Article contents
Aristocracy and its Advocates in Archaic Greece
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 January 2009
Extract
The subject of this article is the appearance in archaic Greek literature of the two basic principles of aristocracy as a form of government—republicanism and noble rule—and how they were upheld, augmented, qualified, idealized, and justified against the alternatives of monarchy and the aspirations of non-nobles either to join or disestablish the nobility as the ruling class. When Greek states emerged from the Dark Ages into the clearer light of history in the eighth and seventh centuries b.c., monarchy had almost everywhere given way to aristocracy. More or less exclusive groups of noble families had learnt, in Aristotle's phrase, ‘to take turns in ruling and being ruled’. The formation of the first republics required no change in the ideological climate of the unquestioning acceptance of the noble monopoly of wealth and privilege which we find in Homer and Hesiod, and similarly no change in this climate was required before republican governments were likely to be challenged. The Homeric nobleman's primary obligation, simply expressed in Hippolochus' parting injunction to his son ‘always to be best’, runs contrary to the principle of equals taking turns in ruling and being ruled, and it would not be surprising if many a Greek aristocrat acquiesced in being equal best only because he lacked the opportunity to make himself single best. And where there were narrow aristocracies which by their exclusiveness made permanent political inferiors of noble families which were the socio-economic peers of the politically privileged, as in Corinth under the Bacchiads or Mytilene under the Penthilids, there was likely to be a greater incentive for an ambitious nobleman to usurp for his own family the corporate constitutional superiority of his privileged rivals; and there might be correspondingly less ideological opposition from noble republicans so far as other politically unprivileged nobles would be constitutionally no less deprived under a tyrant, and might have much to gain in power and wealth from supporting the overthrower of the exclusive regime. The disappearance of Dark Age kingship of the Homeric primus inter pares type is nowhere likely to have generated all at once an ideology which made monarchy an anathema. The Homeric king is not even distinguished from the other nobles by a title which is not also enjoyed by the heads of other great houses, and the lack of traditions about the disappearance of kingship suggests that it was undramatic. On the other hand, because tyranny (in the basic sense of an autocracy established in a state which had been a republic) necessarily meant permanent constitutional inferiority for social equals, acquiescence in even a benign and initially popular autocracy was likely to wane once the possibility of constitutional equality had been discovered (however narrow the ruling circle of equals had been).
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Classical Association 1972
References
page 190 note 1 Aristotle, Politics 1287a16–18.
page 190 note 2 Iliad vi. 208–11.Google Scholar
page 191 note 1 The sources are collected by Page, D. L., Sappho and Alcaeus (Oxford, 1955)Google Scholar, and I follow his reconstruction of the events. Fragments are numbered according to Lobel, E. and Page, D. L., Poetarum Lesbiorum Fragmenta (Oxford, 1955).Google Scholar
page 192 note 1 Aristotle, Politics 1285a30–b2.
page 192 note 2 Carmina Popularia 43, in Bergk, T., Poetae Lyrici Graeci iii (Leipzig, 1882).Google Scholar
page 192 note 3 Aristotle, , Politics 1310b20, 1305a15–18; Ath. Pol. 13.Google Scholar
page 193 note 1 Diogenes Laertius i. 75.
page 193 note 2 Aristotle, Politics 1274b18–19.
page 193 note 3 Fragments of Solon are numbered according to Diehl, E., Anthologia Lyrica Graeca (Leipzig, 1925).Google Scholar
page 193 note 4 Plutarch, Solon 14.
page 194 note 1 Diogenes Laertius i. 49; Solon, frs. 8–10.
page 194 note 2 Hignett, C., A History of the Athenian Constitution (Oxford, 1952), 93–6.Google Scholar
page 195 note 1 e.g. Iliad ii. 24 ff.; Odyssey ii. 230 ff., xix. 109 ff.
page 196 note 1 Cyrnus poems will be indicated by the letter ‘C’ after the reference.
page 198 note 1 Adkins, A. W. H., Merit and Responsibility (Oxford, 1960), 78–9Google Scholar; Bowra, C. M., Early Greek Elegists (London, 1938), 148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
page 199 note 1 Thucydides viii. 21.
page 199 note 2 Aristotle, Politics 1310a7–10.
page 199 note 3 Ibid. 1295b34.
page 199 note 4 Pindar, fr. 198 (Bowra).
page 201 note 1 Duclos, , Considérations sur les Mœurs, ed. Green, F. C. (Cambridge, 1939), 124.Google Scholar
page 202 note 1 ‘Xenophon’: Stobaeus, Fl. lxxxviii. 14.
page 203 note 1 Herodotus iii. 81.
page 204 note 1 Phocylides, fr. 3 (Diehl); Stobaeus, Fl. lxxxvii. 2.
page 204 note 2 Plato, Meno 95 d–e.
page 205 note 1 Euripides, , Electra 253, 261–2Google Scholar; cf. 367 ff., and fr. 345 (Nauck).
page 206 note 1 Herodotus v. 44; ix. 33.
page 207 note 1 Iliad vi. 146.
- 11
- Cited by