Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T05:17:40.007Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Sisyphus was an international lawyer. On Martti Koskenniemi's “From Apology to Utopia” and the place of law in international politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

From Apology to Utopia is a disturbing reading experience. I first came across Martti Koskenniemi's book of 1989 during research for my thesis on Hans Kelsen. In his monograph “Das Problem der Souveränität”, published immediately after the First World War, Kelsen attempted to destroy the central doctrinal pillars of the nineteenth century German international law discourse by exposing the ideological nature of its central doctrines, such as the concept of the sovereign will of the state, autolimitation and consent. 70 years later, the analytical programme of From Apology to Utopia deconstructed international law by exposing the inherent “political” nature of international legal discourse, interpreted as an argumentative practice. Exposing the unstable discursive boundaries between politics and international law is the central objective of this monograph. Martti Koskenniemi portrays international legal doctrine as an inherently contradictory and repetitive argumentative routine that is incapable of producing meaningful “legal” results. International lawyers somewhat tragically feel compelled to engage in this Sisyphean routine in order to maintain their professional identity.

Type
Articles: Special Issue
Copyright
Copyright © 2006 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 Kelsen, Hans, Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts (2nd ed. 1928); on the Vienna School: Stolleis, Michael, Geschichte des Öffentlichen Rechts in Deutschland, vol. 3: Staats- und Verwaltungsrechtswissenschaft in Republik und Diktatur, 1914–1945 163–171 (1999).Google Scholar

2 Koskenniemi, Martti, From Apology to Utopia, the Structure of International Legal Argument, Reissue with a new Epilogue (2005).Google Scholar

3 See Jellinek's attempt to integrate these conflicting elements in his theory of international law: Bernstorff, Jochen von, Georg Jellinek,.Völkerrecht als modernes öffentliches Recht im fin de siècle, in Georg Jellinek. Beiträge zu Leben und Werk 183 (Stanley L. Paulson & Martin Schulte eds., 2000).Google Scholar

4 Kelsen, Hans, supra note 1, 182, 224241 and 320, on Kelsen's critique: Bernstorff, Jochen Von, Der Glaube an das Universale Recht, Zur Völkerrechtstheorie Hans Kelsens und seiner Schüler [Believing in Universal Law, The Public International Law Theory of Hans Kelsen and his Disciples] 54–61 (2001).Google Scholar

5 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 575.Google Scholar

6 Id., 13.Google Scholar

7 On Kelsen, and Neokantianism: Horst Dreier, Rechtslehre, Staatssoziologie, und Demokratietheorie bei Hans Kelsen 56 (1986); on the development of the concept of methodological dualism: Paulson, Stanley, Kelsen's Earliest Legal Theory: Critical Constructivism, in Normativity and Norms. Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes 23, 2930 (Stanley L. Paulson & Bonnie Litschewski Paulson eds., 1998).Google Scholar

8 On Koskenniemi's intentions in retrospect: Koskenniemi, supra note 2, 564.Google Scholar

9 For an early critique of From Apology to Utopia: Scobbie, Ian, Towards the Elimination of International Law: Some Radical Scepticism about Sceptical Radicalism, 61 British Yearbook of International Law 339 (1990); for an overview of critical reactions to Kelsen's theory of international law by German interwarscholars: Bernstorff, Von, supra note 4, 6468 and 95–104.Google Scholar

10 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 4.Google Scholar

11 “This is a contentious distinction (the one between practitioners and academics, JvB) - after all, academics too practise the law and it is only the context in which they do so that makes them special”, Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 617.Google Scholar

12 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 1.Google Scholar

13 On Austrian fin de siècle - liberalism represented predominantly by emancipated and highly assimilated Austrian Jews: Schorske, Carl E., Wien, Geist und Gesellschaft im Fin de Siecle (1982) 111–114; Beller, Steven, Vienna and the Jews 122–137 (1989).; on Jewish emanzipation and German public law in the nineteenth century: Stolleis, Michael, “Junges Deutschland”, jüdische Emanzipation und liberale Staatsrechtslehre in Deutschland, Sitzungsberichte der Wissenschaftlichen Gesellschaft an der Johann Wolfgang Goethe-Universität (1994).Google Scholar

14 On the role of the international lawyer: Kelsen, Hans, The Law of the United Nations. A Critical Analysis of its Fundamental Problems XIII (Second Impression, 1951). See also Fassbender, Bardo, Hans Kelsen und die Vereinten Nationen, in: Völkerrecht als Wertordnung/ Common Values in International Law. Festschrift für/ Essays in honour of Christian Tomuschat 763 (Dupuy/Fassbender/Shaw/Sommermann eds., 2006).Google Scholar

15 Koskenniemi, Martti, The Gentle Civilizer, The Rise and Fall of International Law, 1870–1960, (2001) 249; on the Civilizer, Gentle, see e.g. Brunkhorst, Hauke, Verfallsgeschichten, 2 Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 295 (2002); Bogdandy, Armin von, Pragmatismus, Imperialismus und internationales Recht, Martti Koskenniemis Konzeption der Geschichte, Krise und Zukunft der Wissenschaft vom Völkerrecht, 63 Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht 205–211 (2003).Google Scholar

16 On the quest for objectivity: Koskenniemi, supra note 2, 16.Google Scholar

17 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 58. Koskenniemi hereby draws on David Kennedy's famous article David Kennedy, Theses about International Law Discourse, 23 German Yearbook of International Law 353 (1980).Google Scholar

18 Kelsen, , supra note 1, 320; on this aspect of the pure theory: von Bernstorff, supra note 4, 9194.Google Scholar

19 Kelsen, , Reine Rechtslehre, 142 (1934).Google Scholar

20 Kelsen, , supra note 1, 155, 317.Google Scholar

21 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 503.Google Scholar

22 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 596.Google Scholar

23 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 24.Google Scholar

24 On this point: Ian Scobbie, supra note 9, 348350.Google Scholar

25 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 26.; see with an overview of different theoretical approaches to the function of international law: Ulrich Fastenrath, Lücken im Völkerrecht, Zu Rechtscharakter, Quellen, Systemzusammenhang, Methodenlehre und Funktionen des Völkerrechts 252–268 (1991).Google Scholar

26 See below on Niklas Luhmann and Jacques Derrida.Google Scholar

27 Kelsen, , supra note 19, 97.Google Scholar

28 Luhmann, Niklas, Das Recht der Gesellschaft 317 (1993); Jacques Derrida, Gesetzeskraft 49 (1991).Google Scholar

29 Kennedy, Duncan, A Critique of Adjudication (1997); on the role of the judge between commitment to rules and “cynicism”: Martti Koskenniemi, Between Commitment and Cynicism: Outline for a Theory of International Law as Practice, in Collection of Essays by Legal Advisers of States, Legal Advisers of International Organisations and Practitioners in the Field of International law 495, 512 (1999).Google Scholar

30 Luhmann, , supra note 28, 317; Derrida, supra note 28, 49.Google Scholar

31 See On Lauterpacht: Koskenniemi, Martti, Lauterpacht, The Victorian Tradition in International Law, 2 European Journal of International Law 215 (1997); on Kelsen's campaign for a system of compulsory jurisdiction: Bernstorff, Von, supra note 4, 169.Google Scholar

32 See below.Google Scholar

33 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 601.Google Scholar

34 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 555.Google Scholar

35 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 548.Google Scholar

36 Kunz, Joseph L., The Swing of the Pendulum, From Overestimation to Underestimation of International Law, in: The Changing Law of Nations. Essays on Int. Law 125, 126127 (Id. ed., 1968) [article first published in 1950].Google Scholar

37 On the problem of “objectification” and law as ideology, see Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 537542; on interwar international legal scholarship: Bernstorff, Von, supra note 4, 5.Google Scholar

38 On the move to political discourse of critical int. lawyers: Purvis, Nigel, Critical Legal Studies in Public Int. Law, 32 Harvard International Law Journal 81, 116117 (1991).Google Scholar

39 I borrow this term from Camus, Albert, Le Mythe de Sisyphe (1942), chapt. 1.Google Scholar

40 On a theory of “situationality” of legal practice: Outi Korhonen, New International Law: Silence, Defence or Deliverance?, 7 European Journal of International Law 1 (1996).Google Scholar

41 See on the problem of nihilism and deconstruction in international law: Nigel Purvis, supra note 39, Korhonen, Outi, supra note 41Google Scholar

42 On the role of courts in the legal system: Niklas Luhmann, supra note 28, 258.Google Scholar

43 See for a differentiated reading of this change of tone: Outi Korhonen, supra note 41, 21.Google Scholar

44 Kelsen, , supra note 19, 19.Google Scholar

45 Koskenniemi, Martti, The Place of Law in Collective Security, 17 Michigan Journal of International Law 455, 468 (1996).Google Scholar

46 Id., 467.Google Scholar

47 Koskenniemi, , supra note 15, 480; see on “governance-networks” and international law: Jochen von Bernstorff, Democratic Global Internet Regulation? Governance Networks, International Law and the Shadow of Hegemony, 9 European Law Journal 511 (2003).Google Scholar

48 Koskenniemi, , supra note 15, 413; on the current debate on the divergence between US and EU-perceptions of international law: Koskenniemi, Martti, Perceptions of Justice: Walls and Bridges between Europe and the United States, 64 Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht 305 (2004); with an overview of the main issues addressed in this debate: Wolfrum, Rüdiger, American-European Dialogue: Different Perceptions of International Law - Introduction, 64 Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht 255 (2004); and United States Hegemony and the Foundations of International Law (Michael Byers & Georg Nolte eds., 2003).Google Scholar

49 Koskenniemi, Martti, Legal Universalism – Between Morality and Power in a World of States, in Law, Justice and Power - Between Reason and Will 46, 54, 60 (Sinkwan Cheng ed., 2004).Google Scholar

50 Schmitt, Carl, Der Begriff des Politischen 55 (1932, reissue 1979).Google Scholar

51 Koskenniemi, , supra note 50, 46.Google Scholar

52 Koskenniemi, , supra note 15, 500.Google Scholar

53 Kelsen, Hans, The Principle of Sovereign Equality of States as a Basis for International Organisation, 53 Yale LAW JOURNAL 207 (1944).Google Scholar

54 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 616.Google Scholar

55 Koskenniemi, , supra note 46, 455.Google Scholar

56 Koskenniemi, , supra note 15, 502.Google Scholar

57 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 614; Louis Henkin sees the reason for the survival of international law in its open structure: How Nations Behave - Law and Foreign Policy 109 (1979); on the merits of a relatively open international legal order with further references: Fastenrath, Ulrich, Lücken im Völkerrecht, Zu Rechtscharakter, Quellen, Systemzusammenhang, Methodenlehre und Funktionen des Völkerrechts 270 (1991).Google Scholar

58 Koskenniemi, , supra note 50, 60.Google Scholar

59 Id., 61.Google Scholar

60 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 545.Google Scholar

61 As Nigel Purvis has emphasized, the postulation of a “move to open political discourse” contains a normative principle on public discourse and decision-making, Nigel Purvis, supra note 39, 116117; on the utopian character of Koskenniemi's emancipatory concept of law: Fastenrath, Ulrich, Book Review - From Apology to Utopia, 31 Archiv des Völkerrechts 182, 184 (1993).Google Scholar

62 Koskenniemi, Martti, Book Review – Giovanna Borradori (Ed.), Philosophy in a Time of Terror. Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida (Chicago and London, University of Chicago Press 2003), 4 German Law Journal 1084 (2003), available at http://www.germanlawjournal.com/article.php?id=319.Google Scholar

63 Habermas, Jürgen, Der gespaltene Westen 153–178 (2004).Google Scholar

64 For Koskenniemi, , human rights can have a negative effect on political culture. Institutionalised rights can loose their progressive character and marginalize those community-values or interests that resist translation into rights language, Koskenniemi, Martti, The Effect of Rights on a Political Culture, in The EU and Human Rights, 99 (Philip Alston ed., 1999), Koskenniemi agrees with Karl Marx that human rights are a “theology of the bourgeois state whose citizens are obsessed by their weakness, and fearful of “evil” are ever ready to turn whatever powers into the hands of a bureaucratic theocracy”, Koskenniemi, Martti, What Should International Lawyers Learn from Karl Marx?, 17 Leiden Journal of International Law 229, 244 (2004); in line with his own concept of legal universalism Koskenniemi acknowledges, however, that rights can open a political culture to experiences of injustice and “provide a voice through which the pain of torture, for example can be articulated”, Koskenniemi, Martti, The Effect of Rights on a Political Culture, in The EU and Human Rights 99 (Philip Alston ed., 1999); on the concept of human rights as a medium to express experiences of injustice and fear: Günther, Klaus, The Legacies of Injustice and Fear: A European Approach to Human Rights and their Effects on Political Culture, in The EU and Human Rights, 177 (Philip Alston ed., 1999); on Koskenniemi's “negative” universalism and human rights: Brunkhorst, Hauke, Verfallsgeschichten, 2 Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 295, 311 (2002).Google Scholar

65 Koskenniemi, Martti, Book Review – Giovanna Borradori (Ed.), Philosophy in a Time of Terror. Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida (Chicago and London, University of Chicago Press 2003), 4 German Law Journal 1084 (2003).Google Scholar

66 Koskenniemi, , supra note 2, 600615.Google Scholar

67 For international human rights law: Kennedy, David, The International Human Rights Movement: Part of the Problem?, 15 HarvARD Human RIGHTS JOURNAL 101 (2002).Google Scholar

68 Koskenniemi, Martti, supra note 65, 229, 241; on the ideological dimension of the separation of science and practice from the perspective of the “Frankfurt School”: Max Horkheimer, Critical Theory. Selected Essays, 188–243 (Matthew O’ Connell et. al., transl., 1972).Google Scholar

69 Koskenniemi, , supra note 15, 247.Google Scholar

70 Formalism is being used by Kelsen as a counter-hegemonic (political) strategy. I have made this argument in my: Der Glaube an das Universale Recht. Zur Völkerrechtstheorie Hans Kelsens und seiner Schüler (2001). On formalism as a political strategy, see the new epilogue, in Koskenniemi, supra note 2, 602, 616.Google Scholar

71 For Kennedy, David, Koskenniemi might have produced “the last modern treatment of the field”: Kennedy, David, From Apology to Utopia, 31 HARVARD JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 385, 388 (1990); on this aspect: Nigel Purvis, supra note 39, 118. See also Kennedy, David, The last treatise: project and person. (Reflections on Martti Koskenniemi's From Apology to Utopia), 7 German Law Journal 981 (2006).Google Scholar