Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T14:13:16.699Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Welfare and the Value of Liberty*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2014

Extract

THE IDEA OF THE WELFARE STATE IS CURRENTLY TREATED with more scepticism across the political spectrum than at any time during its development. Insofar as the institutions of the welfare state were consolidated during the period of Butskellite consensus which lasted until the late 1960s, in the more polarized political climate of today it is now seen on both the Right and the Left to embody many of the failures implicit in that consensus. It was assumed, so it was argued, that the fiscal dividends of growth could be used to increase welfare in a relatively painless way by maintaining the absolute position of the better off and using the dividends of growth via public expenditure on health, education and welfare to improve the relative standing of the worst-off members of society. In this way it was thought that the social and economic rights of citizenship could be extended within a market economy without putting excessive strain on that economy.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Government and Opposition Ltd 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Crosland, C. A. R., Social Democracy in Europe, Fabian Society, 1975 Google Scholar.

2 Hayek, F., The Constitution of Liberty, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1960 Google Scholar; Friedman, M., Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1962 Google Scholar.

3 Ken, C., Industrialism and Industrial Man, London, Heinemann, 1962 Google Scholar.

4 Thompson, D., ‘The Welfare State’, The New Reasoner, Vol. 1, No. 4, 1958, pp. 4462 Google Scholar.

5 O’Connor, J., The Fiscal Crisis of the State, New York, St Martin’s Press, 1973 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Hayek, F., The Constitution of Liberty, p. 44 Google Scholar.

7 Powell, E., Medicine and Politics, London, Pitman, 1966 Google Scholar.

8 Brittan, S., The Role and Limits of Government, London, Temple Smith, 1983 Google Scholar.

9 Hayek, F., The Constitution of Liberty, p. 133 Google Scholar.

10 ibid, p. 16.

11 ibid, p. 16.

12 ibid.

13 Hayek, F., Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. II: The Mirage of Social justice, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1976, p. 64 Google Scholar.

14 For a forceful statement of this view see Gray, J., ‘Classical Liberalism, Positional Goods and the Politicisation of Poverty’, in Kumar, K. and Ellis, A. (eds), Dilemmas of Liberal Democracies, London, Tavistock, 1983, pp. 181–82Google Scholar.

15 Hayek, F., The Constitution of liberty, p. 29 Google Scholar.

16 Rawls, J., A Theory of justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1972, p. 204 Google Scholar.

17 MacCallum, G., ‘Negative and Positive Liberty Negative and Positive Liberty’, Philosophical Review, 1967, pp. 312–34Google Scholar.

18 Plant, R., Lesser, H. and Taylor‐Gooby, P., Political Philosophy and Social Welfare, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981 Google Scholar; Rawk, J., op. cit; Gewirth, A., Reason and Morality, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1978 Google Scholar; Doyal, L. and Cough, I., ‘A Theory of Human Needs’, Journal of Critical and Social Policy, 10, 1984, pp. 638 Google Scholar.

19 See Sen, A. K., Choice, Welfare and Measurement, Oxford, Blackwell, 1982 Google Scholar.

20 Nozick, R., Anarchy, State and Utopia, Oxford, Blackwell, 1974 Google Scholar.

21 Acton, H. B., The Morals of Markets, London, Longman, 1971 Google Scholar.

22 Sen, A. K., op. cit., p. 368 Google Scholar.

23 J. Gray, op cit.

24 le Grand, J., The Strategy of Equality, London, Allen & Unwin, 1982 Google Scholar.