Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-8bljj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-05T23:36:09.109Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Range of Social Human Rights

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Even though poverty and poverty-related deaths are still increasing worldwide, too little has been undertaken against them. The question addressed in this article is whether citizens in the industrial countries who are better off have a duty to mitigate or stop the misery of the poor; and if so, what kind of duty is it. One could assume that social human rights offer an adequate answer to this question but their content, justification and implementation are highly contested from a legal as well as philosophical point of view. Different approaches to justifying social human rights and corresponding obligations are discussed in this contribution, and it is argued that neither focussing solely on a concept of “negative” obligations nor on a concept of “positive” obligations is sufficient. Moreover, it is pointed out that it is not convincing to deny social rights the status of human rights on the grounds that they do not correspond to negative universal duties. Instead liberal rights as well as social rights are both correlated with “waves of duties,” “negative” and “positive.”

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2001 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

(1) The Word Bank, THE WORLD DEVELOPMENT REPORT 1999/2000, 2000, 19ff. See: www.worldbank.org.wdr.Google Scholar

(2) Alston, Philip, Making Economic and Social Rights Count: a Strategy for the Future, POLITICAL QUARTERLY 2, (1997), 188.Google Scholar

(3) Künnemann, Rolf, Neuere Entwicklung beim Recht auf Nahrung, in: JAHRBUCH MENSCHENRECHTE 2000, ed. by Gabriele von Arnim/Volker Deile u.a., 290ff. See also the website of FIAN, Food First Information and Action Network: www.fian.org.Google Scholar

(4) O'Neill, Onora, Transnationale Gerechtigkeit, ed. by Stefan Gosepath/ Georg Lohmann, Philosophie der Menschenrechte, 1998, 220.Google Scholar

(5) See: Pogge, Thomas, The Bounds of Nationalism, CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY. SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME ON NATIONALISM (1997); and: How Should Human Rights be Conceived?, in: JAHRBUCH FÜR RECHT UND ETHIK, 3, ed. by Joachim Hruschka, 1995, 103120.Google Scholar

(6) Pogge, Thomas, Lebensstandards im Kontext der Gerechtigkeitslehre, ZEITSCHRIFT FÜR PHILOSOPHISCHE FORSCHUNG 51,1 (1997), 16.Google Scholar

(7) See Onora O'Neill 1998 (Fn. 4), 228; and Thomas Pogge (Fn 5); Michael Baumann/Michael Windfuhr, Politische Globalisierung versus ökonomische Archipelisierung, in: World Watch Institute Report — Zur Lage der Welt 2000, 7–35, 2000Google Scholar

(8) The lex mercatoria is an example for a juridical regulation between private actors that takes place without state intervention. See: Gunter Teubner, Globale Law Wthout a State, 1997.Google Scholar

(9) See: Gosepath, Stefan, Zur Begründung sozialer Rechte, in: Philosophie der Menschenrechte, ed.by Stefan Gosepath/Georg Lohmann, 1998:Google Scholar

(10) See also: Philosophie der Menschenrechte, hg. Stefan Gosepath/Georg Lohmann 1998, especially the contributions by Georg Lohmann, 62–96; Andreas Wldt, 124–146; Stefan Gosepath, 146–188; Robert Alexy, 244–265; Thomas Pogge, 378–401; see also: Ernst Tugendhat, Vorlesungen zur Ethik, 1993, 336ff., and, Die Kontroverse um die Menschenrechte. In: ANALYSE&KRITIK 15 (1993), 101110.Google Scholar

(11) See also: Tugendhat, Ernst, Dialog in Leticia, 1997, 70Google Scholar

(12) See: Habermas, Jürgen, Faktizität und Geltung. Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats, 1992, 112ff.Google Scholar

(13) See: Habermas, Jürgen (Fn. 12), 156, and also: Ulrich K. Preuß, Verfassungstheoretische Überlegungen zur normativen Begründung des Wohlfahrtsstaates, in: Sicherheit und Freiheit. Zur Ethik des Wohlfahrtstaates, hg. von Ch. Sachße/H.T. Engelhardt, 1990 Google Scholar

(14) See: Habermas, Jürgen (Fn. 12), 155Google Scholar

(15) Shue, Henry, Basic Rights, 1980 Google Scholar

(16) Robert Alexy, Theorie der Grundrechte, 1986, 386ff.Google Scholar

(17) See Amartya, Sen, Capability and Well-Being, in: The Quality of Life, ed. by Martha Nussbaum/ Amartya Sen, 1993; see also: Ernst Tugendhat (Fn. 10) Vorlesungen…, 360Google Scholar

(18) Tugendhat, Ernst, (Fn. 10), Die Kontroverse…, 108Google Scholar

(19) See also: Frankenberg, Günter, Why Care? — The Trouble with Social Rights, CARDOZO LAW REVIEW 17, 1996, 1386.Google Scholar

(20) Waldron, Jeremy, Liberal Rights, collected papers 1981–1991, 203ff. Cambridge.Google Scholar

(21) See: The Limburg Principles, HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY 9, (1987), 122–135; see also: The Maastricht Guidelines on Violations of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, HUMAN RIGHTS QUARTERLY 20, 1996, 691–730; and: General Comments of the Committee on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, especially: General Comment No. 3: The Nature of States Parties Obligation (art.2, para. 1 of the Covenant), in: Economic, social and cultural rights. A textbook, ed. by A. Eide/ C. Krause/ A. Rosas, 1995, 442ff.Google Scholar

(22) Goodin, Robert E., What is so special about our fellow countrymen?, ETHICS 98, 1988, 663–686 and Henry Shue, Mediating Duties, ETHICS 98, 1988.Google Scholar

(23) Koller, Peter, Der Geltungsbereich der Menschenrechte, in: Philosophie der Menschenrechte, ed. by. Stefan Gosepath/Georg Lohmann 1998. (Fn. 40), 104ff.Google Scholar

(24) See also: Tugendhat, Ernst (Fn. 10), Vorlesungen…, 350; Axel Honneth, Universalismus als moralische Falle? Bedingungen und Grenzen einer Politik der Menschenrechte, MERKUR 48, 9/10, 1994, 878.Google Scholar

(25) I am grateful to the Department of Moral and Political Philosophy (University of Prague) for the opportunity to participate in a conference on Philosophy and Social Sciences in May of 2001. Thanks are due to participants in that conference, and to the following people for helpful comments: Felmon Davis, René Gabriëls, Peter Niesen, Thomas Pogge, Anna Riek, Thomas Schramme, as well as Russell Miller and Peer Zumbansen for reviewing this contribution.Google Scholar