Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T16:08:29.638Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Socrates and Authority

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2009

Extract

In a well-known passage in the Apology, Socrates says that if the court release him on condition that he give up questioning the views of his fellow citizens, he will refuse to obey:

… If you say to me, ‘Socrates, this time we will not follow Anytus but will let you go on condition that you no longer spend your time on this inquiry and stop philosophizing; if you are caught doing this again, you shall die’—if you were to acquit me on this condition, I would reply: ‘Men of Athens, I honour and love you, but I shall obey the god rather than you and as long as I breathe and have the capacity I shall never cease philosophizing …’ (29 c 6–d 5.)

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Classical Association 1972

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 208 note 1 See, for example, Barker, E., Greek Political Theory (London, 1957), 112Google Scholar; Sinclair, T. A., A History of Greek Political Thought 2 (London, 1967), 92Google Scholar; Gulley, N., The Philosophy of Socrates (London, 1968), 175–7.Google Scholar

page 209 note 1 It is not clear precisely what ‘persuading the laws’ involves. It is usually taken to imply making actual changes in the laws; in which case Socrates' theory of obligation applies only to those who may participate in the process of legislation. On the other hand, it may simply mean being able to plead one's case in court. Both rights, of course, were possessed by Athenian citizens, but the ambiguity is important because, as in certain states citizens could possess the latter without the former, it affects the scope of Socrates' theory.

page 210 note 1 Cf. Greenberg, N. A., ‘Socrates' Choice in the Crito’, HSCP lxx (1965), 46.Google Scholar Greenberg interprets the threat as an attempt by Socrates to ‘raise the stakes’ like a gambler. This is to overlook the peculiar importance that the practice of questioning and philosophizing had for Socrates (see below, p. 211).

page 210 note 2 The fact that Socrates in the Apology is unwilling to contradict the Crito openly and explicitly provides further justification for taking the two works together.

page 210 note 3 As Gulley seems to suggest, loc. cit.

page 211 note 1 Cf. Guthrie, W. K. C., A History of Greek Philosophy, iii (Cambridge, 1969), 405–8.Google Scholar

page 211 note 2 Cf. Greenberg, art. cit. 66.

page 211 note 3 Bentham, J., A Fragment on Government, Preface, § 16.Google Scholar