Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-29T11:14:01.598Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Edwards and the Ethical Question

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 June 2011

Clyde A. Holbrook
Affiliation:
Oberlin College, Oberlin, Ohio

Extract

Whereas traditionally the nature of God and his actions have been counted as decisive for man's morality, it has been argued by some contemporary moral philosophers that man's moral autonomy is such that reference to deity in any decisive way is either irrelevant or at best an optional addendum to the moral life. Thus P. H. Nowell-Smith asserts that even if God commands a certain course of action, “it still makes sense … to ask whether or not I ought to do it.” But even the sense of obligation is weakened from its Kantian austerity by this author who insists that “morality is a set of habits of choice determined by the question ‘what life is most satisfactory to me as a whole?’” Outside this teleological reference he professes ignorance as to what the term “ought” means. A similar view is explicitly stated by Kai Nielsen, “The moral agent must independently decide that whatever God wills or commands is good.” Our own moral awareness and sensitivity are used “to decide that God is good and that God ought to be obeyed. We have not derived our moral convictions just from discerning what are the commands of God.” A slightly different position is taken by W. G. MacLagan. It is argued at length that the sense of the moral ought, moral law or moral values is arrived at independently of the theistic hypothesis, although he is willing to employ the notion of moral law as an index to the meaning of the term God. God is not completely shut out of moral calculations, but any independent recourse to deity infringes upon the prior and sui generis character of duty which man directly feels.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © President and Fellows of Harvard College 1967

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Ramsey, Ian, ed., Christian Ethics and Contemporary Philosophy (SCM Press, 1966), 97, henceforth CECP.Google Scholar

2 CECP, 108.

3 CECP, 141.

4 The Theological Frontier of Ethics (Allen and Unwin, London, 1961), 81; cf. 50, 84, 87.

5 CECP, 108.

6 Works, Vol. 2 (Worcester ed.), 444f.

7 Ibid., 406.

8 Inquiry into the Original of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1738), 275.

9 Ibid., 275f.

10 Ibid., 301.

11 Ibid., 303.

12 Ibid., 129f.

13 F. Hutcheson, Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections with Illustrations on the Moral Sense (1728), 215.

14 Ibid., 212.

15 Ibid., 214f.

17 Works, Vol. 2 (Worcester ed.), 412f.

18 Hutcheson, Essay …, 115.

19 Ibid., 149.

20 Works, Vol. 2 (Worcester ed.), 408ff.

21 Bonar, James, Moral Sense (N.Y., Macmillan Co., 1930), 103Google Scholar.

22 MacLagan, 50.

23 Works, Vol. i (Worcester Reprint, 1843), 567.

24 Cf. ibid., 571.

25 H. G. Townsend, ed., The Philosophy of Jonathan Edwards, No. 986, p. 212.

26 Works, Vol. 2 (Worcester ed.), 465.

27 Cf. Religious Affections, Vol. 2 (Yale ed.), 197ff.

28 Cf. Works, Vol. 2 (Worcester ed.), 457.

29 Ibid., 415.

30 Ibid., 420.

31 Ibid., 421.

32 Ibid., 441.

33 ibid., 443.

34 Cf. Barbour, I., Issues in Science and Religion (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1966), 25fGoogle Scholar.

35 Cf. MacLagan, 84, 87.

36 Cf. Smith, C. A., Jonathan Edwards and “The Way of Ideas,” Harvard Theological Review 59 (1966), 155CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 MacLagan, 84, 85.

38 Cf. CECP, 158f.

39 CECP, 141.

40 Works, Vol. 1 (Dwight ed.), 693, 696.

41 Works, Vol. 2 (Worcester ed.), 421.