Article contents
Freedom from community: Individual rights, group life, state authority and religious freedom under the Indian Constitution
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 03 November 2016
Abstract:
The religious freedom clauses of the Indian Constitution attempt to mediate between the competing claims of individuals, religious groups and the state, in a manner that is born out of specific historical circumstances. This article examines the controversial questions of whether, and to what extent, the Constitution grants individuals (specifically, dissenters) rights against the religious communities to which they belong. Taking as its point of departure a landmark Supreme Court judgment that struck down an anti-excommunication law, the article argues that the Indian Constitution is committed to an ‘anti-exclusion principle’: that is, group rights and group integrity are guaranteed to the extent – and only to the extent – that religious groups do not block individuals’ access to the basic public goods required to sustain a dignified life. Moreover – and unlike most other Constitutions – an individual may vindicate this right directly against her community in a court of law, by invoking the Constitution. This remedy is justified both philosophically, and in the specific context of Indian history. In this manner, Indian constitutionalism offers a novel and innovative solution to the perennial problem of balancing individual rights to religious freedom against the claims of community.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016
Footnotes
BCL, MPhil (Oxon); LLM (Yale Law School). The ideas in this article were first discussed in seminar courses at the National Law School of India University, Bangalore, and the West Bengal National University of Juridical Sciences, Kolkata. I am grateful to Shreya Atrey and Krishnaprasad KV, my perennial first readers, for their painstaking engagement with this article. I am also grateful to Suhrith Parthasarathy, Kalyani Ramnath, Abhinav Sekhri, Malavika Prasad and Rupali Samuel for their comments and suggestions.
References
1 PTI, ‘Now women seek entry into Haji Ali Dargah’, The Indian Express, 28 January 2016Google Scholar.
2 Express News Service, ‘Supreme Court to examine ban on women’s entry on Sabrimala’, Indian Express, 13 February 2016Google Scholar.
3 Sardar Syedna Tahir Saifuddin v State of Bombay, 1962 SCR Supl. (2) 496.
4 Ibid, para 61 (concurring opinion of Ayyangar J).
5 Ibid, para 19 (dissenting opinion of Sinha CJ).
6 Ibid, para 23 (dissenting opinion of Sinha CJ).
7 Part III, Constitution of India.
8 See e.g. Dhavan, R and Nariman, FS, ‘The Supreme Court and Group Life’ in Kirpal, BN et al. (eds), Supreme But Not Infallible: Essays in Honour of the Supreme Court of India (OUP, New Delhi, 2000) 256–87Google Scholar; Rao, BP, ‘Matters of Religion’ (1963) 5 Journal of the Indian Law Institute 509Google Scholar; Galanter, M, ‘Hinduism, Secularism, and the Indian Judiciary’ (1971) 21(4) Philosophy East and West 467Google Scholar.
9 Art 25(1) Constitution of India.
10 See e.g. First Amendment, Constitution of the United States of America; Section 15, Constitution of South Africa.
11 Art 25(2)(a) Constitution of India.
12 Art 25(2)(b) Constitution of India.
13 A point made by BP Rao in ‘Matters of Religion’ (n 8); Smith, DE, ‘India as a Secular State’ in Bhargava, R (ed), Secularism and Its Critics (OUP, New Delhi, 1998) 177Google Scholar.
14 Art 26(b) Constitution of India.
15 Art 26(d) Constitution of India.
16 Rudolph, L and Rudolph, S, In Pursuit of Lakshmi: The Political Economy of the Indian State (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1987) 33.Google Scholar
17 Galanter, M, ‘The Religious Aspects of Caste: A Legal View’ in Smith, D (ed), South Asian Politics and Religion (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1966) 289.Google Scholar
18 See (n 16).
19 Kymlicka, W, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (OUP, Oxford, 1996) ch 3Google Scholar.
20 See e.g. Hosanna-Tabor Evangelical Lutheran Church and School v EEOC, 565 US ____ (2012) (US Supreme Court).
21 For a summary of the opposing views, see Bhargava, R, ‘Introducing Multiculturalism’ in Bhargava, R et al. (eds), Multiculturalism, Liberalism, and Democracy (OUP, New Delhi, 2007) 1.Google Scholar
22 See (n 3) para 33.
23 See e.g. Parthasarathy, S, ‘The Flawed Reasoning in the Santhara Ban’, The Hindu, 24 August 2015Google Scholar.
24 Wisconsin v Yoder, 406 U.S. 275 (1972) (US Supreme Court).
25 Multani v Commissioner, [2006] 1 SCR 256 (Supreme Court of Canada).
26 Leyla Sahin v Turkey, [2007] 44 EHRR 5 (Grand Chamber) (European Court of Human Rights).
27 But see MEC for Education v Pillay (2008) 2 BCLR 99 (CC) (South African Constitutional Court); R(E) v Governing Body of JFS [2009] UKSC 15 (United Kingdom Supreme Court). Note, however, that the JFS case was decided under the UK Race Relations Act, which specifically prohibited discrimination and exclusion in certain aspects of the private sphere. The argument in this article deals with how the Indian Constitution speaks to such issues.
28 Jacobsohn, G, The Wheel of Law: India’s Secularism in Comparative Constitutional Context (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2003) 102.Google Scholar
29 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VII, 2nd December 1948 (speech of Dr BR Ambedkar) at <http://164.100.47.132/LssNew/constituent/vol7p18.html> (emphasis added).
30 See ibid 29; also Madan, TN, ‘Secularism in its Place’ in Bhargava, R (ed), Secularism and Its Critics (OUP, New Delhi, 1998) 297, 302.Google Scholar
31 See Madan (n 30).
32 See Dhavan and Nariman (n 8) 260.
33 The Commissioner, Hindu Religious Endowments, Madras v Lakshmindra Swamiar, 1954 SCR 1005, para 20.
34 Ratilal Panachand Gandhi v State of Bombay, 1954 SCR 1035.
35 Ram Prasad Seth v State of UP, AIR 1957 All 411, para 12, relying upon State of Bombay v Narasu Appa Mali, AIR 1952 Bom 84.
36 Mohd Hanif Qureshi v State of Bihar, 1959 SCR 629, para 13.
37 Durgah Committee, Ajmer v Syed Hussain Ali, 1962 1 SCR 383, para 33 (emphasis added).
38 Tilkayat Shri Govindlalji v State of Rajasthan, 1964 SCR (1) 561, para 57 (emphasis added).
39 Sastri Yagnapurushadji v Muldas, 1966 SCR (3) 242.
40 Dhavan, R, ‘Religious Freedom in India’ (1987) 35(1) American Journal of Comparative Law 209, 224Google Scholar.
41 For criticism, see Rao (n 8).
42 Seshammal v State of Tamil Nadu, (1972) 2 SCC 11.
43 Commissioner of Police v Acharya Jagdishwarananda Avadhuta, (2004) 12 SCC 770. See also Ismail Faruqui v Union of India, 1994 SCC (6) 360, holding that praying at a mosque was not an essential part of Islam.
44 Cantwell v Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296 (1940).
45 United States v Ballard, 322 U.S. 78 (1944).
46 Commissioner of Police (n 43) para 62 (dissenting opinion of Lakshmanan J). See also Seervai, HM, Constitutional Law of India, Vol. 2 (4th edn, Universal, New Delhi, 1993) 1268Google Scholar.
47 Adi Saiva Sivachariyargal Nala Sanga v Govt of Tamil Nadu, (2016) 2 SCC 725.
48 See Jacobsohn (n 28) 101.
49 Groves, HE, ‘Religious Freedom’ (1962) 4 Journal of the Indian Law Institute 190Google Scholar.
50 Galanter (n 8) 482–3.
51 Dhavan and Nariman (n 8) 260.
52 For a critique of how colonial scholars themselves approached the question of Indian religion through a set of established lenses, see Sen, R, Articles of Faith: Religion, Secularism, and the Supreme Court (OUP, New Delhi 2013) 5.Google Scholar
53 See e.g. Shilubana v Nwamitva, 2008 (9) BCLR 914 (CC) (South African Constitutional Court).
54 Mohd Hanif Qureshi v State of Bihar; see (n 36).
55 Nandy, A, ‘The Politics of Secularism and the Recovery of Religious Tolerance’ in Bhargava, R (ed), Secularism and Its Critics (OUP, New Delhi, 1998) 321, 322.Google Scholar
56 See (n 52) 18; see also (n 28) 101.
57 Lynch, C, ‘A neo-Weberian approach to religion in international politics’ (2009) 1(3) International Theory 381, 400Google Scholar.
58 See ibid 401. Indeed, this broad critique exposes striking similarities between the judicial analysis of the freedom of religion, and the colonial British view of religious groups in India. The use of textual sources of dubious variety over the lived practice of the constituents, and the imposition of an external point of view that runs contrary to how the believers themselves act, were best exemplified by the notorious Aga Khan decision in 1866, dealt with extensively in Purohit, T, The Aga Khan Case (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 2012)Google Scholar.
59 Derrett, JDM, Religion, Law and the State in Indi (Faber & Faber, London, 1968)Google Scholar; see also (n 52). More broadly, systems theorists such as Gunther Teubner have argued that autonomous social systems (in this case, law and religion) ‘cannot directly influence one another but can only effect self-regulatory processes’ through ‘structural coupling’. Teubner warns that when the ‘juridification process’ oversteps these boundaries, it leads to a ‘regulatory trilemma’, characterised by mutual indifference between the spheres, or by the disintegration of either one. Teubner, G, ‘Juridification – Concepts, Aspects, Limits, Solutions’ in Juridification of Social Spheres (Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 1987) 1Google Scholar. While flagging that point, I note that a complete analysis of the effect of the Supreme Court’s ‘essential religious practices’ doctrine both upon its own jurisprudence, and upon the fate of internal reform movements within religion is beyond the scope of this article.
60 As Farah Ahmed correctly notes, in the context of Indian personal law, ‘if group autonomy means anything, it surely means that the group should decide for itself the norms by which it is governed’. Ahmed, F, ‘Remedying Personal Law Systems’, International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family (forthcoming) available at <http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2777337>>Google Scholar. Ahmed is equally cognisant of the heterodox claims within the group, and the tension securing between group autonomy and such claims.
61 Galanter (n 8) 482; see also (n 28) 98.
62 Galanter (n 8) 483.
63 See (n 28).
64 Bhargava, R, ‘What is Secularism For?’ in Secularism and Its Critics (n 13)Google Scholar.
65 A point made by both Galanter and Sen.
66 Saifuddin (n 3) para 11 (dissenting opinion of Sinha CJ).
67 Saifuddin (n 3) para 23 (dissenting opinion of Sinha CJ).
68 Ambedkar, BR, The Untouchables: Who Were They and Why They Became Untouchables, <http://www.ambedkar.org/ambcd/39A.Untouchables%20who%20were%20they_why%20they%20became%20PART%20I.htm>>Google Scholar. Seervai, for instance, denies the validity of the analogy. See (n 46) 1278.
69 Venkataramana Devaru vs State of Mysore, 1958 SCR 895.
70 Art 17, Constitution of India.
71 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VIII, 29 November 1948 (speech of Dr BR Ambedkar) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol7p15.htm>. The first official definition of ‘untouchability’, in 1931 by the British Census Commissioner, was a broad one, defining it as social segregation characterised by exclusion from public amenities. Hutton, JH, Caste in India: Its Nature, Function and Origins (3rd edn, OUP, New Delhi 1961), 194Google Scholar.
72 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VIII, 29 November 1948 (speech of Na Ahmed) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol7p15.htm>>Google Scholar.
73 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VIII, 29 November 1948 <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol7p15.htm>>Google Scholar.
74 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. III, 29 April 1947 (speech of KM Munshi) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol3p2.htm>>Google Scholar.
75 Ibid (speech of RK Choudhury).
76 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VIII, 29 November 1948 (speech of KT Shah) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol7p15.htm>>Google Scholar.
77 See Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. III, 29 April 1947 (speech of Promatha Ranjan Thakur) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol3p2.htm>>Google Scholar; Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. V, 27 August 1947 (speech of Monomohan Das), <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol5p8a.htm>>Google Scholar; Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. XI, 21 November 1949 (speech of HJ Khandekar) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/v11p7m.htm>>Google Scholar.
78 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. III, 29 April 1947 (speech of PS Deshmukh) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol3p2.htm>>Google Scholar; Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VII, 29 November 1948 (speech of Shri Shibban Lal Saksena), <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol7p15.htm>>Google Scholar.
79 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. III, 29 April 1947 (speech of SC Bannerjee) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol3p2.htm>>Google Scholar.
80 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. XI, 19 November 1949 (speech of M Ananthasayanam Ayyangar), <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol11p6.htm>>Google Scholar.
81 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. XI, 23 November 1949 (speech of BM Gupta) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/v11p9m.htm>>Google Scholar.
82 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VII, 29 November 1948 (speech of Santanu Kumar Das) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/vol7p15.htm>>Google Scholar.
83 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. XI, 22 November 1949 (speech of Ajit Prasad Jain) <http://parliamentofindia.nic.in/ls/debates/v11p8m.htm>>Google Scholar.
84 Furthermore, scholars who accept group rights in liberal political theory are circumspect about the legitimacy of imposing liberal norms upon groups who might be following illiberal practices. See e.g. Kukathas, C, ‘Are There Any Cultural Rights?’ (1992) 20(1) Political Theory 105Google Scholar; Kymlicka, W, ‘The Rights of Minority Cultures: Reply to Kukathas’ (1992) 20(1) Political Theory 140Google Scholar.
85 Tushnet, M, ‘The issue of state action/horizontal effect in comparative constitutional law’ (2003) 1(1) International Journal of Constitutional Law 79Google Scholar.
86 Bhatia, G, ‘Comprehensive Transformative Amendments – Theory and Practice: Rethinking the Nineteenth Amendment and the Place of Women’s Rights in the Constitution’ (2015) 13 Dartmouth Law Journal 1Google Scholar.
87 Rawls, J, Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press, New York, NY, 1993).Google Scholar
88 Art 23, Constitution of India. In PUDR v Union of India, AIR 1982 SC 1473, the Supreme Court interpreted the term ‘forced labour’ to include non-payment of minimum wage, which workers were compelled – or ‘forced’ – to accept because of adverse market conditions.
89 Art 15(2), Constitution of India.
90 IMA v Union of India, C.A. No. 8170 of 2009.
91 See Rao, A, The Caste Question (University of California Press, Berkeley, CA, 2009).Google Scholar For a detailed analysis of art 15(2) of the Indian Constitution, see Bhatia, G, ‘Horizontal Discrimination and Article 15(2) of the Indian Constitution: A Transformative Approach’ (2016) 11(1) Asian Journal of Comparative Law 87Google Scholar.
92 See Rao (n 91) 165; see also Ambedkar, BR, What Congress and Gandhi Have Done to the Untouchables <http://www.ambedkar.org/ambcd/41D.What%20Congress%20and%20Gandhi%20CHAPTER%20III.htm>>Google Scholar.
93 Rao (n 91) chs 1–2.
94 The link between secularism and equality has been suggested by Cossman and Kapur. Cossman, B and Kapur, R, ‘Secularism: Bench-Marked by the Hindu Right’ (1996) 31(38) Economic and Political Weekly 2613Google Scholar.
95 See Wood, G, The Creation of the American Republic, 1776–1787 (University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill, NC, 1998);Google Scholar Benhabib, S, Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (Routledge, New York, NY, 1992).Google Scholar
96 This argument is developed in greater detail in Bhatia, ‘Horizontal Discrimination’ (n 91).
97 Rao (n 91) 81.
98 Ibid 81–5.
99 Ibid.
100 For an overlapping (but different) account, see Collins, H, ‘Discrimination, Equality and Social Inclusion’ (2003) 66 Modern Law Review 16Google Scholar.
101 Khaitan, T, A Theory of Discrimination Law (OUP, Oxford, 2015).Google Scholar
102 For a version of this argument, see Gutmann, A, Identity in Democracy (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2003) ch 2Google Scholar.
103 Chatterjee, P, ‘Secularism and Tolerance’ in Secularism and Its Critics (n 13) 344, 375Google Scholar.
104 Ibid.
105 Bilgrami, A, ‘Secularism, Nationalism and Modernity’ in Secularism and Its Critics (n 13) 380, 405Google Scholar.
106 Bhargava, ‘What is Secularism For?’ (n 13).
107 See e.g. Hosanna Tabor (n 20).
108 See (n 102) 98.
109 It might be argued that for internal dissidents, the religious context is always a ‘thick’ one. This is undoubtedly true, to a certain extent, as far as the basic good of cultural membership goes. However, ‘thick’ religious groups, in the sense that we are discussing here, have the ability to deny to their constituents more than just the good of cultural membership; they have the ability to block their access to other basic goods, including material and economic ones. I am grateful to an anonymous peer reviewer for pushing me towards greater clarity on this issue.
110 Kukathas argues, for instance, that groups can subordinate their members as long as there is an option to exit into the broader market economy. See Kukathas, ‘Are There Any Cultural Rights?’ (n 86). See also Hofer v Hofer, [1970] S.C.R. 958 (dissenting opinion of Pigeon J) (Supreme Court of Canada). However, as Farrah Ahmed points out (with the specific example of India), the right to exit is often illusory. Ahmed, F, ‘Personal Autonomy and the Option of Religious Law’ (2010) 24(2) International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 222Google Scholar.
111 Note, however, that this argument doesn’t depend upon an a priori definition of the term ‘public’, as has been the route taken by the American Supreme Court, and some judges of the Canadian Supreme Court. Boy Scouts of America v Dale, 530 U.S. 640 (2000) (Supreme Court of the United States); Roberts v United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609 (1984) (Supreme Court of the United States); Gould v Yukon Order of Pioneers, [1996] 1 SCR 571 (concurring opinion of La Forest J; dissenting opinion of L’Hereux-Dube J).
112 Rao (n 91) 89.
113 See Gutmann (n 102) 97 (emphasis added); see also (n 100) 23. See also Gould v Yukon Order of Pioneers, ibid (dissenting opinion of MacLachlin J) (Supreme Court of Canada). For an examination of religious group membership itself being an important good, see Ahmed, F, Religious Freedom under the Personal Law System (OUP, Oxford, 2015) 60Google Scholar.
114 See (n 102) 103. The public expression of second-class citizenship is the basis of some decisions of United States Supreme Court on the Establishment Clause, although that is limited to expression by the state. See Lynch v Donelly, 465 U.S. 668 (1984) (Concurring opinion of O’Connor J) (Supreme Court of the United States).
115 Woolman, S, ‘Seek Justice Elsewhere: An Egalitarian Pluralist’s Reply to David Bilchitz on the Distinction between Differentiation and Domination’ (2012) 28 South African Journal on Human Rights 273, 285Google Scholar.
116 Walzer, M, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (Basic Books, New York, NY, 1983) 19.Google Scholar
117 Rao (n 91) 77.
118 Ibid 82. Rao cites the example of how the right to access temples and water tanks ended up becoming part of the same campaign, because of the spatial proximity of the two.
119 In response to a possible objection to the use of ‘Western’ philosophers such as Gutmann and Walzer in the context of an argument about the Indian Constitution (which, I have been arguing, had its own distinct normative origin), I should clarify that Gutmann and Walzer simply help us to understand more clearly the transformative purpose of the Indian Constitution: that is, to transform a political and social reality in which individuals’ access to basic goods is often mediated (and sometimes blocked) by their religious group affiliations. I am grateful to an anonymous peer reviewer for pushing me towards greater clarity on this issue.
120 See e.g. Kukathas (n 86); Margalit, A and Halbertal, M, ‘Liberalism and the Right to Culture’ (1994) 61(3) Social Research 491Google Scholar; Santa Clara Pueblo v Martinez, 436 U.S. 49 (1978) (Supreme Court of the United States).
121 However, as Farah Ahmed argues, groups that do not achieve ‘minimal representativeness and deliberative quality’ end up constraining the individual autonomy of their members; and the thicker the group, the more harmful those constraints will be; Ahmed (n 113) 85–91.
122 Section 31, Constitution of South Africa.
123 Art 27, International Covenant for Civil and Political Rights.
124 See Christian Education South Africa v Minister of Education, (2000) (10) BCLR 1051 (Constitutional Court of South Africa).
125 See e.g. Taylor, C, ‘The Politics of Recognition’ in Gutmann, A (ed), Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1994)Google Scholar; for instances of how religious groups can facilitate personal autonomy, see Ahmed (n 113) 62, 82.
126 See (n 21) 38.
127 Bilchitz, D, ‘Should Religious Associations be Allowed to Discriminate’ (2011) 27 South African Journal on Human Rights 219Google Scholar; Bilchitz, D, ‘Why Courts Should Not Sanction Unfair Discrimination in the Private Sphere: A Reply’ (2012) 28 South African Journal on Human Rights 296Google Scholar.
128 Chatterjee, P, ‘Colonialism, Nationalism, and Colonized Women: The Contest in India’ (1989) 16(4) American Ethnologist 622Google Scholar.
129 See (n 28) 80.
130 Section 295A, Indian Penal Code. See also Sections 153A and 153B, Indian Penal Code.
131 Hasanali v Mansoorali, (1948) 50 BomLR 389, relied upon in Saifuddin. As discussed above though, the colonial approach to determining the composition and character of religious groups was entirely external in nature. Purohit, The Aga Khan Case (n 58).
132 Sarkar, T, ‘Something like rights? Faith, law and widow immolation debates in colonial Bengal’ (2012) 49(3) The Indian Economic and Social History Review 295Google Scholar.
133 Sarkar, T, ‘A Prehistory of Rights: The Age of Consent Debate in Colonial Bengal’ (2000) 26(3) Feminist Studies 601Google Scholar.
134 Chatterjee (n 128) 622.
135 Sinha, M, Specters of Mother India: The Global Restructuring of an Empire (Duke University Press, Durham, NC, 2006).Google Scholar
136 In fact, the 1928 government report specifically stated that the social boycott was particularly ‘dangerous’, since it invoked the principles of freedom of contract as justification – and notwithstanding that, deserved to be outlawed. Ambedkar, What Congress and Gandhi Have Done to the Untouchables (n 94).
137 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VII, 4th November 1948 (speech of Dr BR Ambedkar), available at <http://164.100.47.132/LssNew/constituent/vol7p1.html>; see also F Ahmed, Religious Freedom under the Personal Law System (n 112) 37;+see+also+F+Ahmed,+Religious+Freedom+under+the+Personal+Law+System+(n+112)+37>Google Scholar.
138 Parliament of India, Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. VII, 2nd December, 1948 (speech of Dr BR Ambedkar)Google Scholar.
139 See (n 102) 77–8.
- 3
- Cited by