Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T02:29:54.266Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Platonis Aemvlvs?1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Extract

‘M. Tvllivs … etiam in hoc opere [i.e. philosophia] Platonis aemulus exstitit.’ There is a fallacy underlying Quintilian's judgement here—he is not by any means at his best in this famous chapter—which is interesting in that, with very different consequences, it also underlies the almost total neglect of Cicero's philosophical works prevalent in this country in our own day. (That Cicero's philosophical works were once popular everyone knows; but many would, I fancy, be surprised to learn how much serious and scholarly attention they are still receiving in America, France, and Germany.) The fallacy which is the common basis of Quintilian's approbation and our neglect is the belief, explicit or implicit in much modern criticism, that Roman literature is to be assessed by comparison, man for man and genre for genre, with Greek. Some such comparisons can be made, and with profit for those who do not prejudge the issue of the investigation and, since the Roman writers often seem deliberately to invite such comparisons, for those who are equipped with the necessary understanding of what ‘imitation’ means in the context of ancient literature. But these comparisons are silly and fruitless when conducted with the kind of naïveté which can see in Cicero's philosophical writings only a ‘poor man's Plato’. To compare Cicero and Plato in this field is to compare incomparables. This becomes clear if we forget our presuppositions and ask, as I propose to do, (1) what was Cicero in his philosophical writings trying to do and was it worth doing, and (2) how did he set about his task, and were his methods the right ones ? Only then can we attempt, as I shall do briefly in concluding, an estimate of his achievement.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 1962

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 41 note 2 Quint, x. 1. 123

page 41 note 3 Throughout I deal primarily with the works of 45–44 b.c. (from Academica to De Officiis), not with the earlier De Oratore (54 b.c.), De Re Publica (51 b.c.), Brutus and Orator (46 b.c.). These works, treated by Cicero as part of his philosophical output (De Diu. ii. 1–4), differ from the later group in explicitly presenting Cicero's own views, however much he owed to Greek ideas and influences. Further, modern neglect of the rhetorical works is due rather to a loss of interest in rhetoric itself than to inapt comparisons with the Greeks.

page 42 note 1 Fin. i. 10.

page 42 note 2 Att. xii. 52. 3.

page 43 note 1 Ac. Pr. 29.

page 44 note 1 Fin. i. 42, ii. 86.

page 44 note 2 Ac. Post. 3.

page 44 note 3 Fin. i. 13.

page 45 note 1 The Humanism of Cicero (Melbourne, 1954).Google Scholar

page 46 note 1 Fin. ii. 1–17. The passage reveals Cicero's interest in the various ways of conducting philosophical discussion.

page 46 note 2 Tusc. i. 9–25.

page 46 note 3 This statement, from the Oxford Class. Dict., s.v. ‘Dialogue, Latin’, is true (more or less) only of Brutus, De Legibus, parts of the Tusculans, and the two short essays on friendship and old age.

page 47 note 1 Tusc. iii. 50.

page 47 note 2 Tusc. i. 7.

page 47 note 3 Ac. Pr. 1–4.

page 48 note 1 N.D. i. 18.

page 48 note 2 Cicéron traducteur de Platon (Paris, 1957).Google Scholar

page 49 note 1 Ac. Post. 24; Fin. iii. 15; Tusc. i. 14, iii. 16.

page 49 note 2 Tusc. iii. 20.

page 49 note 3 The Greeks (Harmondsworth, 1951), 28Google Scholar; cf. the alleged examination question: ‘Μέν and δέ are the curse of the Greek language. Discuss.’

page 50 note 1 Att. xii. 52. 3; cf. above, p. 41.