Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T00:20:12.342Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Territoriality, Democracy, and Borders: A Retrospective on the “Refugee Crisis”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The so-called refugee crisis has triggered a broad and divisive political discussion about overrun national borders, crumbling state sovereignty, and the disintegration of democratic governance resulting from an alleged disregard for the law by the German Federal Government. Many critics have advanced arguments that are nothing more than hot-tempered polemics based on blunt legal or theoretical misconceptions. Nonetheless, it is obvious that external boundaries played—and will continue to play—a pivotal role in managing the inflow of migrants into the European Union, which is surrounded by areas of political instability, authoritarianism, poverty, civil war, and religious extremism. This Article addresses the function of territorial borders for a liberal democracy from the perspective of constitutional theory. It demonstrates that effectively controlled outer boundaries are an adequate democratic answer to an instable, fragmented, and fragile world, while avoiding the pitfalls of defining political and social membership by substantive and inescapable criteria, such as ethnicity.

Type
Special issue - Constitutional Dimensions of the Refugee Crisis
Copyright
Copyright © 2016 by German Law Journal, Inc. 

References

1 Taylor, Peter J., The State as Container: Territoriality in the Modern World-System, 18 Progress in Hum. Geography 151 (1994).Google Scholar

2 See Klaus Ferdinand Gärditz, Säkularität und Verfassung, in Verfassungstheorie § 5, pp. 3–4 (Otto Depenheuer & Christoph Grabenwarter eds., 2010).Google Scholar

3 See for the originally imperialist roots of legal extraterritoriality Turan Kayaoglu, Legal Imperialism: Sovereignty And Extraterritoriality In Japan, The Ottoman Empire, and China (2014); Chen Li, Chinese Law in Imperial Eyes: Sovereignty, Justice, and Transcultural Politics 29–68 (2015); Teemu Ruskola, Legal Orientalism (2013). Another concept of aggressive hyper-territorialisation is the wider sphere of influence (Großraumtheorie) presented by Carl Schmitt, Völkerrechtliche Großraumordnungmit Intervention für raumfremde Mächte (3d ed. 1941). In fact, this is a concept aimed at overcoming of territorial jurisdictions and establishing a hierarchy of powers.Google Scholar

4 Klaus Ferdinand Gärditz, Die Ordnungsfunktion der Staatsgrenze: Demokratizität, Liberalität und Territorialität im Kontext, in Der Staat in der Flüchtlingskrise. Zwischen gutem Willen und geltendem Recht 105, 107–08 (Otto Depenheuer & Christoph Grabenwarter eds., 2016).Google Scholar

5 Acquisition of nationality by ius sanguinis is—despite common contention—not an expression of ethnicity but of parental continuity. The German Federal Constitutional Court convincingly argued that the attribution of nationality by birth is necessary to protect the unity of the family, which is protected by Article 6 (1) Grundgesetz, and would be seriously hampered if parents and children did not share at least one nationality. See Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] 1 BvL 22/71, 21/72, May 5, 2974, 1 BvL 22/71, 21/72, in 37 BVerfGE 217, 247; Peter Michael Huber & Kirsten Butzke, Das neue Staatsangehörigkeitsrecht und sein verfassungsrechtliches Fundament, 52 Neue Juristische Wochenschrift 2769, 2771 (1999); Burkhardt Ziemske Die deutsche Staatsangehörigkeit nach dem Grundgesetz 289 (1995) Anyone can hand down one's own nationality to her/his descendants irrespective of origin, culture, religion or ethnicity. E. g., if a Pakistani citizen is naturalized in Germany this week and gives birth to a child next week, under the current ius sanguinis (Sec. 4 German Citizenship Act) model the child would be German without any difference in right and status. It is a different discussion whether the dichotomy of social and economic inclusion and democratic-political exclusion should be overcome by disconnecting citizenship from nationality or encouraging naturalization. See Ruth Rubio-Marin, Immigration as a Democratic Challenge 99–129 (2000).Google Scholar

6 Klaus Ferdinand Gärditz, Der Bürgerstatus im Licht von Migration und europäischer Integration, in: Repräsentative Demokratie in der Krise?, in 72 Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung Deutscher Staatsrechtslehrer 49, 6089 (2013).Google Scholar

7 Of course, there have always been attempts to abuse the concept of territoriality to redraw territorial boundaries by tracing ethnic settlement structures to exclude members of purportedly ‘alien’ ethnicity, and, thus, implicitly defining borders on racist concepts. Cf. Rosen, Deborah A., Border Law - The Fist Seminole War and American Nationhood 158–84 (2015). The bloody history of the secession wars on former Yugoslavian soil are the latest example of ethnic re-territorialisation. For the intricate blending of Montesquieu's theory of the particularity of legal culture and racist concepts of supremacy, see Kroncke, Jedidiah Joseph, The Futility of Law and Development: China and the Dangers of Exporting American Law 40–41 (2016). For the discriminating territoriality within the British Empire, see Gosewinkel, Dieter, Schutz und Freiheit? Staatsbürgerschaft in Europa im 20. und 21. Jahrhundert 83–97, 637 (2016). In contrast, modern models of “territorial pluralism” try to federalize conflicts in territorially concentrated communities. Cf. John McGarry, Brendan O'Leary & Richard Simeon, Integration or Accommodation? The Enduring Debate in Conflict Regulation, in Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation? 41, 63–67 (2008, Sujit Choudhry, ed.).Google Scholar

8 Paolo Novak, Back to Borders, in Critical Sociology (forthcoming 2016).Google Scholar

9 Of course, oversized states need additional mechanisms to enable democratic ruling and prevent drifting off into tyranny. Federalism can be a solution, if the right sentiment is met. Yet, external boundaries remain a prerequisite of any internal order.Google Scholar

10 Compare Alexander Somek, The Cosmopolitan Constitution 215 (2014). He argues that cosmopolitan complexity furthers tendencies to strengthen the executive branch, which can use superior knowledge and stave off the public by pointing to the inherent complexity of the subject matter.Google Scholar

11 David Miller, On Nationality 179–80 (1995).Google Scholar

12 In particular Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] July 30, 2009, 2 BvE 2, 5/08, 2 BvR 1010, 1022, 1259/08, 182/09, in 123 BVerfGE 267, 343–47, 350, 353–55, 381 (“Lissabon”).Google Scholar

13 Ayelet Shachar, The Birthright Lottery: Citizenship and Global Inequality 46 (2009).Google Scholar

14 See, e.g., Burger, Hannelore, Passwesen und Staatsbürgerschaft, in Grenze und Staat 1, 91 (Waltraud Heindl & Edith Saurer eds., 2000).Google Scholar

15 See, e.g.,. Nehal Bhuta, The Frontiers of Extraterritoriality - Human Rights Law as Global Law, in The Frontiers of Human Rights 1, 2–9 (Nehal Bhuta ed., 2016).Google Scholar

16 Lena Laube, Postsouveräne Räume: Makroterritorien und die Exterritorialisierung der europäischen Grenzpolitik, in Postsouveräne Territorialität – Die Europäische Union und ihr Raum 169, 171–81 (Ulrike Jureit & Nikola Tietze eds., 2015); Steffen Mau, Heike Brabandt, Lena Laube & Christof Roos, Liberal States and the Freedom of Movement: Selective Borders, Unequal Mobility 88–120 (2012).Google Scholar

17 Ulrike Jureit & Nikola Tietze, Postsouveräne Territorialität, in Postsouveräne Territorialität – Die Europäische Union und ihr Raum 7–24 (Ulrike Jureit & Nikola Tietze eds. 2015) (providing with further references).Google Scholar

18 H. Patrick Glenn, The Cosmopolitan State 8485 (2013).Google Scholar

19 Lucidly developed by Anuscheh Farahat, Progressive Inklusion 141 et seq. (2014). See also the proposals by Hiroshi Motomura, Americans in Waiting: The Lost Story of Immigration and Citizenship in the United States 189–200 (2007).Google Scholar

20 Giorgio Agamben, Means Without End: Notes on Politics 21 (2000).Google Scholar

21 And where the model was and is imitated, the consequences are often disturbing.Google Scholar

22 Attempts to imitate 19th century European nationalism in Asia follow different paths and ideologies, in particular, in culturally, ethnically, and linguistically diversified countries like India and China.Google Scholar

23 Uwe Volkmann, Grund und Grenzen der Toleranz, in 39 Der Staat 25, 352 (2000).Google Scholar

24 It is still too early to say whether the disturbing revival of cloudy nationalism and the political pressure of right wing populism in many European countries—in particular, as a reaction to the growing numbers of refugees — poses a countermovement that has enough impetus to influence democratic practices and legislation.Google Scholar

25 See Choudhry, Sujit, Bridging Comparative Politics and Comparative Constitutional Law: Constitutional Design in Divided Societies, in Constitutional Design for Divided Societies: Integration or Accommodation? 3, 30–31 (Sujit Choudhry ed., 2008); See Miller, supra note 11, p. 81–195.Google Scholar

26 Gosewinkel, supra note 7, at 636–38. The traditional correlation of protection and authority is clearly expressed in Article 1 A (2) of the Refugee Convention, which defines a refugee, inter alia, as a person that “is outside the country of his nationality and is unable or, owing to such fear, is unwilling to avail himself of the protection of that country.” G.A. Res. 429(V) Convention Relating to the status of Refugees (Dec. 14, 1951).Google Scholar

27 See Agamben, supra note 20, at 22.Google Scholar

28 These categorical legal—not necessarily moral—differences are often blurred in public discourse when all foreigners are labelled “refugee.” Critical remarks by Christian Hillgruber, Flüchtlingsschutz oder Arbeitsmigration — Über die Notwendigkeit und die Konsequenzen einer Unterscheidung, in Der Staat in der Flüchtlingskrise. Zwischen gutem Willen und geltendem Recht 185–94 (Otto Depenheuer & Christoph Grabenwarter eds., 2016).Google Scholar

29 Mau et al., supra note 16, at 5.Google Scholar

30 See, e.g., Landtag Nordrhein-Westfalen, Official Journal (Drucksache) 16/12588; BMI-Fact Sheet zur Durchsetzung der Ausreisepflicht (Abschiebung), https://www.bmi.bund.de/SharedDocs/Kurzmeldungen/DE/2016/07/factsheet-abschiebungen.html (11.11.2016); Eckart Lohse, Ablehnen ist einfacher als abschieben, http://www.faz.net/aktuell/politik/fluechtlingskrise/fluechtlingskrise-ablehnen-ist-einfacher-als-abschieben-13909297.html (11.11.2016).Google Scholar

31 Sec. 60(7), Sec. 60a Residence Act [Aufenthaltsgesetz].Google Scholar

32 Shachar, supra note 13, at 137.Google Scholar

33 Ulrich Becker & Jens Kersten, Demokratie als optimistische Staatsform, in 35 Neue Zeitschrift für Verwaltungsrecht 580, 584 (2016); Otto Depenheuer, Zwischen staatlicher Souveränität und Menschenrecht. Grundfragen staatlicher Einwanderungpolitik, in Festschrift für Georg Brunner 46, 57, 59 (2001); Gärditz, supra note 6, at 121–22; Thomas Groß, Postnationale Demokratie—Gibt es ein Menschenrecht auf transnationale Selbstbestimmung?, in 2 Rechtswissenschaft 125, 139–42 (2011).Google Scholar

34 See, e.g., Gosewinkel, supra note 7, at 631; David Miller, Immigrants, Nations, and Citizenship, in 16 J. Pol. Phil. 371–90 (2008).Google Scholar

35 Phrase used by Shachar, supra note 13, at 134.Google Scholar

36 See, e.g., Shachar, Ayelet, Citizenship, in The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Constitutional Law 1002, 1018 (Michael Rosenfeld & András Sajó eds., 2012).Google Scholar

37 Shachar, supra note, at 46.Google Scholar

38 See, e.g., Volkmann, Uwe, Der Flüchtling vor den Toren der Gemeinschaft, in 49 Kritische Justiz 180, 190 (2016).Google Scholar

39 This is the focus of the critique by Sofia Näsström, The Legitimacy of the People, 35 Political Theory 624, 647–50 (2007).Google Scholar

40 For an excellent overview of the European discussion, see Volkmann, supra note 36, at 183–90.Google Scholar

41 David Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice 226228 (2007).Google Scholar

42 Id. at 229.Google Scholar

43 Such effects can occur when immigration meets strong resistance and nourishes an anti-egalitarian and antidemocratic sentiment (internal de-democratization) or when the immigrants import antidemocratic sentiments from their societies. Both effect, which apparently occur, are not easily attributable: The refugee is neither responsible for xenophobic response nor for political misconceptions of numerous fellow-refugees. Nonetheless, a political order can take these effects seriously and try to restrict asylum or immigration rights to avoid political tensions a democratic society is probably unable to bear.Google Scholar

44 Shachar, supra note 13, at 137.Google Scholar

45 Becker & Kersten, supra note 33, at 582.Google Scholar

46 Joseph h. Carens, The Ethics of Immigration 283 (2013).Google Scholar

47 Volkmann, supra note 36, at 182. See also Ruhs, Martin, The Price of Rights: Regulating International Labor Migration 187200 (2015). He demonstrates that states that bestow migrants with strong and effective rights tend to restrict entry, while those countries that prefer relatively open borders, in particular, for cheap workers tend to be reluctant to grant social entitlements. Even if exploitation of workers shall not be a political option for a liberal democracy, the conflict of interests is fairly illustrated. And even immigration countries can follow disparate strategies how to reconcile border control and immigrant rights. Regarding Canada, see Anderson, Christopher G., Canadian Liberalism and the Politics of Border Control (2013).Google Scholar

48 Naive denial by Carens, supra note 46, at 276.Google Scholar

49 Volkmann, supra note 36, at 188.Google Scholar

50 Id. at 188.Google Scholar

51 Dana Schmalz, Rezension, 49 Kritische Justiz 260, 262 (2016); Volkmann, supra note 36, at 191–92.Google Scholar

52 Notwithstanding a popular misconception, moral constraints conceptually cannot threaten legal sovereignty of states. Carens, supra note 46, at 273.Google Scholar

53 Näsström, supra note 39, at 650.Google Scholar

54 For a pragmatic and optimistic concept, see Benhabib, Seyla, The Rights of Others. Aliens, Citizens and Residents (2004).Google Scholar

55 Seyla Benhabib, Democracy, Demography, and Sovereignty, 2 Law & Ethics of Human Rights 1, 4 (2008).Google Scholar

56 Critically commented by Günter Frankenberg, Flüchtlingsabwehr oder Flüchtlingsschutz?, 49 Kritische Justiz 145, 147–48 (2016).Google Scholar

57 Udo Di Fabio, Sicherheit in Freiheit, 61 Neue Juristische Wochenschrift 421 (2008); Christoph Möllers, Demokratie – Zumutungen und Versprechen 81 (2008).Google Scholar

58 Regulation No. 604/2013 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 26 June 2013 establishing the criteria and mechanisms for determining the Member State responsible for examining an application for international protection lodged in one of the Member States by a third-country national or a stateless person, 2013 O.J. (L 180) at 31.Google Scholar

59 Compare Gerrit Hellmuth Stumpf, Der Ruf nach der „Rückkehr zum Recht“ bei der Bewältigung der Flüchtlingskrise, 69 Die Öffentliche Verwaltung 357–68 (2016).Google Scholar

61 Asylverfahrensbeschleunigungsgesetz [Asylum Procedure Acceleration Act] of October 20, 2015, Bundesgesetzblatt I at 1722.Google Scholar

62 See, e.g., Möllers, supra note 57, at 68–69 (noting that democratic systems tend to be bureaucratic).Google Scholar

63 Becker & Kersten, supra note 33, at 584.Google Scholar

64 Energetically advocated by Carens, supra note 46, at 225–54. Instead, Somek, supra note 10, at 209–16, illustrates the ambivalence of open borders which socially privileges some and puts others at a disadvantage.Google Scholar

65 Shachar, supra note 13.Google Scholar

66 For the inherent value of pragmatic realism in refugee affairs, see Snyder, Jack, Realism, Refugees and Strategic Humanitarianism, in Refugees in International Relations (Alexander Betts & Gil Loescher eds., 2011).Google Scholar

67 In particular Carens, supra note 46, at 256–60.Google Scholar

68 Farahat, supra note 19.Google Scholar

69 Shachar, supra note 13, at 164–90.Google Scholar

70 See id. at 138. She argues that “citizenship laws, which mark the literal delineation between insider and outsider, member and nonmember, have coercive effects.” Thus, those feeling coercive authority should participate in the process of rulemaking. This idealistic position has its flaws, too. As long as democratic self-determination prevails, there is always membership and non-membership, rules practically affecting those who are not part of a body politic. Even if the border shifts from nationality-based citizenship to (permanent or more than temporary) residency, there will be borders. Her proposed ius nexi (p. 164 et seq.) also needs a body politic (with members) who allow a nexus to be established and to define what kind or degree of nexus shall be sufficient.Google Scholar

71 Gosewinkel, supra note 7, at 648–50.Google Scholar

72 See Gärditz, supra note 6, at 51–88.Google Scholar

73 Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice – A Defense of Pluralism and Equality 52, 62 (1983).Google Scholar