Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-89wxm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-07T22:47:55.854Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Three arenas of struggle: A contextual approach to the constituent power of ‘the people’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 July 2014

ZORAN OKLOPCIC*
Affiliation:
Department of Law and Legal Studies, Carleton University, 1125 Colonel By Drive, Ottawa, Ontario K1S 5B6, Canada

Abstract

Against recent contributions to the debate about the constituent power of the people, the article proposes to reorient the debate by analytically distinguishing three dominant arenas of political struggle – democratic, social and national – in which the vocabulary of ‘the people’ and its constituent power is invoked. The invocation of the ‘will of the people’ and its constituent power in these arenas is associated with different assumptions, risks and implicit ideational trade-offs that must be laid bare. A contextual approach to constituent power counsels caution in dignifying pro-democratic constitutional transformations with the name of ‘the people’. It invites those who theorize constituent power with social struggles in mind to rebalance their attention to constituent power – and devote more attention to imaginaries and strategies that minimize moral hazards implicit in the vocabulary of peoplehood and to maximize the likelihood of the new order’s survival. Finally, a contextual approach rejects the role for constituent power in national struggles, arguing that constitutional theory is incapable of arbitrating between competing assertions of popular sovereignty. In the final part of the paper, I defend the contextual approach against the theoretical interventions currently on offer, and gesture towards its potential in crafting a provincialized constitutional theory.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 ‘It’s “the people” that happened’, a statement by the Serbian poet Milovan Vitezović at a mass meeting organized by supporters of Slobodan Milošević’s ‘anti-bureaucratic revolution’. Vitezović implicitly responded to allegations that the popular happenings that toppled the regional leaderships of Vojvodina and Montenegro in the fall of 1988, were orchestrated by Milošević.

2 ‘We are the people’, the slogan chanted at anti-regime demonstrations in Leipzig, German Democratic Republic, on 2 October 1989.

3 ‘We are one people’, the transfiguration of the slogan ‘we are the people’, widely popularized in Western Germany as the putative East German plea for national unification, but which initially began as a plea on the part of the civil society groups in Leipzig on 9 October 1989, with the aim of inviting the members of the security forces to see themselves as members of same people as the protesters, and thus renounce violence. Vanessa Fischer, ‘‘‘Wir sind ein Volk’’: Die Geschichte eines deutschen Rufes’ <http://www.deutschlandradiokultur.de/wir-sind-ein-volk.1001.de.html?dram:article_id=155887>.

4 ‘The people wants to topple the regime’, the slogan used during the Arab Spring in 2011, which, for some analysts like Uriel Abulof, signified the question, ‘What is the Arab Third Estate?’, The Huffington Post <http://www.huffingtonpost.com/uriel-abulof/what-is-the-arab-third-es_b_832628.html>. For Abulof, ‘the people ( sha'ab) was born – a collective, rather than a collection, of individuals, a whole greater than the sum of its parts’.

5 ‘When the people are an unconquered power, the government is no longer a power.’: statement by the Ukrainian pop star Ruslana, in her blog post, ‘Very concerned about what is happening, and even more so as it happens!’ <http://blogs.pravda.com.ua/authors/ruslana/52d0acdc26f07/>.

6 Barshack, L, ‘Constituent Power as Body: An Outline of Constitutional Theology’ (2006) 56 University of Toronto Law Journal 185CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Cristi, R, ‘Schmitt on Constituent Power and Monarchical Principle’ (2011) 18(3) Constellations 352CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Kuo, M-S, ‘Reconciling Constitutionalism with Power: Towards a Constitutional Nomos of Political Ordering’ (2010) 23(3) Ratio Juris 390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Jaume, L, ‘Constituent Power in France: The Revolution and Its Consequences’ in Loughlin, M and Walker, N (eds),The Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and Constitutional Form (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2007) 67Google Scholar ; C Möllers, ‘‘‘We are (afraid of) the People”: Constituent Power in German Constitutionalism’ in Loughlin and Walker 87; Azellini, D, ‘Constituent Power in Motion: Ten Years of Transformation in Venezuela’ (2010) 24:2Socialism and Democracy 8CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; Mattei, U and Balley, S, ‘Social Movements as Constituent Power: The Italian Struggle for the Commons’ (2013) 20 Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 965Google Scholar ; Stacey, R, ‘Constituent Power and Carl Schmitt’s Theory of Constitution in Kenya’s Constitution-Making Process’ (2011) 9 International Journal of Constitutional Law 587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8 Chalmers, D, ‘Constituent Power and the Pluralist Ethic’ 291–315 inLoughlin, and Walker, , The Paradox of Constitutionalism (n 7) 291, 300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 UK Preuss, ‘The Exercise of Constituent Power in Central and Eastern Europe’ in Loughlin and Walker, The Paradox of Constitutionalism (n 7) 211, 227.

10 Schmitt, C, Constitutional Theory, trans. by Seitzer, J, (Duke University Press, Durham, NC, 2007) 267Google Scholar, ‘[a] dictatorship in particular is possible only on a democratic foundation’.

11 Lowenstein, K, ‘Constitutions and Constitutional Law in the East and in the West’ (1969) 30 The Indian Journal of Political Science 203, 214.Google Scholar

12 UK Preuss, ‘Constitutional Powermaking for the New Polity: Some Deliberations on the Relations between Constituent Power and the Constitution’ (1992) 14 Cardozo Law Review 639, 641.

13 Thornhill, C, ‘Contemporary Constitutionalism and the Dialectic of Constituent Power’ (2012) 1 Global Constitutionalism 369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Thornhill’s account of constituent power is not, admittedly, explicitly liberal-democratic, but his re-articulation of the telos of constituent power does not leave much room to interpret it otherwise.

14 Sewell, WH, A Rhetoric of Bourgeois Revolution: The Abbé Sieyès and What is the Third Estate? (Duke University Press, Durham, NC, 1994) 54.Google Scholar

15 Ibid.

16 Ibid.

17 Sieyès, EJ, ‘What is the Third Estate?’ trans. by Sonenscher, M in Political Writings: Including the Debate between Sieyès and Tom Paine in 1791 (Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, IN, 2003) 92, 95(emphasis mine).Google Scholar

18 Ibid 97.

19 Loughlin, M, ‘The Concept of Constituent Power’ (2014) 13 European Journal of Political Theory 218, 220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20 Constitutional theory has by and large insisted on this ‘body of associates’ definition of the people. See for example, H Brunkhorst, From Civic Friendship to a Global Legal Community (The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA and London, 2005) 57. See also UK Preuss, Constitutional Revolution: The Link between Constitutionalism and Progress (Humanities Press, Atlantic Highlands, NJ, 1995) 6. More recently, these simplistic accounts of the nation have begun to be complicated. For a more nuanced account distinguishing ‘substance’ and ‘form’ of nationhood, see IR Wall, Human Rights and Constituent Power: Without Model or Warranty (Routledge, New York, 2012) 47. The difficulty with this account is that it does not acknowledge that accounts of ‘substance’ and ‘form’ can clash against each other, and can be in effect understood as juxtaposed, coequal, complete understandings of a nation. For another attempt to reconcile the pre-political and political account of Sieyèsian nationhood, see I Hont, ‘The Permanent Crisis of a Divided Mankind: Contemporary Crisis of the Nation State in Historical Perspective’ (1994) 42 Political Studies 166, 193.

21 See (n 17) 134.

22 Ibid. This ‘seeking to unite’, I hasten to add, should not be interpreted as evidence of the contractual nature of the Nation. Rather, arguing with Paul W Kahn, we should see it as an expression of political eros, ‘that links us to the polity and to each other’. Kahn, PW, Putting Liberalism in Its Place (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2005) 287.Google Scholar

23 See (n 17) 134.

24 Kalyvas, A, ‘The Basic Norm and Democracy in Hans Kelsen’s Legal and Political Theory’ (2005) 32 Philosophy and Social Criticism 573, 589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25 CJ Friedrich, Constitutional Government and Democracy: Theory and Practice in Europe and America (Ginn, Boston, MA, 1950) 128 quoted from Kalyvas (n 24) 590.

26 P Virilio, Speed and Politics: An Essay on Dromology (Semiotexte, Los Angeles, CA, 2006) 120 (italics by Virilio).

27 Mada Masr: Independent, Progressive Journalism, ‘Excuse me sir, is it a coup?’ at <http://madamasr.com/content/excuse-me-sir-it-coup>, 5 July 2013.

28 Lindahl, H, ‘Acquiring a Community: The Acquis and the Institution of European Legal Order’ (2003) 9 European Law Journal 441–2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29 A Somek, ‘The Constituent Power in a Transnational Context’, Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin für Sozialforschung, <www.wzb.eu/sites/default/files/u32/somek_constituent_power_in_a_transnational_context.pdf> 3.

30 See (n 3 and n 4).

31 H Lindahl, ‘Constituent Power and Reflexive Identity: Towards an Ontology of Collective Selfhood’ in Loughlin and Walker, The Paradox of Constitutionalism (n 7) 9, 18.

32 J Locke, Second Treatise of Government, (Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, IN, 1980) section 223, 113. The same assumption reverberates, for example, in the American Declaration of Independence (1776). Echoing Locke, the signatories maintained that ‘mankind are more disposed to suffer, while evils are sufferable, than to right themselves by abolishing the forms to which they are accustomed’. It is only after ‘long train of abuses and usurpations’ and only after ‘patient sufferance’ that they have undertook the revolution. For a similar rhetorical juxtaposition of ‘patient sufferance’ and justified exhaustion in contemporary Egypt see Khaled Fahmy, ‘We did not risk our lives simply to change the players’, CNN, 3 July 2013, <http://www.cnn.com/2013/07/03/opinion/egypt-morsy-khaled-fahmy/>.

33 See (n 5) 379ff.

34 See (n 27).

35 Arato, A and Tombus, E, ‘Learning from Success, Learning from Failure: South Africa, Hungary, Turkey and Egypt’ (2013) 39 Philosophy and Social Criticism 427, 437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

36 Ibid 438.

37 de Soto, H, ‘The Free Market Secret of the Arab Revolutions’, Financial Times, 8 November 2012.Google Scholar

38 Colón-Riós, JI, Weak Constitutionalism: Democratic Legitimacy and the Question of Constituent Power (Routledge, London, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

39 Ibid 27.

40 Ibid 50.

41 Ibid 59.

42 An interesting twist in the Croatian case was the ‘Upozorenje’ [Warning] issued by the Croatian Constitutional Court who rejected the interpretation of the Croatian Sabor’s [Parliament] standing Committee on Constitution, Parliamentary Procedure and Political System which interpreted a potential ‘yes’ vote in the referendum as triggering the process of constitutional amendment, with the final decision allegedly resting in the Sabor. In contrast, the Court stated that the ‘Constitution is changed on the day the referendum was held, with an immediate legal effect.’ (6.1.) But, the support for the outcome preferred by the radical-democratic constitutionalists was in fact justified by a structural reading of the constitution where ‘every particular constitutional provision must be interpreted in accordance with the highest values of the constitutional order which are the foundation for the interpretation of the Constitution itself’. (5.1.) Thus, robust radical democracy in Croatia was justified by a robust understanding of constitutionalism (on file with the author).

43 Douzinas, C, Philosophy and Resistance in the Crisis: Greece and the Future of Europe (Polity, London, 2013) 105.Google Scholar

44 Ibid.

45 Another reason to abandon it in favour of a speaking, debating multitude is to undercut liberal qualms about mass politics. In constitutional theory, masses feature prominently in Schmitt’s vision as inarticulate constituent power capable only of sounding binary signs – yes or no – in the ‘race track’, ‘streets’ or ‘theatre’. For Douzinas, in contrast, in demos in the square, ‘the crowd became a speaking multitude’ ibid 163. As such, Douzinas simultaneously rejects the charge of demos being a mob – mobile vulgus – fickle commoners, but also wrests away the epistemic authority of the rulers, because, as he maintains, ‘for the first time, the ruled have the same knowledge and skills as their rulers’. Ibid 168.

46 Ibid 171.

47 Ibid 194.

48 Ibid 178.

49 Ibid 192.

50 Ibid 157.

51 See (n 9) 227.

52 Loughlin for example writes about constituent power in the context of a right ‘to make and re-make the institutional arrangements through which they are governed’ (emphasis mine). See (n 19) 219.

53 Scottish Executive, Choosing Scotland’s Future: A National Conversation, para 3.5 at 20 <http://www.scotland.gov.uk/Resource/Doc/194791/0052321.pdf> accessed 23 February 2014.

54 Grand Council of the Crees, ‘Sovereign Injustice: Summary of Double Standards, Inconsistencies and Discrimination by Separatists’ <http://www.gcc.ca/archive/article.php?id=137> accessed 11 February 2014.

55 Lixinski, L, ‘Constitutionalism and the Other: Multiculturalism and Indigeneity in Selected Latin American Countries’ (2010) Anuario Iberoamericano de Justicia Constitucional 235.Google Scholar

56 Landau, D, ‘Constitution Making Gone Wrong’ (2013) 64 Alabama Law Review 923, 957.Google Scholar

57 Eaton, K, ‘Conservative Autonomy Movements: Territorial Dimensions of Ideological Conflict in Bolivia and Ecuador’ (2011) 43 Comparative Politics 291, 297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

58 M Sadović, ‘Could Sarajevo Protests Herald ‘‘Bosnian Spring’’?’, IWPR <http://iwpr.net/report-news/could-sarajevo-protests-herald-bosnian-spring> accessed 23 February 2014.

59 ‘Manifest “Nova Bosna i Hercegovina”: Pročitajte zahtjeve grupe Udar I Revolt’, Index <http://www.index.hr/vijesti/clanak/manifest-nova-bosna-i-hercegovina-procitajte-zahtjeve-grupe-udar-i-revolt/726493.aspx> accessed 28 May 2014.

60 ‘‘‘Donetsk People’s Republic” leadership declares independence, seeks accession to Russia’, Kyiv Post, available at <http://www.kyivpost.com/content/ukraine/donetsk-peoples-republic-leadership-declares-independence-seeks-accession-to-russia-2-347490.html> accessed 28 May 2014.

61 Bhuta, N, ‘Antinomies of Transformative Occupation’ (2005) 16 European Journal of International Law 721, 737.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

62 See (n 41) 46.

63 Ibid 48.

64 Tierney, S, ‘Beyond the Ontological Question: Liberal Nationalism and the Task of Constitution-Building’ (2008) 14 European Law Journal 128, 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

65 Taylor, C, Modern Social Imaginaries (Duke University Press, Durham, NC, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

66 Tully, J, Public Philosophy in a New Key: Democracy and Civic Freedom (vol I) (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2008).Google Scholar

67 Dyzenhaus, D, ‘The Politics of the Question of Constituent Power’ in Loughlin, M and Walker, N (eds), Paradox of Constitutionalism (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2007) 129, 134.Google Scholar

68 Ibid.

69 Dyzenhaus, D, ‘Constitutionalism in an Old Key: Legality and Constituent Power’ (2012) 1 Global Constitutionalism, 229, 260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

70 Ibid 255.

71 Ibid.

72 C McIlwain, Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern (Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY, 1947) (emphases mine).

73 See (n 10).

74 Skordas, A, ‘Self-Determination of Peoples and Transnational Regimes: A Foundational Principle of Global Governance’ in Tsagourias, N (ed), Transnational Constitutionalism: International and European Models (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2007) 207, 215.Google Scholar

75 Oklopcic, Z, ‘Constitutional (Re)Vision: Sovereign Peoples, New Constituent Powers, and the Formation of Constitutional Orders in the Balkans’ (2012) 19 Constellations 81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

76 M Hardt and A Negri, Empire (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 2000) 134. Hardt, M and Negri, A, ‘Globalization and Democracy’ in Negri, Aet al., Reflections on Empire (Polity Press, Cambridge, 2008) 91.Google Scholar

77 Ibid 89.

78 See (n 19) 231.

79 See (n 28) 378.

80 Ibid 383.

81 Ibid.

82 An Allegory of the Revolution with a Portrait Medallion of Jean-Jacques Rousseau by Nicolas Henri Jeaurat de Bertry, painted at the end of the Reign of Terror in 1794, also features on the front page of the Penguin Classics’ edition of Rousseau’s Social Contract (trans., by M Cranston) (Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1968).

83 See (n 19) 234 (emphasis mine). For a similar, if a bit more elegiac de-subjectivizing account of pouvoir constituant as a placeholder for our increasingly unrealistic hopes of collective self-government see N Krisch, ‘Pouvoir Constituant and Pouvoir Irritant in the Postnational Order’ (28 April 2014) <http://ssrn.com/abstract=2430128>.

84 See (n 66) 17.

85 Ibid 37.

86 Ibid 19.

87 Oklopcic, Z, ‘Provincializing Constitutional Pluralism’ (2014) 5(2) Transnational Legal Theory (forthcoming).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

88 Kennedy, D, ‘Law and the Political Economy of the World’ (2013) Leiden Journal of International Law 1, 29.Google Scholar

89 Some notable exceptions include D Bonilla Maldonaldo (ed), Constitutionalism of the Global South: The Activist Tribunals of India, South Africa, and Colombia (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013); J Tully, ‘Modern Constitutional Democracy and Imperialism’ (2008) 46 Osgoode Hall Law Journal 461; U Baxi, ‘Constitutionalism as a Site of State Formative Practices’ (1999) 21 Cardozo Law Review 1183; L Catá Backer, ‘From Constitution to Constitutionalism: A Global Framework for Legitimate Power Systems’ (2008) 113 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 671.

90 See, for example, Arjomand, S, ‘Islamic Constitutionalism’(2007) 3 Annual Review of Law and Social Science 115CrossRefGoogle Scholar ; An-Na’im, A A, African Constitutionalism and the Role of Islam (University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, PA, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ginsburg, T, ‘Constitutionalism: East Asian Antecedents’ (2012) 88 Chicago-Kent Law Review 11Google Scholar; Tushnet, M, ‘Authoritarian Constitutionalism: Some Conceptual Issues’ in Ginsburg, T and Simpser, A (eds), Constitutions in Authoritarian Regimes (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2014).Google Scholar

91 This in no way implies denying the plurality, tensions and contradictions within the TWAIL movement itself. For a recent account, see Haskell, J, (2014) ‘Trailing the TWAIL: Arguments and Blind Spots in Third World Approaches to International LawCanadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence (forthcoming).CrossRefGoogle Scholar