Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T23:04:05.706Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

From Theology to a Science of Religions: Jonathan Edwards and William James on Religious Affections

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 June 2011

Wayne Proudfoot
Affiliation:
Columbia University

Extract

In a volume of speeches published in 1799 and addressed to those whom he called “the cultured among the despisers of religion,” Friedrich Schleiermacher offered a description of religious experience, doctrine, and practice designed to convince his readers that the conventional pieties they deplored in the churches and synagogues were not genuine religion. Instead, true religion was the sense and taste for the infinite that they themselves were cultivating in poetry, criticism, conversation, and other aesthetic pursuits of their romantic circle. He was especially concerned to allay their fears that religious beliefs might conflict with the growth of knowledge about the world of nature or the mind. “Religion,” he wrote, “leaves you, your physics and … also your psychology untouched.”

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © President and Fellows of Harvard College 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Schleiermacher, Friedrich, On Religion (trans. Richard Crouter; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988) 133Google Scholar. (translation slightly altered).

2 “I believe that Judaism knows of no revealed religion in the sense in which Christians understand this term. The Israelites possess a divine legislation—laws, commandments, ordinances, rules of life, instruction in the will of God as to how they should conduct themselves in order to attain temporal and eternal felicity. Propositions and prescriptions of this kind were revealed to them by Moses in a miraculous and supernatural manner, but not doctrinal opinions, no saving truths, no universal propositions of reason” (Mendelssohn, Moses, Jerusalem, or, On Religious Power and Judaism [trans. Arkush, Allan; Hanover/London: University Press of New England, 1983] 8990).Google Scholar

3 Edwards, Jonathan, A Treatise Concerning Religious Affections (ed. Smith, John E.; New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959) 95Google Scholar; James, William, The Varieties of Religious Experience (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985) 341.Google Scholar

4 Edwards, Jonathan, “A Faithful Narrative of the Surprising Work of God in the Conversion of Many Hundred Souls in Northampton,” in The Great Awakening (ed. Goen, C. C.; New Haven: Yale University Press, 1972) 130211.Google Scholar

5 Miller, Perry, Jonathan Edwards (New York: Meridian, 1959).Google Scholar

6 See, e.g., Cherry, Conrad. The Theology of Jonathan Edwards: A Reappraisal (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1966).Google Scholar

7 Miller, Perry, “The Rhetoric of Sensation,” in idem, Errand into the Wilderness (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1956) 167–83.Google Scholar

8 Religious Affections, 205–6.

9 Ibid., 193.

10 Calvin, John, Institutes of the Christian Religion (ed. McNeill, John T.; trans. Ford Lewis Battles; Philadelphia: Westminster, 1977) 1. 551.Google Scholar

11 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, The Blue and Brown Books (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958) 2425.Google Scholar

12 Religious Affections, 197 (original emphasis).

13 This is Edwards's formulation of the fourth sign. Religious Affections, 266.

14 Ibid., 383.

15 Ibid., 426.

16 Varieties, 342.

17 For further discussion of this issue, see my Religious Experience (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985) 155227.Google Scholar

18 James's conception of an empirical psychology, centering on introspection, was influenced by Franz Brentano's Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. See Ryan, Judith, “American Pragmatism/Viennese Psychology,” Raritan 8 (1989) 4554.Google Scholar

19 See Proudfoot, Religious Experience, 155–89.

20 Varieties, 34.

21 The Letters of William James (ed. James, Henry; Boston: Atlantic Monthly Press, 1920) 1. 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Varieties, 341–42.

23 In addition to the examples he adduces, James's chief argument for his claim that religion is a matter of feeling or sense rather than of intellect is that a comparison across traditions would show feeling and practice to be invariant, while doctrines and beliefs vary widely. For a criticism of this argument, see Proudfoot, Religious Experience, 158–61.

24 Varieties, 55.

25 For a brief discussion of this thread that runs through the Varieties, and citation of the relevant passages, see Proudfoot, Religious Experience, 156–69.

26 James, William, The Principles of Psychology (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1983) 186 (original emphasis).Google Scholar

27 Varieties, 335–36.

28 Principles, 850. See also Chapter XVII, esp. 662–78.

29 Varieties, 13.

30 Ibid., 25 (original emphasis).

31 Ibid., 399–400.

32 This point is set out more fully in “The Will to Believe,” in The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979) 1333.Google Scholar

33 Varieties, 13; Peirce, Charles Sanders, “The Fixation of Belief,” in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (ed. Hartshorne, Charles and Weiss, Paul; Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1934)5. par. 358–87.Google Scholar

34 Peirce says that a person who sees that any of her beliefs are determined by something extraneous to the facts should experience doubt about those beliefs. He recommends a method “by which our beliefs may be determined [originally “caused”] by nothing human, but by some external permanency—by something on which our thinking has no effect” (Peirce, “The Fixation of Belief,” in Collected Papers V, par. 384).

35 See, e.g, Shope, Robert K., The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983).Google Scholar

36 Varieties, 193.

37 “A Faithful Narrative,” in The Great Awakening, 130–211.

38 “Some Thoughts Concerning the Revival,” in The Great Awakening, 331 —41.

39 Varieties, 223–24.

40 Ibid., 221.

41 Ibid., 34. For “thick description,” see Geertz, Clifford, “Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture,” in The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973) 330.Google Scholar

42 Varieties, 34.

43 Religious Affections, 197 (original emphasis).

44 For more on this distinction, see Proudfoot, Religious Experience, 190–227.

45 An earlier version of this article was delivered as the William James Lecture at Harvard Divinity School in November 1987.