normative considerations might suggest people at risk of some types of condition ought not to lose access to insurance or to face higher premiums because of their genetic risk. A per se rejection of risk-based pricing for these individuals shifts their costs onto those with lower (genetic) risk, with the effect that a cross-subsidy is created from lower to higher-risk individuals. This cross-subsidy may be very modest in scale, although the scale of this impact remains to be determined and overall consequence of rejecting risk-based pricing is unlikely to ‘net off’ to zero costs. For example, depending on the nature of the risks and proportions of people in each risk category, it is possible that the reduction in costs for high risks is not as great as the increase in costs for the low risks. In this scenario, the aggregate costs of insurance become higher for society albeit the extent of increase remains to be established. Moreover, any potential gains from actuarial pricing of genetic risk (such as improved medication adherence incentivised by life insurance policies that request information on polygenic risk) would not be realised.

The risks faced by individuals are not abolished simply because some groups do not face actuarially fair risk-based pricing for their insurance products; instead, there will necessarily be impacts on the price and availability of insurance. There may be second-order effects on the dynamics of competition amongst insurance. For example, adverse selection is still possible even if those with the highest genetic risk do not face premiums based on their actuarial risk. Higher prices amongst the lower risk groups may reduce their use of insurance, resulting in future avoidable health impairments and economic detriment. On the other hand, appropriate regulatory protections could prevent individuals being penalised from undertaking genetic testing where indicated (Filipova-Neumann and Hoy, Reference Filipova-Neumann and Hoy2014).

The analytic challenges therefore involve characterising and modelling the trade-offs involved (Ossa and Towse, Reference Ossa and Towse2004; Wilson, Reference Wilson2006). These trade-offs include the quantitative impact of genetic information on the terms and price of insurance, increasing knowledge of genetic contributions to disease and mortality, the predictive capacity of polygenic and other genetic risk scores, the demand for insurance and the behavioural responses of consumers. If genetic data cannot be used in risk based-pricing, then variables correlated with these data could potentially be used (if available) and this may frustrate to some degree restrictions on the use of genetic data (Pope and Sydnor, Reference Pope and Sydnor2011; Aseervatham et al., Reference Aseervatham, Lex and Spindler2016). The feasibility of finding robust proxies for genetic data may be more limited than for more traditional risk factors such as gender (Oxera, 2010) but this is likely to vary by context.

The normative issues require, we suggest, a deliberative approach to identify what deviations from actuarially fair pricing are appropriate. The final product of a deliberative process is ‘guidance shaped by judgements’ (Culyer, Reference Culyer2006). What judgements matter or ought to matter in this context? A fundamental consideration is to establish which conditions and which genetic risks (and their consequences) society assesses should be borne by the individual and which should be shared more widely.

A starting point is perhaps to recognise the value of insurance, and the need to ensure its sustainable provision. An overarching approach could be to minimise the overall cost of insurance (potentially subject to specific exemptions) and the costs of which are either managed through cross-subsidy imposed on lower risk groups or met through some other mechanism. An alternative starting point could be to ensure that those facing the greatest possible health burden (however defined) from genetic conditions retain access on reasonable terms.

A multitude of other models could be proposed, each of which will embody their own trade-offs and give rise to different cost profiles and health outcomes. This will also give rise to a host of ethical issues. Should the treatment of genetic information be different from other fundamental personal characteristics that influence insurance premiums, such as sex and age? Is discrimination by insurance companies on the basis of genotype normatively the same as discrimination according to sex, the use of which as a rating factor the European Union prohibited in 2012 (Commission, 2012)? Can and should there be separate ethical frameworks for different types of insurance?

7. Conclusion

Insurance is valuable. Well-functioning insurance markets help individuals manage the risk of adverse events whose timing and impact is uncertain. Risk disclosure and actuarial pricing of risk are fundamental to risk-rated insurance underwriting. We considered how developments in genomics could result in unintended impacts on insurers and policy holders, with a particular focus on the regulatory context of the United Kingdom.

We contend that expansions in the volume and quality of genetic data, the blurring of diagnostic and predictive genetic testing, and new evidence on the association between genotype and mortality, healthcare costs and related phenotypes mean that conversations about their consequences and new regulatory developments are now needed. These issues affect both the specific regulatory regime prevailing in the United Kingdom (with the Code's distinction between diagnostic and predictive tests) as well as more general issues regarding whether and to what extent deviations from actuarial pricing of genetic risks are justified. Both the UK-specific issues and the more general issues require deliberative processes to examine how new regulatory approaches relating to the use of genetic data might be developed.

Any new approaches will depend in a fundamental way on normative ideas of fairness. Deviations from actuarial pricing could increase the aggregate costs of insurance, but in doing so could reflect preferences regarding fairness in the accessibility and pricing of insurance that depends on genetic information. Future regulatory developments in this area will likely involve identifying relevant normative principles, quantifying these costs and developing mechanisms for distribution of costs amongst individuals.

Financial support

W. G. N. and J. H. M. are supported by the National Institute for Health and Care Research (NIHR) Manchester Biomedical Research Centre (NIHR203308). J. H. M. is supported by a NIHR Doctoral Fellowship Award (NIHR 301748). The views expressed are those of the authors and not necessarily those of the NIHR or the Department of Health and Social Care. R. H. H.'s work is funded by a Wellcome Trust Research Award for Health Professionals in Humanities and Social Science 218092/A/19/Z. A. L.'s work is supported by funding from a Wellcome Trust collaborative award 208053/B/17/Z.

Competing interests

None.

Footnotes

1 We use ‘genetics’ and ‘genomics’ interchangeably throughout.

References

ABI (2022) ABI Annual Report: Code on Genetic Testing and Insurance. London.Google Scholar
Allain, DC, Friedman, S and Senter, L (2012) Consumer awareness and attitudes about insurance discrimination post enactment of the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act. Familial Cancer 11, 637644. doi: 10.1007/s10689-012-9564-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arthur, AMW, Ahmad, SA and Postema Pieter, G (2022) Diagnosis, management and therapeutic strategies for congenital long QT syndrome. Heart 108, 332. doi: 10.1136/heartjnl-2020-318259Google Scholar
Aseervatham, V, Lex, C and Spindler, M (2016) How do unisex rating regulations affect gender differences in insurance premiums? The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance – Issues and Practice 41, 128160. doi: 10.1057/gpp.2015.22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashcroft, R (2007) Should genetic information be disclosed to insurers? No. BMJ 334, 11971197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Auton, A, Abecasis, GR, Altshuler, DM, Durbin, RM, Abecasis, GR, Bentley, DR, Chakravarti, A, Clark, AG, Donnelly, P, Eichler, EE, Flicek, P, Gabriel, SB, Gibbs, RA, Green, ED, Hurles, ME, Knoppers, BM, Korbel, JO, Lander, ES, Lee, C, Lehrach, H, Mardis, ER, Marth, GT, McVean, GA, Nickerson, DA, Schmidt, JP, Sherry, ST, Wang, J, Wilson, RK, Gibbs, RA, Boerwinkle, E, Doddapaneni, H, Han, Y, Korchina, V, Kovar, C, Lee, S, Muzny, D, Reid, JG, Zhu, Y, Wang, J, Chang, Y, Feng, Q, Fang, X, Guo, X, Jian, M, Jiang, H, Jin, X, Lan, T, Li, G, Li, J, Li, Y, Liu, S, Liu, X, Lu, Y, Ma, X, Tang, M, Wang, B, Wang, G, Wu, H, Wu, R, Xu, X, Yin, Y, Zhang, D, Zhang, W, Zhao, J, Zhao, M, Zheng, X, Lander, ES, Altshuler, DM, Gabriel, SB, Gupta, N, Gharani, N, Toji, LH, Gerry, NP, Resch, AM, Flicek, P, Barker, J, Clarke, L, Gil, L, Hunt, SE, Kelman, G, Kulesha, E, Leinonen, R, McLaren, WM, Radhakrishnan, R, Roa, A, Smirnov, D, Smith, RE, Streeter, I, Thormann, A, Toneva, I, Vaughan, B, Zheng-Bradley, X, Bentley, DR, Grocock, R, Humphray, S, James, T, Kingsbury, Z, Lehrach, H, Sudbrak, R, Albrecht, MW, Amstislavskiy, VS, Borodina, TA, Lienhard, M, Mertes, F, Sultan, M, Timmermann, B, Yaspo, M-L, Mardis, ER, Wilson, RK, Fulton, L, Fulton, R, Sherry, ST, Ananiev, V, Belaia, Z, Beloslyudtsev, D, Bouk, N, Chen, C, Church, D, Cohen, R, Cook, C, Garner, J, Hefferon, T, Kimelman, M, Liu, C, Lopez, J, Meric, P, O'Sullivan, C, Ostapchuk, Y, Phan, L, Ponomarov, S, Schneider, V, Shekhtman, E, Sirotkin, K, Slotta, D, Zhang, H, McVean, GA, Durbin, RM, Balasubramaniam, S, Burton, J, Danecek, P, Keane, TM, Kolb-Kokocinski, A, McCarthy, S, Stalker, J, Quail, M, Schmidt, JP, Davies, CJ, Gollub, J, Webster, T, Wong, B, Zhan, Y, Auton, A, Campbell, CL, Kong, Y, Marcketta, A, Gibbs, RA, Yu, F, Antunes, L, Bainbridge, M, Muzny, D, Sabo, A, Huang, Z, Wang, J, Coin, LJM, Fang, L, Guo, X, Jin, X, Li, G, Li, Q, Li, Y, Li, Z, Lin, H, Liu, B, Luo, R, Shao, H, Xie, Y, Ye, C, Yu, C, Zhang, F, Zheng, H, Zhu, H, Alkan, C, Dal, E, Kahveci, F, Marth, GT, Garrison, EP, Kural, D, Lee, W-P, Leong, WF, Stromberg, M, Ward, AN, Wu, J, Zhang, M, Daly, MJ, DePristo, MA, Handsaker, RE, Altshuler, DM, Banks, E, Bhatia, G, del Angel, G, Gabriel, SB, Genovese, G, Gupta, N, Li, H, Kashin, S, Lander, ES, McCarroll, SA, Nemesh, JC, Poplin, RE, Yoon, SC, Lihm, J, Makarov, V, Clark, AG, Gottipati, S, Keinan, A, Rodriguez-Flores, JL, Korbel, JO, Rausch, T, Fritz, MH, Stütz, AM, Flicek, P, Beal, K, Clarke, L, Datta, A, Herrero, J, McLaren, WM, Ritchie, GRS, Smith, RE, Zerbino, D, Zheng-Bradley, X, Sabeti, PC, Shlyakhter, I, Schaffner, SF, Vitti, J, Cooper, DN, Ball, EV, Stenson, PD, Bentley, DR, Barnes, B, Bauer, M, Keira Cheetham, R, Cox, A, Eberle, M, Humphray, S, Kahn, S, Murray, L, Peden, J, Shaw, R, Kenny, EE, Batzer, MA, Konkel, MK, Walker, JA, MacArthur, DG, Lek, M, Sudbrak, R, Amstislavskiy, VS, Herwig, R, Mardis, ER, Ding, L, Koboldt, DC, Larson, D, Ye, K, Gravel, S and Consortium The Genomes Project, authors Corresponding, committee Steering, group Production, Medicine Baylor College of, B. G. I. Shenzhen, M. I. T. Broad Institute of, Harvard, Research Coriell Institute for Medical, European Bioinformatics Institute European Molecular Biology Laboratory, Illumina, Genetics Max Planck Institute for Molecular, University McDonnell Genome Institute at Washington, U. S. National Institutes of Health, Oxford University of, Institute Wellcome Trust Sanger, group Analysis, Affymetrix, Medicine Albert Einstein College of, University Bilkent, College Boston, Laboratory Cold Spring Harbor, University Cornell, Laboratory European Molecular Biology, University Harvard, Database Human Gene Mutation, Sinai Icahn School of Medicine at Mount, University Louisiana State, Hospital Massachusetts General, University McGill, and N. I. H. National Eye Institute (2015) A global reference for human genetic variation. Nature 526, 6874. doi: 10.1038/nature15393Google ScholarPubMed
Barton, S and Roth, P (1992) Life insurance and HIV antibody testing. BMJ: British Medical Journal 305, 902.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Beaumont, RN and Wright, CF (2022) Estimating diagnostic noise in panel-based genomic analysis. Genetics in Medicine 24, 20422050. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gim.2022.06.008CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bélisle-Pipon, J-C, Vayena, E, Green, RC and Glenn Cohen, I (2019) Genetic testing, insurance discrimination and medical research: what the United States can learn from peer countries. Nature Medicine 25, 11981204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bombard, Y and Heim-Myers, B (2018) The Genetic Non-Discrimination Act: critical for promoting health and science in Canada. Canadian Medical Association Journal 190, E579. doi: 10.1503/cmaj.180298CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Born, P (2019) Genetic testing in underwriting: implications for life insurance markets. Journal of Insurance Regulation 38, 118.Google Scholar
Botton, MR, Whirl-Carrillo, M, Del Tredici, AL, Sangkuhl, K, Cavallari, LH, Agúndez, JAG, Duconge, J, Michael Lee, MT, Woodahl, EL, Claudio-Campos, K, Daly, AK, Klein, TE, Pratt, VM, Scnott, SA and Gaedigk, A (2021) PharmVar GeneFocus: CYP2C19. Clinical Pharmacology & Therapeutics 109, 352366. https://doi.org/10.1002/cpt.1973CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Christiaans, I, Kok, TM, van Langen, IM, Birnie, E, Bonsel, GJ, Wilde, AAM and Smets, EMA (2010) Obtaining insurance after DNA diagnostics: a survey among hypertrophic cardiomyopathy mutation carriers. European Journal of Human Genetics 18, 251253. doi: 10.1038/ejhg.2009.145CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Commission, European (2012) EU rules on gender-neutral pricing in insurance industry enter into force. Available at https://ec.europa.eu/commission/presscorner/detail/en/IP_12_1430 (accessed 24 January 2024).Google Scholar
Conley, D (2019) From fraternities to DNA: the challenge genetic prediction poses to insurance markets. The Milbank Quarterly 97, 4043. doi: 10.1111/1468-0009.12365CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Culyer, AJ (2006) NICE's use of cost effectiveness as an exemplar of a deliberative process. Health Economics, Policy, and Law 1, 299318. doi: 10.1017/s1744133106004026CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cutler, DM and Zeckhauser, RJ (1998) Adverse selection in health insurance. Forum for Health Economics & Policy 1, 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cutler, DM and Zeckhauser, RJ (2000) The anatomy of health insurance. In Culyer, A and Newhouse, J (eds), Handbook of Health Economics. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 563643.Google Scholar
Daniels, N (2004) The functions of insurance and the fairness of genetic underwriting. In Rothstein, MA (ed), Genetics and Life Insurance: Medical Underwriting and Social Policy. Cambridge MA: MIT Press, pp. 119145.Google Scholar
de Zeeuw, EL, Voort, L, Schoonhoven, R, Nivard, MG, Emery, T, Hottenga, JJ, Willemsen, G, Dykstra, PA, Zarrabi, N, Kartopawiro, JD and Boomsma, DI (2021) Safe linkage of cohort and population-based register data in a genomewide association study on health care expenditure. Twin Research and Human Genetics 24, 103109. doi: 10.1017/thg.2021.18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Department of Health and Social Care (2022) Code on genetic testing and insurance: 3-year review 2022. London.Google Scholar
Dixon, P, Hollingworth, W, Harrison, S, Davies, NM and Smith, GD (2020) Mendelian randomization analysis of the causal effect of adiposity on hospital costs. Journal of Health Economics 70, 102300. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jhealeco.2020.102300CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dixon, P, Harrison, S, Hollingworth, W, Davies, NM and Smith, GD (2022 a) Estimating the causal effect of liability to disease on healthcare costs using Mendelian randomization. Economics & Human Biology 46, 101154. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ehb.2022.101154CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dixon, P, Sallis, H, Munafo, M, Smith, GD and Howe, L (2022 b) The causal effect of cigarette smoking on healthcare costs. medRxiv:2022.07.05.22277228. doi: 10.1101/2022.07.05.22277228CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Filipova-Neumann, L and Hoy, M (2014) Managing genetic tests, surveillance, and preventive medicine under a public health insurance system. Journal of Health Economics 34, 3141. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jhealeco.2013.12.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaedigk, A, Sangkuhl, K, Whirl-Carrillo, M, Klein, T and Steven Leeder, J (2017) Prediction of CYP2D6 phenotype from genotype across world populations. Genetics in Medicine 19, 6976. https://doi.org/10.1038/gim.2016.80CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haga, SB, Barry, WT, Mills, R, Ginsburg, GS, Svetkey, L, Sullivan, J and Willard, HF (2013) Public knowledge of and attitudes toward genetics and genetic testing. Genetic Testing and Molecular Biomarkers 17, 327335. doi: 10.1089/gtmb.2012.0350CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hall, MA and Rich, SS (2000) Genetic privacy laws and patients’ fear of discrimination by health insurers: the view from genetic counselors. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 28, 245257.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harper, PS (1992) Genetic testing and insurance. Journal of the Royal College of Physicians of London 26, 184187.Google ScholarPubMed
Hazewinkel, A-D, Richmond, RC, Wade, KH and Dixon, P (2022) Mendelian randomization analysis of the causal impact of body mass index and waist-hip ratio on rates of hospital admission. Economics & Human Biology 44, 101088. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ehb.2021.101088CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Holmes, EM (1996) Solving the insurance/genetic fair/unfair discrimination dilemma in light of the Human Genome Project. Kentucky Law Journal 85, 503.Google ScholarPubMed
Horton, RH and Lucassen, AM (2019) Recent developments in genetic/genomic medicine. Clinical Science 133, 697708. doi: 10.1042/cs20180436CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horton, R and Lucassen, A (2022) Ethical considerations in research with genomic data. The New Bioethics 29, 115. doi: 10.1080/20502877.2022.2060590Google ScholarPubMed
Horton, R, Crawford, G, Freeman, L, Fenwick, A, Wright, CF and Lucassen, A (2019) Direct-to-consumer genetic testing. BMJ 367, l5688. doi: 10.1136/bmj.l5688CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
House of Commons Science and Technology Committee (2001) Science and technology – Fifth Report. London.Google Scholar
Hoy, M and Witt, J (2007) Welfare effects of banning genetic information in the life insurance market: the case of BRCA1/2 genes. Journal of Risk and Insurance 74, 523546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Insurance Newsnet (2023) MassMutual embraces behavioral insurance with new program. Available at https://insurancenewsnet.com/innarticle/massmutual-embraces-behavioral-insurance-with-new-program (accessed 3 January 2024).Google Scholar
Jackson, L, Weedon, MN, Harrison, JW, Wood, AR, Ruth, KS, Tyrrell, J and Wright, CF 2022. Influence of family history on penetrance of hereditary cancers in a population setting. medRxiv:2022.07.08.22277415. doi: 10.1101/2022.07.08.22277415CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joly, Y, Dalpé, G, Dupras, C, Bévière-Boyer, B, De Paor, A, Dove, ES, Moreno, PG, Ho, CWL, Ho, C-H and Cathaoir, (2020 a) Establishing the international genetic discrimination observatory. Nature Genetics 52, 466468.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Joly, Y, Dupras, C, Pinkesz, M, Tovino, SA and Rothstein, MA (2020 b) Looking beyond GINA: policy approaches to address genetic discrimination. Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 21, 491507. doi: 10.1146/annurev-genom-111119-011436CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Karlsson Linnér, R and Koellinger, PD (2022) Genetic risk scores in life insurance underwriting. Journal of Health Economics 81, 102556. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jhealeco.2021.102556CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lacaze, P, Ryan, J, Woods, R, Winship, I and McNeil, J (2017) Pathogenic variants in the healthy elderly: unique ethical and practical challenges. Journal of Medical Ethics 43, 714722. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2016-103967CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lakhani, CM, Tierney, BT, Manrai, AK, Yang, J, Visscher, PM and Patel, CJ (2019) Repurposing large health insurance claims data to estimate genetic and environmental contributions in 560 phenotypes. Nature Genetics 51, 327334. doi: 10.1038/s41588-018-0313-7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lee, J, Jukarainen, S, Dixon, P, Davies, NM, Smith, GD, Natarajan, P and Ganna, A 2022. Quantifying the causal impact of biological risk factors on healthcare costs. medRxiv:2022.11.19.22282356. doi: 10.1101/2022.11.19.22282356CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macdonald, A and Yu, F (2011) The impact of genetic information on the insurance industry: conclusions from the ‘bottom-up’ modelling programme. ASTIN Bulletin 41, 343376. doi: 10.2143/AST.41.2.2136981Google Scholar
MacMinn, RD, Brockett, PL and Raeburn, JA (2007) Health insurance, genetic testing and adverse selection. Annals of Actuarial Science 2, 327347. doi: 10.1017/S1748499500000385CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marian, AJ and Braunwald, E (2017) Hypertrophic cardiomyopathy: genetics, pathogenesis, clinical manifestations, diagnosis, and therapy. Circulation research 121, 749770.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marston, S, Copeland, O, Gehmlich, K, Schlossarek, S and Carrrier, L (2012) How do MYBPC3 mutations cause hypertrophic cardiomyopathy? Journal of Muscle Research and Cell Motility 33, 7580. doi: 10.1007/s10974-011-9268-3CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maxwell, JM, Russell, RA, Wu, HM, Sharapova, N, Banthorpe, P, O'Reilly, PF and Lewis, CM (2021) Multifactorial disorders and polygenic risk scores: predicting common diseases and the possibility of adverse selection in life and protection insurance. Annals of Actuarial Science 15, 488503. doi: 10.1017/S1748499520000226CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGurk, KA, Zheng, SL, Henry, A, Josephs, K, Edwards, M, de Marvao, A, Whiffin, N, Roberts, A, Lumbers, TR, O'Regan, DP and Ware, JS (2022) Correspondence on ‘ACMG SF v3.0 list for reporting of secondary findings in clinical exome and genome sequencing: a policy statement of the American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics (ACMG)’ Miller et al. Genetics in Medicine 24, 744746. doi: 10.1016/j.gim.2021.10.020CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McLean, SAM and Gannon, P (1998) Genetics and insurance. In Sorrell, T (ed.), Health Care, Ethics and Insurance. London: Routledge, pp. 103116.Google Scholar
Ossa, DF and Towse, A (2004) Genetic screening, health care and the insurance industry. Should genetic information be made available to insurers? The European Journal of Health Economics 5, 116121. doi: 10.1007/s10198-003-0213-2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Oxera (2010) The use of gender in insurance pricing: analysing the impact of a potential ban on the use of gender as a rating factor. In ABI Research Paper No.24 edited by Association of British Insurers.Google Scholar
Peter, R, Richter, A and Thistle, P (2017) Endogenous information, adverse selection, and prevention: implications for genetic testing policy. Journal of Health Economics 55, 95107. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jhealeco.2017.06.010CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pope, DG and Sydnor, JR (2011) Implementing anti-discrimination policies in statistical profiling models. American Economic Journal: Economic Policy 3, 206231. doi: 10.1257/pol.3.3.206Google Scholar
Prince, AER (2017) Insurance risk classification in an era of genomics: is a rational discrimination policy rational? Nebraska Law Review 96, 624.Google Scholar
Prince, AER (2018) Political economy, stakeholder voices, and saliency: lessons from international policies regulating insurer use of genetic information. Journal of Law and the Biosciences 5, 461494.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Prince, AER, Uhlmann, WR, Suter, SM and Scherer, AM (2021) Genetic testing and insurance implications: surveying the US general population about discrimination concerns and knowledge of the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act (GINA). Risk Management and Insurance Review 24, 341365. https://doi.org/10.1111/rmir.12195CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Roberts, JS, Dolinoy, DC and Tarini, BA (2014) Emerging issues in public health genomics. Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 15, 461480. doi: 10.1146/annurev-genom-090413-025514CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Robinson, JO, Carroll, TM, Feuerman, LZ, Perry, DL, Hoffman-Andrews, L, Walsh, RC, Christensen, KD, Green, RC and McGuire, AL (2016) Participants and study decliners’ perspectives about the risks of participating in a clinical trial of whole genome sequencing. Journal of Empirical Research. on Human Research Ethics 11, 2130. doi: 10.1177/1556264615624078CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodriguez-Rincon, D, Parkinson, S, Hocking, L, Evans, H, Hudson, E and Morley, KI (2022) Assessing the impact of developments in genetic testing on insurers’ risk exposure. Santa Monica, CA: RAND Corporation.Google Scholar
Rothstein, MA (2018) Time to end the use of genetic test results in life insurance underwriting. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 46, 794801. doi: 10.1177/1073110518804243CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scott, SA, Sangkuhl, K, Stein, CM, Hulot, JS, Mega, JL, Roden, DM, Klein, TE, Sabatine, MS, Johnson, JA and Shuldiner, AR (2013) Clinical pharmacogenetics implementation consortium guidelines for CYP2C19 genotype and clopidogrel therapy: 2013 update. Clinical Pharmacology & Therapeutics 94, 317323. https://doi.org/10.1038/clpt.2013.105CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, GD (2011) Epidemiology, epigenetics and the ‘gloomy prospect’: embracing randomness in population health research and practice. International Journal of Epidemiology 40, 537562. doi: 10.1093/ije/dyr117CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sud, A, Turnbull, C and Houlston, R (2021) Will polygenic risk scores for cancer ever be clinically useful? NPJ Precision Oncology 5, 40. doi: 10.1038/s41698-021-00176-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sud, A, Horton, RH, Hingorani, AD, Tzoulaki, I, Turnbull, C, Houlston, RS and Lucassen, A (2023) Realistic expectations are key to realising the benefits of polygenic scores. BMJ 380, e073149. doi: 10.1136/bmj-2022-073149CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Supreme Court of Canada (2020) Reference re Genetic Non-Discrimination Act. Available at https://www.scc-csc.ca/case-dossier/cb/2020/38478-eng.aspx (accessed 29 November 2022).Google Scholar
Tiller, J and Lacaze, P (2023) Life insurers can charge more or decline cover based on your genetic test results. New laws must change this. The Conversation. Available at https://theconversation.com/life-insurers-can-charge-more-or-decline-cover-based-on-your-genetic-test-results-new-laws-must-change-this-212183#:~:text=This%20means%20a%20health%20insurer,factors%2C%20including%20genetic%20risk%20factors (accessed 3 January 2024).Google Scholar
Tiller, J, Morris, S, Rice, T, Barter, K, Riaz, M, Keogh, L, Delatycki, MB, Otlowski, M and Lacaze, P (2020) Genetic discrimination by Australian insurance companies: a survey of consumer experiences. European Journal of Human Genetics 28, 108113. doi: 10.1038/s41431-019-0426-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tiller, J, Bakshi, A, Brotchie, AR, Green, RC, Winship, IM and Lacaze, P (2023) Public willingness to participate in population DNA screening in Australia. Journal of Medical Genetics 60, 662668. doi: 10.1136/jmg-2022-108921. Epub 2022 Nov 30. PMID: 36450406.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tiller, J, Bakshi, A, Dowling, G, Keogh, L, McInerney-Leo, A, Barlow-Stewart, K, Boughtwood, T, Gleeson, P, Delatycki, MB and Winship, I (2024) Community concerns about genetic discrimination in life insurance persist in Australia: a survey of consumers offered genetic testing. European Journal of Human Genetics 32, 286294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wauters, A and Van Hoyweghen, I (2016) Global trends on fears and concerns of genetic discrimination: a systematic literature review. Journal of Human Genetics 61, 275282. doi: 10.1038/jhg.2015.151CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, D (2006) Acquisition and disclosure of genetic information under alternative policy regimes: an economic analysis. Health Economics, Policy and Law 1, 263276. doi: 10.1017/S1744133106003021CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Young, AI (2019) Solving the missing heritability problem. PLoS Genetics 15, e1008222. doi: 10.1371/journal.pgen.1008222CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed